% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % % % % The Project Gutenberg EBook of Elementary Illustrations of the % % Differential and Integral Calculus, by Augustus De Morgan % % % % This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with % % almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or % % re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included % % with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.net % % % % % % Title: Elementary Illustrations of the Differential and Integral Calculus % % % Author: Augustus De Morgan % % % % Release Date: March 3, 2012 [EBook #39041] % % % % Language: English % % % % Character set encoding: ISO-8859-1 % % % % *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK DIFFERENTIAL, INTEGRAL CALCULUS *** % % % %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % \def\ebook{39041} %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% %% %% %% Packages and substitutions: %% %% %% %% book: Required. %% %% inputenc: Latin-1 text encoding. Required. %% %% %% %% ifthen: Logical conditionals. Required. %% %% %% %% amsmath: AMS mathematics enhancements. Required. %% %% amssymb: Additional mathematical symbols. Required. %% %% %% %% alltt: Fixed-width font environment. Required. %% %% %% %% indentfirst: Indent first paragraph of each section. Optional. %% %% yfonts: Gothic font on title page. Optional. %% %% %% %% footmisc: Start footnote numbering on each page. Required. %% %% icomma: No space after commas in math mode. Optional. %% %% %% %% multicol: Multicolumn environment for index. Required. %% %% makeidx: Indexing. Required. %% %% %% %% array: Extended array facilities. Required. %% %% %% %% graphicx: Standard interface for graphics inclusion. Required. %% %% %% %% calc: Length calculations. Required. %% %% %% %% fancyhdr: Enhanced running headers and footers. Required. %% %% %% %% geometry: Enhanced page layout package. Required. %% %% hyperref: Hypertext embellishments for pdf output. Required. %% %% %% %% %% %% Producer's Comments: %% %% %% %% OCR text for this ebook was obtained on January 6, 2012, from %% %% http://www.archive.org/details/elementaryillust00demouoft. %% %% %% %% Minor changes to the original are noted in this file in three %% %% ways: %% %% 1. \Typo{}{} for typographical corrections, showing original %% %% and replacement text side-by-side. %% %% 2. \Chg{}{} and \Add{}, for inconsistent/missing punctuation,%% %% italicization, and capitalization. %% %% 3. [** TN: Note]s for lengthier or stylistic comments. %% %% %% %% %% %% Compilation Flags: %% %% %% %% The following behavior may be controlled by boolean flags. %% %% %% %% ForPrinting (false by default): %% %% If false, compile a screen optimized file (one-sided layout, %% %% blue hyperlinks). If true, print-optimized PDF file: Larger %% %% text block, two-sided layout, black hyperlinks. %% %% %% %% %% %% PDF pages: 194 (if ForPrinting set to false) %% %% PDF page size: 4.5 x 6.5" (non-standard) %% %% %% %% Summary of log file: %% %% * Five overfull hboxes, three underfull hboxes. %% %% %% %% Compile History: %% %% %% %% February, 2012: (Andrew D. Hwang) %% %% texlive2007, GNU/Linux %% %% %% %% Command block: %% %% %% %% pdflatex x4 %% %% makeindex %% %% pdflatex x3 %% %% %% %% %% %% March 2012: pglatex. %% %% Compile this project with: %% %% pdflatex 39041-t.tex ..... FOUR times %% %% makeindex 39041-t.idx %% %% pdflatex 39041-t.tex ..... THREE times %% %% %% %% pdfTeX, Version 3.1415926-1.40.10 (TeX Live 2009/Debian) %% %% %% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \listfiles \documentclass[12pt]{book}[2005/09/16] %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% PACKAGES %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \usepackage[latin1]{inputenc}[2006/05/05] \usepackage{ifthen}[2001/05/26] %% Logical conditionals \usepackage{amsmath}[2000/07/18] %% Displayed equations \usepackage{amssymb}[2002/01/22] %% and additional symbols \usepackage{alltt}[1997/06/16] %% boilerplate, credits, license \IfFileExists{indentfirst.sty}{% \usepackage{indentfirst}[1995/11/23] }{} \IfFileExists{yfonts.sty}{% \usepackage{yfonts}[2003/01/08] }{% \providecommand{\textgoth}[1]{#1}% } \usepackage[perpage,symbol]{footmisc}[2005/03/17] \IfFileExists{icomma.sty}{% \usepackage{icomma} }{} \usepackage{multicol}[2006/05/18] \usepackage{makeidx}[2000/03/29] \usepackage{array}[2005/08/23] \usepackage{graphicx}[1999/02/16]%% For diagrams \usepackage{calc}[2005/08/06] \usepackage{fancyhdr} %% For running heads %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% %%%% Interlude: Set up PRINTING (default) or SCREEN VIEWING %%%% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % ForPrinting=true false (default) % Asymmetric margins Symmetric margins % 1 : 1.6 text block aspect ratio 3 : 4 text block aspect ratio % Black hyperlinks Blue hyperlinks % Start major marker pages recto No blank verso pages % \newboolean{ForPrinting} %% UNCOMMENT the next line for a PRINT-OPTIMIZED VERSION of the text %% %\setboolean{ForPrinting}{true} %% Initialize values to ForPrinting=false \newcommand{\Margins}{hmarginratio=1:1} % Symmetric margins \newcommand{\HLinkColor}{blue} % Hyperlink color \newcommand{\PDFPageLayout}{SinglePage} \newcommand{\TransNote}{Transcriber's Note} \newcommand{\TransNoteCommon}{% The camera-quality files for this public-domain ebook may be downloaded \textit{gratis} at \begin{center} \texttt{www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/\ebook}. \end{center} This ebook was produced using scanned images and OCR text generously provided by the University of Toronto Gerstein Library through the Internet Archive. \bigskip Punctuation in displayed equations has been regularized, and clear typographical errors have been changed. Aside from this, every effort has been made to preserve the phrasing and punctuation of the original. \bigskip } \newcommand{\TransNoteText}{% \TransNoteCommon This PDF file is optimized for screen viewing, but may be recompiled for printing. Please consult the preamble of the \LaTeX\ source file for instructions and other particulars. } %% Re-set if ForPrinting=true \ifthenelse{\boolean{ForPrinting}}{% \renewcommand{\Margins}{hmarginratio=2:3} % Asymmetric margins \renewcommand{\HLinkColor}{black} % Hyperlink color \renewcommand{\PDFPageLayout}{TwoPageRight} \renewcommand{\TransNote}{Transcriber's Note} \renewcommand{\TransNoteText}{% \TransNoteCommon This PDF file is optimized for printing, but may be recompiled for screen viewing. Please consult the preamble of the \LaTeX\ source file for instructions and other particulars. } }{% If ForPrinting=false, don't skip to recto \renewcommand{\cleardoublepage}{\clearpage} } %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% %%%% End of PRINTING/SCREEN VIEWING code; back to packages %%%% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \ifthenelse{\boolean{ForPrinting}}{% \setlength{\paperwidth}{8.5in}% \setlength{\paperheight}{11in}% % 1:1.6 \usepackage[body={5in,8in},\Margins]{geometry}[2002/07/08] }{% \setlength{\paperwidth}{4.5in}% \setlength{\paperheight}{6.5in}% \raggedbottom % 3:4 \usepackage[body={4.25in,5.6in},\Margins,includeheadfoot]{geometry}[2002/07/08] } \providecommand{\ebook}{00000} % Overridden during white-washing \usepackage[pdftex, hyperref, hyperfootnotes=false, pdftitle={The Project Gutenberg eBook \#\ebook: Elementary illustrations of the differential and integral calculus.}, pdfauthor={Augustus De Morgan}, pdfkeywords={University of Toronto, The Internet Archive, Andrew D. Hwang}, pdfstartview=Fit, % default value pdfstartpage=1, % default value pdfpagemode=UseNone, % default value bookmarks=true, % default value linktocpage=false, % default value pdfpagelayout=\PDFPageLayout, pdfdisplaydoctitle, pdfpagelabels=true, bookmarksopen=true, bookmarksopenlevel=0, colorlinks=true, linkcolor=\HLinkColor]{hyperref}[2007/02/07] %% Fixed-width environment to format PG boilerplate %% \newenvironment{PGtext}{% \begin{alltt} \fontsize{8.1}{10}\ttfamily\selectfont}% {\end{alltt}} % Errors found during digitization \newcommand{\Typo}[2]{#2} % Stylistic changes made for consistency \newcommand{\Chg}[2]{#2} %\newcommand{\Chg}[2]{#1} % Use this to revert inconsistencies in the original \newcommand{\Add}[1]{\Chg{}{#1}} %% Miscellaneous global parameters %% % No hrule in page header \renewcommand{\headrulewidth}{0pt} % Loosen spacing \setlength{\emergencystretch}{1.5em} \newcommand{\Loosen}{\spaceskip 0.375em plus 0.75em minus 0.25em} % Scratch pad for length calculations \newlength{\TmpLen} \setlength{\extrarowheight}{12pt} \renewcommand{\arraystretch}{1.2} \newcommand{\ArrayCompress}[1][0.6]{\renewcommand{\arraystretch}{#1}} %% Running heads %% \newcommand{\FlushRunningHeads}{\clearpage\fancyhf{}} \newcommand{\InitRunningHeads}{% \setlength{\headheight}{15pt} \pagestyle{fancy} \thispagestyle{empty} \ifthenelse{\boolean{ForPrinting}} {\fancyhead[RO,LE]{\thepage}} {\fancyhead[R]{\thepage}} } % Uniform style for running heads \newcommand{\RHeads}[1]{\textsc{\MakeLowercase{#1}}} \newcommand{\SetRunningHeads}[2][]{% \ifthenelse{\equal{#1}{}}{% \fancyhead[C]{\RHeads{#2}}% }{% \fancyhead[CE]{\RHeads{#1}}% \fancyhead[CO]{\RHeads{#2}}% }% } \newcommand{\BookMark}[2]{\phantomsection\pdfbookmark[#1]{#2}{#2}} %% Major document divisions %% \newcommand{\PGBoilerPlate}{% \pagenumbering{Alph} \pagestyle{empty} \BookMark{0}{PG Boilerplate.} } \newcommand{\FrontMatter}{% \cleardoublepage \frontmatter \BookMark{-1}{Front Matter.} } \newcommand{\MainMatter}{% \FlushRunningHeads \InitRunningHeads \SetRunningHeads[Elementary Illustrations of]{The Differential and Integral Calculus.} \mainmatter \BookMark{-1}{Main Matter.} } \newcommand{\BackMatter}{% \FlushRunningHeads \InitRunningHeads \backmatter \BookMark{-1}{Back Matter.} } \newcommand{\PGLicense}{% \FlushRunningHeads \pagenumbering{Roman} \InitRunningHeads \BookMark{-1}{PG License.} \SetRunningHeads{License.} } %% ToC formatting %% \AtBeginDocument{\renewcommand{\contentsname}% {\protect\thispagestyle{empty}% \vspace*{-3.5\baselineskip} \protect\Section{Contents.} \vspace*{-1.5\baselineskip}} } \newcommand{\TableofContents}{% \FlushRunningHeads \InitRunningHeads \SetRunningHeads{Contents.} \BookMark{0}{Contents.} \tableofcontents } % For internal use, to determine if we need the Sect./Page line \newcommand{\ToCAnchor}{} % \ToCLine{SecNo}{Title} \newcommand{\ToCLine}[2]{% \label{toc:#1}% \ifthenelse{\not\equal{\pageref{toc:#1}}{\ToCAnchor}}{% \renewcommand{\ToCAnchor}{\pageref{toc:#1}}% \noindent\makebox[\textwidth][r]{\scriptsize \hfill PAGE}\\ }{}% \settowidth{\TmpLen}{999}% \noindent\strut\parbox[b]{\textwidth-\TmpLen}{\small% \hangindent2em#2\dotfill}% \makebox[\TmpLen][r]{\pageref{section:#1}}% \smallskip } %% Sectional units %% % For internal use by \Tag and \Eq \newcounter{SecNo} \newcommand{\Section}[2][]{ \subsection*{\centering\large\normalfont\MakeUppercase{#2}} \refstepcounter{SecNo} \label{section:\theSecNo}% \ifthenelse{\not\equal{#1}{}}{% \addtocontents{toc}{\protect\ToCLine{\theSecNo}{#1}}% }{} } \newcommand{\SubSectHead}[1]{ \subsubsection*{\centering\footnotesize\normalfont\MakeUppercase{#1}} } \newcommand{\Subsection}[2][]{ \SubSectHead{#2} \refstepcounter{SecNo} \label{section:\theSecNo}% \ifthenelse{\equal{#1}{}}{% \addtocontents{toc}{\protect\ToCLine{\theSecNo}{#2}}% }{% \addtocontents{toc}{\protect\ToCLine{\theSecNo}{#1}}% } } \newcommand{\Signature}[2]{% \medskip \null\hfill#1\hspace{\parindent} \\ \hspace*{\parindent}#2 } %% Index formatting \makeindex \makeatletter \renewcommand{\@idxitem}{\par\hangindent 30\p@\global\let\idxbrk\nobreak} \renewcommand\subitem{\idxbrk\@idxitem \hspace*{12\p@}\let\idxbrk\relax} \renewcommand{\indexspace}{\par\penalty-3000 \vskip 10pt plus5pt minus3pt\relax} \renewenvironment{theindex}{% \setlength\columnseprule{0.5pt}\setlength\columnsep{18pt}% \FlushRunningHeads \InitRunningHeads \SetRunningHeads{Index} \BookMark{0}{Index} \begin{multicols}{2}[{\Section[Index]{Index.}\small}]% \setlength\parindent{0pt}\setlength\parskip{0pt plus 0.3pt}% \thispagestyle{empty}\let\item\@idxitem\raggedright% }{% \end{multicols}\FlushRunningHeads } \makeatother \newcommand{\EtSeq}[1]{\hyperpage{#1}~et~seq.} %% Bibliography %% \newlength{\ParIndent} \settowidth{\ParIndent}{2em} % Template for definitions, theorems, examples \newenvironment{Book}{\medskip\par\noindent\hangindent\ParIndent\ignorespaces}{\par} \newenvironment{Descrip}{% \begin{list}{}{% \setlength{\leftmargin}{1.5\ParIndent}% \setlength{\itemindent}{\ParIndent}% \setlength{\listparindent}{\ParIndent}% \setlength{\topsep}{4pt}% \item\small\ignorespaces% }% }{% \end{list}} \newcommand{\BibSect}[1]{% \subsubsection*{\centering\normalsize\normalfont\MakeUppercase{#1}} } \newcommand{\BibSubsect}[1]{% \subsubsection*{\centering\footnotesize\normalfont\MakeUppercase{#1}} } %% Diagrams %% \newcommand{\Graphic}[2]{% % \phantomsection\label{fig:#2}% \includegraphics[width=#1]{./images/fig#2.png}% } % \Figure[width]{figure number}{file} \newcommand{\DefWidth}{4.25in}% Default figure width \newcommand{\Figure}[2][]{% \begin{figure}[hbt!] \Graphic{\textwidth}{#2}% \ifthenelse{\equal{#1}{}}{% \phantomsection\label{fig:#2}% }{}% \end{figure}% } % Figure labels \newcommand{\Fig}[2][Fig.]{\hyperref[fig:#2]{#1~{\upshape #2}}} \newcommand{\Pagelabel}[1]{\phantomsection\label{page:#1}} % Page separators \newcommand{\PageSep}[1]{\Pagelabel{#1}\ignorespaces} \newcommand{\PageNo}[1]{\pageref{page:#1}} \newcommand{\PageRef}[2][page]{\hyperref[page:#2]{#1~\pageref*{page:#2}}} \newcommand{\PageRefs}[3][pages]{% \ifthenelse{\equal{\pageref*{page:#2}}{\pageref*{page:#3}}}{% \hyperref[page:#2]{page~\pageref*{page:#2}}% }{% Else #1 \hyperref[page:#2]{\pageref*{page:#2}}--\hyperref[page:#3]{\pageref*{page:#3}}% }% } % Miscellaneous textual conveniences (N.B. \emph, not \textit) \newcommand{\eg}{\emph{e.g.}} \newcommand{\ie}{\emph{i.e.}} \newcommand{\QED}{\quad\textsc{q.e.d.}} \renewcommand{\etc}{\text{etc}} \newcommand{\Ed}{\textit{Ed}} \newcommand{\ia}{\textit{a}} \newcommand{\ib}{\textit{b}} \renewcommand{\th}{\textsuperscript{th}} \renewcommand{\(}{{\upshape(}} \renewcommand{\)}{{\upshape)}} \newcommand{\First}[1]{\textsc{#1}} \newcommand{\Title}[1]{\textit{#1}} \newcommand{\Author}[1]{\textsc{#1}} \newcommand{\Translator}[1]{\textit{#1}} %% \Price macro accepts numerals, letters, ".", and " ". %% Letters are italicized, spaces made non-breaking. \makeatletter \newif\ifins@rtsp@ce \def\Price#1{{\ins@rtsp@cefalse\Pr@ce #1\null}} \def\Pr@ce#1{% \ifx#1\null\let\next\empty \else\let\next\Pr@ce \ifins@rtsp@ce~\ins@rtsp@cefalse\fi \if.#1.\ins@rtsp@cetrue \else\ifcat#1a\textit{#1}% \else{#1}% \fi\fi\fi\next} \makeatother %% Miscellaneous mathematical formatting %% \newcommand{\dd}{\partial} \DeclareMathOperator{\arc}{arc} \DeclareMathOperator{\chord}{chord} %[** TN: Original uses something like these] %\newcommand{\ux}{u'} %\newcommand{\uy}{u\raisebox{-1.25ex}{$'$}} \newcommand{\ux}{u_{x}'} \newcommand{\uy}{u_{y}'} \renewcommand{\phi}{\varphi} \newcommand{\efrac}[2]{\frac{#1}{#2}} \DeclareInputMath{176}{{}^{\circ}} \DeclareInputMath{183}{\cdot} \newcommand{\Z}{\phantom{0}} \newcommand{\DotRow}[1]{\multispan{#1}{\dotfill}} \newcommand{\Ibar}{\mathop{\vphantom{|}}}% ** Integral bar \newcommand{\THeadSize}{\scriptsize} \newcommand{\ColHead}[2][]{% \ifthenelse{\equal{#1}{}}{% \settowidth{\TmpLen}{\THeadSize #2}% }{% \settowidth{\TmpLen}{\THeadSize #1}% } \parbox[c]{\TmpLen}{\centering\THeadSize #2\medskip}% } \newcommand{\Low}[1]{% \setlength{\TmpLen}{-1.5ex} \smash[b]{\raisebox{\TmpLen}{\ensuremath{#1}}} } % \PadTo[alignment]{width text}{visible text} \newcommand{\PadTo}[3][c]{% \settowidth{\TmpLen}{$#2$}% \makebox[\TmpLen][#1]{$#3$}% } \newcommand{\PadTxt}[3][c]{% \settowidth{\TmpLen}{\text{#2}}% \makebox[\TmpLen][#1]{#3}% } % Cross-ref-able equation tags \newcommand{\Tag}[1]{% \phantomsection\label{eqn:\theSecNo.#1}\tag*{\ensuremath{#1}}% } \newcommand{\Eq}[2][\theSecNo]{% \hyperref[eqn:#1.#2]{\ensuremath{#2}}% } %% Upright capital letters in math mode \DeclareMathSymbol{A}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`A} \DeclareMathSymbol{B}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`B} \DeclareMathSymbol{C}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`C} \DeclareMathSymbol{D}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`D} \DeclareMathSymbol{E}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`E} \DeclareMathSymbol{F}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`F} \DeclareMathSymbol{G}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`G} \DeclareMathSymbol{H}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`H} \DeclareMathSymbol{I}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`I} \DeclareMathSymbol{J}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`J} \DeclareMathSymbol{K}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`K} \DeclareMathSymbol{L}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`L} \DeclareMathSymbol{M}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`M} \DeclareMathSymbol{N}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`N} \DeclareMathSymbol{O}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`O} \DeclareMathSymbol{P}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`P} \DeclareMathSymbol{Q}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`Q} \DeclareMathSymbol{R}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`R} \DeclareMathSymbol{S}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`S} \DeclareMathSymbol{T}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`T} \DeclareMathSymbol{U}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`U} \DeclareMathSymbol{V}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`V} \DeclareMathSymbol{W}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`W} \DeclareMathSymbol{X}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`X} \DeclareMathSymbol{Y}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`Y} \DeclareMathSymbol{Z}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`Z} %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% START OF DOCUMENT %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \begin{document} %% PG BOILERPLATE %% \PGBoilerPlate \begin{center} \begin{minipage}{\textwidth} \small \begin{PGtext} The Project Gutenberg EBook of Elementary Illustrations of the Differential and Integral Calculus, by Augustus De Morgan This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.net Title: Elementary Illustrations of the Differential and Integral Calculus Author: Augustus De Morgan Release Date: March 3, 2012 [EBook #39041] Language: English Character set encoding: ISO-8859-1 *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK DIFFERENTIAL, INTEGRAL CALCULUS *** \end{PGtext} \end{minipage} \end{center} \newpage %% Credits and transcriber's note %% \begin{center} \begin{minipage}{\textwidth} \begin{PGtext} Produced by Andrew D. Hwang. \end{PGtext} \end{minipage} \vfill \end{center} \begin{minipage}{0.85\textwidth} \small \BookMark{0}{Transcriber's Note.} \subsection*{\centering\normalfont\scshape% \normalsize\MakeLowercase{\TransNote}}% \raggedright \TransNoteText \end{minipage} %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% FRONT MATTER %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \PageSep{ii} \FrontMatter \Section{In the Same Series.} \Book{ON THE STUDY AND DIFFICULTIES OF MATHEMATICS.} By \Author{Augustus De~Morgan}. Entirely new edition, with portrait of the author, index, and annotations, bibliographies of modern works on algebra, the philosophy of mathematics, pan-geometry,~etc. Pp.,~288. Cloth, \$1.25 net~(\Price{5s.}). \Book{LECTURES ON ELEMENTARY MATHEMATICS.} By \Author{Joseph Louis Lagrange}. Translated from the French by \Translator{Thomas~J. McCormack}. With photogravure portrait of Lagrange, notes, biography, marginal analyses,~etc. Only separate edition in French or English, Pages,~172. Cloth, \$1.00 net~(\Price{5s.}). \Book{ELEMENTARY ILLUSTRATIONS OF THE DIFFERENTIAL AND INTEGRAL CALCULUS.} By \Author{Augustus De~Morgan}. New reprint edition. With sub-headings, and a brief bibliography of English, French, and German text-books of the Calculus. Pp.,~144. Price, \$1.00 net~(\Price{5s.}). \Book{MATHEMATICAL ESSAYS AND RECREATIONS.} By \Author{Hermann Schubert}, Professor of Mathematics in the Johanneum, Hamburg, Germany. Translated from the German by \Translator{Thomas~J. McCormack}. Containing essays on the Notion and Definition of Number, Monism in Arithmetic, On the Nature of Mathematical Knowledge, The Magic Square, The Fourth Dimension, The Squaring of the Circle. Pages,~149. Cuts,~37. Price, Cloth,~75c net~(\Price{3s. 6d.}). \Book{HISTORY OF ELEMENTARY MATHEMATICS.} By \Author{Dr.\ Karl Fink}, late Professor in Tübingen. Translated from the German by Prof.\ \Translator{Wooster Woodruff Beman} and Prof.\ \Translator{David Eugene Smith}. (Nearly Ready.) \vfill \begin{center} \small THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING CO. \\ \footnotesize 324 DEARBORN ST., CHICAGO. \end{center} \PageSep{iii} \cleardoublepage %[** Title page] \begin{center} ELEMENTARY ILLUSTRATIONS \vfil \footnotesize OF THE \vfil \textsc{\LARGE Differential and Integral \\[4pt] Calculus} \vfil\vfil\vfil \footnotesize BY \\ \normalsize AUGUSTUS DE MORGAN \vfil\vfil\vfil \textit{\small NEW EDITION} \vfil\vfil\vfil\vfil \footnotesize CHICAGO \\ THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY \\ \scriptsize FOR SALE BY \\ \footnotesize\textsc{Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner \&~Co., Ltd., London} \\ 1899 \end{center} \PageSep{iv} % [Blank page] \PageSep{v} \Section{Editor's Preface.} \First{The} publication of the present reprint of De~Morgan's \Title{Elementary Illustrations of the Differential and Integral Calculus} forms, quite independently of its interest to professional students of mathematics, an integral portion of the general educational plan which the Open Court Publishing Company has been systematically pursuing since its inception,---which is the dissemination among the public at large of sound views of science and of an adequate and correct appreciation of the methods by which truth generally is reached. Of these methods, mathematics, by its simplicity, has always formed the type and ideal, and it is nothing less than imperative that its ways of procedure, both in the discovery of new truth and in the demonstration of the necessity and universality of old truth, should be laid at the foundation of every philosophical education. The greatest achievements in the history of thought---Plato, Descartes, Kant---are associated with the recognition of this principle. But it is precisely mathematics, and the pure sciences generally, from which the general educated public and independent students have been debarred, and into which they have only rarely attained more than a very meagre insight. The reason of this is twofold. In the first place, the ascendant and consecutive character of mathematical knowledge renders its results absolutely unsusceptible of presentation to persons who are unacquainted with what has gone before, and so necessitates on the part of its devotees a thorough and patient exploration of the field from the very beginning, as distinguished from those sciences which may, so to speak, be begun at the end, and which are consequently cultivated with the greatest zeal. The second reason is that, partly through the exigencies of academic instruction, but mainly through the martinet traditions of antiquity and the influence of mediĉval \PageSep{vi} logic-mongers, the great bulk of the elementary text-books of mathematics have unconsciously assumed a very repellent form,---something similar to what is termed in the theory of protective mimicry in biology ``the terrifying form.'' And it is mainly to this formidableness and touch-me-not character of exterior, concealing withal a harmless body, that the undue neglect of typical mathematical studies is to be attributed. To this class of books the present work forms a notable exception. It was originally issued as numbers 135 and 140 of the Library of Useful Knowledge (1832), and is usually bound up with De~Morgan's large \Title{Treatise on the Differential and Integral Calculus} (1842). Its style is fluent and familiar; the treatment continuous and undogmatic. The main difficulties which encompass the early study of the Calculus are analysed and discussed in connexion with practical and historical illustrations which in point of simplicity and clearness leave little to be desired. No one who will read the book through, pencil in hand, will rise from its perusal without a clear perception of the aim and the simpler fundamental principles of the Calculus, or without finding that the profounder study of the science in the more advanced and more methodical treatises has been greatly facilitated. The book has been reprinted substantially as it stood in its original form; but the typography has been greatly improved, and in order to render the subject-matter more synoptic in form and more capable of survey, the text has been re-paragraphed and a great number of descriptive sub-headings have been introduced, a list of which will be found in the Contents of the book. An index also has been added. Persons desirous of continuing their studies in this branch of mathematics, will find at the end of the text a bibliography of the principal English, French, and German works on the subject, as well as of the main Collections of Examples. From the information there given, they may be able to select what will suit their special needs. \Signature{Thomas J. McCormack.} {\textsc{La Salle}, Ill., August, 1899.} \PageSep{vii} \TableofContents \iffalse CONTENTS: PAGE On the Ratio or Proportion of Two Magnitudes 2 On the Ratio of Magnitudes that Vanish Together.... 4 On the Ratios of Continuously Increasing or Decreasing Quantities 7 The Notion of Infinitely Small Quantities 11 On Functions 14 Infinite Series 15 Convergent and Divergent Series 17 Taylor's Theorem. Derived Functions 19 Differential Coefficients 22 The Notation of the Differential Calculus 25 Algebraical Geometry.... 29 On the Connexion of the Signs of Algebraical and the Directions of Geometrical Magnitudes 31 The Drawing of a Tangent to a Curve 36 Rational Explanation of the Language of Leibnitz.... 38 Orders of Infinity 42 A Geometrical Illustration: Limit of the Intersections of Two Coinciding Straight Lines 45 The Same Problem Solved by the Principles of Leibnitz. . 48 An Illustration from Dynamics; Velocity, Acceleration, etc.. 52 Simple Harmonic Motion 57 The Method of Fluxions 60 Accelerated Motion 60 Limiting Ratios of Magnitudes that Increase Without Limit. 65 Recapitulation of Results Reached in the Theory of Functions. 74 Approximations by the Differential Calculus 74 Solution of Equations by the Differential Calculus.... 77 Partial and Total Differentials 78 \PageSep{viii} Application of the Theorem for Total Differentials to the Determination of Total Resultant Errors 84 Rules for Differentiation 85 Illustration of the Rules for Differentiation 86 Differential Coefficients of Differential Coefficients .... 88 Calculus of Finite Differences. Successive Differentiation . 88 Total and Partial Differential Coefficients. Implicit Differentiation 94 Applications of the Theorem for Implicit Differentiation .. 101 Inverse Functions 102 Implicit Functions 106 Fluxions, and the Idea of Time 110 The Differential Coefficient Considered with Respect to Its Magnitude 112 The Integral Calculus 115 Connexion of the Integral with the Differential Calculus.. 120 Nature of Integration 122 Determination of Curvilinear Areas. The Parabola... 124 Method of Indivisibles 125 Concluding Remarks on the Study of the Calculus.... 132 Bibliography of Standard Text-books and Works of Reference on the Calculus 133 Index 143 \fi \PageSep{1} \MainMatter \Section{Differential and Integral Calculus.} \SubSectHead{Elementary Illustrations.} \First{The} Differential and Integral Calculus, or, as it was formerly called in this country [England], the Doctrine of Fluxions, has always been supposed to present remarkable obstacles to the beginner. It is matter of common observation, that any one who commences this study, even with the best elementary works, finds himself in the dark as to the real meaning of the processes which he learns, until, at a certain stage of his progress, depending upon his capacity, some accidental combination of his own ideas throws light upon the subject. The reason of this may be, that it is usual to introduce him at the same time to new principles, processes, and symbols, thus preventing his attention from being exclusively directed to one new thing at a time. It is our belief that this should be avoided; and we propose, therefore, to try the experiment, whether by undertaking the solution of some problems by common algebraical methods, without calling for the reception of more than one new symbol at once, or lessening the immediate evidence of each investigation by reference to general rules, the study of more methodical treatises may not be somewhat \PageSep{2} facilitated. We would not, nevertheless, that the student should imagine we can remove all obstacles; we must introduce notions, the consideration of which has not hitherto occupied his mind; and shall therefore consider our object as gained, if we can succeed in so placing the subject before him, that two independent difficulties shall never occupy his mind at once. \Subsection{On the Ratio or Proportion of Two Magnitudes.} The ratio or proportion of two magnitudes is best \index{Proportion|EtSeq}% \index{Ratio!defined|EtSeq}% conceived by expressing them in numbers of some unit when they are commensurable; or, when this is not the case, the same may still be done as nearly as we please by means of numbers. Thus, the ratio of the diagonal of a square to its side is that of $\sqrt{2}$ to~$1$, which is very nearly that of $14142$ to~$10000$, and is certainly between this and that of $14143$ to~$10000$. Again, any ratio, whatever numbers express it, may be the ratio of two magnitudes, each of which is as small as we please; by which we mean, that if we take any given magnitude, however small, such as the line~$A$, we may find two other lines $B$~and~$C$, each less than~$A$, whose ratio shall be whatever we please. Let the given ratio be that of the numbers $m$~and~$n$. Then, $P$~being a line, $mP$~and~$nP$ are in the proportion of $m$ to~$n$; and it is evident, that let $m$,~$n$, and~$A$ be what they may, $P$~can be so taken that $mP$~shall be less than~$A$. This is only saying that $P$~can be taken less than the $m$\th~part of~$A$, which is obvious, since~$A$, however small it may be, has its tenth, its hundredth, its thousandth part,~etc., as certainly as if it were larger. We are not, therefore, entitled to say that because two magnitudes are diminished, their ratio is \PageSep{3} diminished; it is possible that~$B$, which we will suppose to be at first a hundredth part of~$C$, may, after a diminution of both, be its tenth or thousandth, or may still remain its hundredth, as the following example will show: \begin{alignat*}{5} &C && 3600 && 1800 && 36 && 90 \\ &B && 36 && 1\tfrac{8}{10} && \tfrac{36}{100} && 9 \\ &B &{}={}& \frac{1}{100} C\qquad B &{}={}& \frac{1}{1000} C\qquad B &{}={}& \frac{1}{100} C\qquad B &{}={}& \frac{1}{10} C. \end{alignat*} Here the values of $B$~and~$C$ in the second, third, and fourth column are less than those in the first; nevertheless, the ratio of $B$ to~$C$ is less in the second column than it was in the first, remains the same in the third, and is greater in the fourth. In estimating the approach to, or departure from equality, which two magnitudes undergo in consequence of a change in their values, we must not look at their differences, but at the proportions which those differences bear to the whole magnitudes. For example, if a geometrical figure, two of whose sides are $3$~and $4$~inches now, be altered in dimensions, so that the corresponding sides are $100$~and $101$~inches, they are nearer to equality in the second case than in the first; because, though the difference is the same in both, namely one inch, it is one third of the least side in the first case, and only one hundredth in the second. This corresponds to the common usage, which rejects quantities, not merely because they are small, but because they are small in proportion to those of which they are considered as parts. Thus, twenty miles would be a material error in talking of a day's journey, but would not be considered worth mentioning in one of three months, and would be called totally \PageSep{4} insensible in stating the distance between the earth and sun. More generally, if in the two quantities $x$~and~$x + a$, an increase of~$m$ be given to~$x$, the two resulting quantities $x + m$~and $x + m + a$ are nearer to equality as to their \emph{ratio} than $x$~and~$x + a$, \index{Equality}% though they continue the same as to their \emph{difference}; for \index{Differences!arithmetical}% $\dfrac{x + a}{x} = 1 + \dfrac{a}{x}$ and $\dfrac{x + m + a}{x + m} = 1 + \dfrac{a}{x + m}$ of which $\dfrac{a}{x + m}$~is less than~$\dfrac{a}{x}$, and therefore $1 + \dfrac{a}{x + m}$ is nearer to unity than $1 + \dfrac{a}{x}$. In future, when we talk of an approach towards equality, we mean that the ratio is made more nearly equal to unity, not that the difference is more nearly equal to nothing. The second may follow from the first, but not necessarily; still less does the first follow from the second. \Subsection{On the Ratio of Magnitudes that Vanish Together.} It is conceivable that two magnitudes should decrease \index{Time, idea of}% simultaneously,\footnote {In introducing the notion of time, we consult only simplicity. It would do equally well to write any number of successive values of the two quantities, and place them in two columns.} so as to vanish or become nothing, together. For example, let a point~$A$ move on a circle towards a fixed point~$B$. The arc~$AB$ will then diminish, as also the chord~$AB$, and by bringing the point~$A$ sufficiently near to~$B$, we may obtain an arc and its chord, both of which shall be smaller than a given line, however small this last may be. But while the magnitudes diminish, we may not assume either that their ratio increases, diminishes, or remains the same, for we have shown that a diminution of two magnitudes is consistent with either of these. \PageSep{5} \index{Increase without limit|EtSeq}% We must, therefore, look to each particular case for the change, if any, which is made in the ratio by the diminution of its terms. Now two suppositions are possible in every increase or diminution of the ratio, as follows: Let $M$~and~$N$ be two quantities which we suppose in a state of decrease. The first possible case is that the ratio of $M$ to~$N$ may decrease without limit, that is, $M$~may be a smaller fraction of~$N$ after a decrease than it was before, and a still smaller after a further decrease, and so on; in such a way, that there is no fraction so small, to which $\dfrac{M}{N}$~shall not be equal or inferior, if the decrease of $M$~and~$N$ be carried sufficiently far. As an instance, form two sets of numbers as in the adjoining table: \[ \begin{array}{*{7}{c}} \PadTxt{Ratio of }{} M \PadTxt{ to~$N$}{} & 1 & \dfrac{1}{20} & \dfrac{1}{400} & \dfrac{1}{8000} & \dfrac{1}{160000} & \etc. \\ \PadTxt{Ratio of }{} N \PadTxt{ to~$N$}{} & 1 & \dfrac{1}{2} & \dfrac{1}{4} & \dfrac{1}{8} & \dfrac{1}{16} & \etc. \\ \text{Ratio of~$M$ to~$N$} & 1 & \dfrac{1}{10} & \dfrac{1}{100} & \dfrac{1}{1000} & \dfrac{1}{10000} & \etc. \end{array} \] Here both $M$~and~$N$ decrease at every step, but $M$~loses at each step a larger fraction of itself than~$N$, and their ratio continually diminishes. To show that this decrease is without limit, observe that $M$~is at first equal to~$N$, next it is one tenth, then one hundredth, then one thousandth of~$N$, and so on; by continuing the values of $M$ and~$N$ according to the same law, we should arrive at a value of~$M$ which is a smaller part of~$N$ than any which we choose to name; for example,~$.000003$. The second value of~$M$ beyond our table is only one millionth of the corresponding value of~$N$; the ratio is therefore expressed by~$.000001$ \PageSep{6} which is less than~$.000003$. In the same law of formation, the ratio of $N$ to~$M$ is also \emph{increased} without limit. The second possible case is that in which the ratio of $M$ to~$N$, though it increases or decreases, does not increase or decrease without limit, that is, continually approaches to some ratio, which it never will exactly reach, however far the diminution of $M$ and~$N$ may be carried. The following is an example: \[ \begin{array}{*{9}{c}} \PadTxt{Ratio of }{} M \PadTxt{ to~$N$}{} & 1 & \dfrac{1}{3} & \dfrac{1}{6} & \dfrac{1}{10} & \dfrac{1}{15} & \dfrac{1}{21} & \dfrac{1}{28} & \etc. \\ \PadTxt{Ratio of }{} N \PadTxt{ to~$N$}{} & 1 & \dfrac{1}{4} & \dfrac{1}{9} & \dfrac{1}{16} & \dfrac{1}{25} & \dfrac{1}{36} & \dfrac{1}{49} & \etc. \\ \text{Ratio of~$M$ to~$N$} & 1 & \dfrac{4}{3} & \dfrac{9}{6} & \dfrac{16}{10} & \dfrac{25}{15} & \dfrac{36}{21} & \dfrac{49}{28} & \etc. \end{array} \] The ratio here increases at each step, for $\dfrac{4}{3}$~is greater than~$1$, $\dfrac{9}{6}$~than~$\dfrac{4}{3}$, and so on. The difference between this case and the last is, that the ratio of $M$ to~$N$, though perpetually increasing, does not increase without limit; it is never so great as~$2$, though it may be brought as near to~$2$ as we please. To show this, observe that in the successive values of~$M$, the denominator of the second is~$1 + 2$, that of the third $1 + 2 + 3$, and so on; whence the denominator of the $x$\th~value of~$M$ is \[ 1 + 2 + 3 + \dots + x,\quad\text{or}\quad \frac{x(x + 1)}{2}\Add{.} \] Therefore the $x$\th~value of~$M$ is~$\dfrac{2}{x(x + 1)}$, and it is evident that the $x$\th~value of~$N$ is~$\dfrac{1}{x^{2}}$, which gives the $x$\th~value of the ratio $\dfrac{M}{N} = \dfrac{2x^{2}}{x(x + 1)}$, or~$\dfrac{2x}{x + 1}$, or \PageSep{7} $\dfrac{x}{x + 1} × 2$. If $x$~be made sufficiently great, $\dfrac{x}{x + 1}$~may be brought as near as we please to~$1$, since, being $1 - \dfrac{1}{x + 1}$, it differs from~$1$ by~$\dfrac{1}{x + 1}$, which may be made as small as we please. But as $\dfrac{x}{x + 1}$, however great $x$~may be, is always less than~$1$, $\dfrac{2x}{x + 1}$~is always less than~$2$. Therefore (1)~$\dfrac{M}{N}$~continually increases; (2)~may be brought as near to~$2$ as we please; (3)~can never be greater than~$2$. This is what we mean by saying that $\dfrac{M}{N}$~is an increasing ratio, the limit of which is~$2$. Similarly of~$\dfrac{N}{M}$, which is the reciprocal of~$\dfrac{M}{N}$, we may show (1)~that it continually decreases; (2)~that it can be brought as near as we please to~$\frac{1}{2}$; (3)~that it can never be less than~$\frac{1}{2}$. This we express by saying that $\dfrac{N}{M}$~is a decreasing ratio, whose limit is~$\frac{1}{2}$. \Subsection{On the Ratios of Continuously Increasing or Decreasing Quantities.} To the fractions here introduced, there are intermediate \index{Continuous quantities|EtSeq}% \index{Quantities, continuous|EtSeq}% fractions, which we have not considered. Thus, in the last instance, $M$~passed from $1$ to~$\frac{1}{2}$ without any intermediate change. In geometry and mechanics, it is necessary to consider quantities as increasing or decreasing \emph{continuously}; that is, a magnitude does not pass from one value to another without passing through every intermediate value. Thus if one point move towards another on a circle, both the arc and its chord decrease continuously. Let $AB$ \index{Arc and its chord, a continuously decreasing|EtSeq}% (\Fig{1}) be an arc of a circle, the centre of which is~$O$. \PageSep{8} Let $A$ remain fixed, but let $B$, and with it the radius~$OB$, move towards~$A$, the point~$B$ always remaining on the circle. At every position of~$B$, suppose the following figure. Draw $AT$ touching the circle at~$A$, produce $OB$ to meet~$AT$ in~$T$, draw $BM$~and~$BN$ perpendicular and parallel to~$OA$, and join~$BA$. Bisect the arc~$AB$ in~$C$, and draw~$OC$ meeting the chord in~$D$ and bisecting it. The right-angled triangles $ODA$ and $BMA$ having a common angle, and also right angles, are similar, as are also $BOM$ and~$TBN$. If now we suppose $B$ to move towards~$A$, before $B$ \Figure{1} reaches~$A$, we shall have the following results: The arc and chord~$BA$, the lines $BM$,~$MA$, $BT$,~$TN$, the angles $BOA$,~$COA$,~$MBA$, and~$TBN$, will diminish without limit; that is, assign a line and an angle, however small, $B$~can be placed so near to~$A$ that the lines and angles above alluded to shall be severally less than the assigned line and angle. Again, $OT$~diminishes and $OM$~increases, but neither without limit, for the first is never less, nor the second greater, than the radius. The angles $OBM$,~$MAB$, and~$BTN$, increase, but not without limit, each being always less than the right angle, but capable of being made as \PageSep{9} near to it as we please, by bringing~$B$ sufficiently near to~$A$. So much for the magnitudes which compose the figure: we proceed to consider their ratios, premising that the arc~$AB$ is greater than the chord~$AB$, and less than $BN + NA$. The triangle~$BMA$ being always similar to~$ODA$, their sides change always in the same proportion; and the sides of the first decrease without limit, which is the case with only one side of the second. And since $OA$~and~$OD$ differ by~$DC$, which diminishes without limit as compared with~$OA$, the ratio $OD ÷ OA$ is an increasing ratio whose limit is~$1$. But $OD ÷ OA = BM ÷ BA$. We can therefore bring~$B$ so near to~$A$ that $BM$~and~$BA$ shall differ by as small a fraction of either of them as we please. To illustrate this result from the trigonometrical tables, observe that if the radius~$OA$ be the linear unit, and $\angle BOA = \theta$, $BM$~and~$BA$ are respectively $\sin\theta$ and $2\sin\frac{1}{2}\theta$. Let $\theta = 1°$; then $\sin\theta = .0174524$ and $2\sin\frac{1}{2}\theta = .0174530$; whence $2\sin\frac{1}{2}\theta ÷ \sin\theta = 1.00003$ very nearly, so that $BM$~differs from~$BA$ by less than four of its own hundred-thousandth parts. If $\angle BOA = 4'$, the same ratio is~$1.0000002$, differing from unity by less than the hundredth part of the difference in the last example. Again, since $DA$~diminishes continually and without limit, which is not the case either with $OD$ or~$OA$, the ratios $OD ÷ DA$ and $OA ÷ DA$ increase without limit. These are respectively equal to $BM ÷ MA$ and $BA ÷ MA$; whence it appears that, let a number be ever so great, $B$~can be brought so near to~$A$, that $BM$ and $BA$ shall each contain~$MA$ more times than there are units in that number. Thus if $\angle BOA = 1°$, $BM ÷ MA = 114.589$ and $BA ÷ MA = 114.593$ very \PageSep{10} nearly; that is, $BM$ and $BA$ both contain~$MA$ more than $114$~times. If $\angle BOA = 4'$, $BM ÷ MA = 1718.8732$, and $BA ÷ MA = 1718.8375$ very nearly; or $BM$ and $BA$ both contain~$MA$ more than $1718$~times. No difficulty can arise in conceiving this result, if the student recollect that the degree of greatness or smallness of two magnitudes determines nothing as to their ratio; since every quantity~$N$, however small, can be divided into as many parts as we please, and has therefore another small quantity which is its millionth \Figure[nolabel]{1} or hundred-millionth part, as certainly as if it had been greater. There is another instance in the line~$TN$, which, since $TBN$~is similar to~$BOM$, decreases continually with respect to~$TB$, in the same manner as does $BM$ with respect to~$OB$. The arc~$BA$ always lies between $BA$ and $BN + NA$, or $BM + MA$; hence $\dfrac{\arc BA}{\chord BA}$ lies between $1$ and $\dfrac{BM}{BA} + \dfrac{MA}{BA}$. But $\dfrac{BM}{BA}$~has been shown to approach continually towards~$1$, and $\dfrac{MA}{BA}$~to decrease without limit; hence $\dfrac{\arc BA}{\chord BA}$ continually approaches towards~$1$. \PageSep{11} If $\angle BOA = 1°$, $\dfrac{\arc BA}{\chord BA} = .0174533 ÷ .0174530 = 1.00002$, very nearly. If $\angle BOA = 4'$, it is less than $1.0000001$. We now proceed to illustrate the various phrases which have been used in enunciating these and similar propositions. \Subsection{The Notion of Infinitely Small Quantities.} It appears that it is possible for two quantities $m$ and $m + n$ to decrease together in such a way, that $n$~continually decreases with respect to~$m$, that is, becomes a less and less part of~$m$, so that $\dfrac{n}{m}$~also decreases when $n$~and~$m$ decrease. Leibnitz,\footnote {Leibnitz was a native of Leipsic, and died in 1716, aged~70. His dispute \index{Leibnitz}% with Newton, or rather with the English mathematicians in general, about \index{Newton}% the invention of Fluxions, and the virulence with which it was carried on, \index{Fluxions}% are well known. The decision of modern times appears to be that both Newton and Leibnitz were independent inventors of this method. It has, perhaps, not been sufficiently remarked how nearly several of their predecessors approached the same ground; and it is a question worthy of discussion, whether either Newton or Leibnitz might not have found broader hints in writings accessible to both, than the latter was ever asserted to have received from the former.} in introducing the Differential Calculus, presumed that in such a case, $n$~might be taken so small as to be utterly inconsiderable when compared with~$m$, so that $m + n$ might be put for~$m$, or \textit{vice versa}, without any error at all. In this case he used the phrase that $n$~is \emph{infinitely} small with respect to~$m$. The following example will illustrate this term. Since $(a + h)^{2} = a^{2} + 2ah + h^{2}$, it appears that if $a$~be increased by~$h$, $a^{2}$~is increased by~$2ah + h^{2}$. But if $h$~be taken very small, $h^{2}$~is very small with respect to~$h$, for since $1:h :: h:h^{2}$, as many times as $1$~contains~$h$, so many times does $h$~contain~$h^{2}$; so that by taking \PageSep{12} $h$~sufficiently small, $h$~may be made to be as many times~$h^{2}$ as we please. Hence, in the words of Leibnitz, if $h$~be taken \emph{infinitely} small, $h^{2}$~is \emph{infinitely} small \index{Infinitely small, the notion of}% with respect to~$h$, and therefore $2ah + h^{2}$ is the same as~$2ah$; or if $a$~be increased by an infinitely small quantity~$h$, $a^{2}$~is increased by another infinitely small quantity~$2ah$, which is to~$h$ in the proportion of $2a$ to~$1$. In this reasoning there is evidently an absolute error; for it is impossible that $h$~can be so small, that $2ah + h^{2}$ and $2ah$ shall be the same. The word \emph{small} itself has no precise meaning; though the word \emph{smaller}, \index{Small, has no precise meaning}% or \emph{less}, as applied in comparing one of two magnitudes with another, is perfectly intelligible. Nothing is either small or great in itself, these terms only implying a relation to some other magnitude of the same kind, and even then varying their meaning with the subject in talking of which the magnitude occurs, so that both terms may be applied to the same magnitude: thus a large field is a very small part of the earth. Even in such cases there is no natural point at which smallness or greatness commences. The thousandth part of an inch may be called a small distance, a mile moderate, and a thousand leagues great, but no one can fix, even for himself, the precise mean between any of these two, at which the one quality ceases and the other begins. These terms are not therefore a fit subject for mathematical discussion, until some more precise sense can be given to them, which shall prevent the danger of carrying away with the words, some of the confusion attending their use in ordinary language. It has been usual to say that when $h$~decreases from any given value towards nothing, $h^{2}$~will become \emph{small} as compared with~$h$, because, \PageSep{13} let a number be ever so great, $h$~will, before it becomes nothing, contain $h^{2}$~more than that number of times. Here all dispute about a standard of smallness is avoided, because, be the standard whatever it may, the proportion of~$h^{2}$ to~$h$ may be brought under it. It is indifferent whether the thousandth, ten-thousandth, or hundred-millionth part of a quantity is to be considered small enough to be rejected by the side of the whole, for let $h$~be $\dfrac{1}{1000}$, $\dfrac{1}{10,000}$, or $\dfrac{1}{100,000,000}$ of the unit, and $h$~will contain~$h^{2}$, $1000$, $10,000$, or $100,000,000$ of times. The proposition, therefore, that $h$~can be taken so small that $2ah + h^{2}$ and~$2ah$ are rigorously equal, though not true, and therefore entailing error upon all its subsequent consequences, yet is of this character, that, by taking $h$ sufficiently small, all errors may be made as small as we please. The desire of combining simplicity with the appearance of rigorous demonstration, probably introduced the notion of infinitely small quantities; which was further established by observing that their careful use never led to any error. The method of stating the above-mentioned proposition in strict and rational terms is as follows: If $a$~be increased by~$h$, $a^{2}$~is increased by $2ah + h^{2}$, which, whatever may be the value of~$h$, is to~$h$ in the proportion of $2a + h$ to~$1$. The smaller $h$~is made, the more near does this proportion diminish towards that of $2a$ to~$1$, to which it may be made to approach within any quantity, if it be allowable to take $h$ as small as we please. Hence the ratio, $\emph{increment of } a^{2} ÷ \emph{increment of } a$, is a decreasing ratio, whose limit is~$2a$. In further illustration of the language of Leibnitz, \index{Leibnitz}% we observe, that according to his phraseology, if $AB$~be \PageSep{14} an \emph{infinitely} small arc, the chord and arc~$AB$ are equal, or the circle is a polygon of an \emph{infinite} number of \emph{infinitely} small rectilinear sides. This should be considered as an abbreviation of the proposition proved (\PageRef{10}), and of the following: If a polygon be inscribed in a circle, the greater the number of its sides, and the smaller their lengths, the more nearly will the perimeters of the polygon and circle be equal to one another; and further, if any straight line be given, however small, the difference between the perimeters of the polygon and circle may be made less than that line, by sufficient increase of the number of sides and diminution of their lengths. Again, it would be said (\Fig{1}) that if $AB$~be infinitely small, $MA$~is infinitely less than~$BM$. What we have proved is, that $MA$ may be made as small a part of~$BM$ as we please, by sufficiently diminishing the arc~$BA$. \Subsection{On Functions.} An algebraical expression which contains~$x$ in any \index{Functions!definition of|EtSeq}% way, is called a \emph{function} of~$x$. Such are $x^{2} + a^{2}$, $\dfrac{a + x}{a - x}$, $\log(x + y)$, $\sin 2x$. An expression may be a function of more quantities than one, but it is usual only to name those quantities of which it is necessary to consider a change in the value. Thus if in $x^{2} + a^{2}$ $x$~only is considered as changing its value, this is called a function of~$x$; if $x$~and~$a$ both change, it is called a function of $x$~and~$a$. Quantities which change their values during a process, are called \emph{variables}, and \index{Variables!independent and dependent}% those which remain the same, \emph{constants}; and variables \index{Constants}% which we change at pleasure are called \emph{independent}, while those whose changes necessarily follow from \PageSep{15} \index{Variables!independent and dependent}% the changes of others are called \emph{dependent}. Thus in \Fig{1}, the length of the radius~$OB$ is a constant, the arc~$AB$ is the independent variable, while $BM$,~$MA$, the chord~$AB$,~etc., are dependent. And, as in algebra we reason on numbers by means of general symbols, each of which may afterwards be particularised as standing for any number we please, unless specially prevented by the conditions of the problem, so, in treating of functions, we use general symbols, which may, under the restrictions of the problem, stand for any function whatever. The symbols used are the letters $F$,~$f$, $\Phi$,~$\phi$,~$\psi$; $\phi(x)$~and~$\psi(x)$, or $\phi x$~and~$\psi x$, may represent any functions of~$x$, just as $x$~may represent any number. Here it must be borne in mind that $\phi$~and~$\psi$ do not represent numbers which multiply~$x$, but are \emph{the abbreviated directions to perform certain operations with $x$ and constant quantities}. Thus, if $\phi x = x + x^{2}$, $\phi$~is equivalent to a direction to add~$x$ to its square, and the whole~$\phi x$ stands for the result of this operation. Thus, in this case, $\phi(1) = 2$; $\phi(2) = 6$; $\phi a = a + a^{2}$; $\phi(x + h) = x + h + (x + h)^{2}$; $\phi \sin x = \sin x + (\sin x)^{2}$. It may be easily conceived that this notion is useless, unless there are propositions which are generally true of all functions, and which may be made the foundation of general reasoning. \Subsection{Infinite Series.} To exercise the student in this notation, we proceed \index{Series|EtSeq}% \index{Taylor's Theorem|EtSeq}% to explain one of these functions which is of most extensive application and is known by the name of \emph{Taylor's Theorem}. If in~$\phi x$, any function of~$x$, the value of~$x$ be increased by~$h$, or $x + h$~be substituted instead of~$x$, the result is denoted by~$\phi(x + h)$. It \PageSep{16} will generally\footnote {This word is used in making assertions which are for the most part \index{Generally@\emph{Generally}, the word}% true, but admit of exceptions, few in number when compared with the other cases. Thus it generally happens that $x^{2} - 10x + 40$ is greater than~$15$, with the exception only of the case where $x = 5$. It is generally true that a line which meets a circle in a given point meets it again, with the exception only of the tangent.} happen that this is either greater or less than~$\phi x$, and $h$~is called the \emph{increment} of~$x$, and \index{Increment}% $\phi(x + h) - \phi x$ is called the \emph{increment} of~$\phi x$, which is negative when $\phi(x + h) < \phi x$. It may be proved that $\phi(x + h)$ can generally be expanded in a series of the form \[ \phi x + ph + qh^{2} + rh^{3} + \etc.,\quad \textit{ad infinitum}, \] which contains none but whole and positive powers of~$h$. It will happen, however, in many functions, that one or more values can be given to~$x$ for which it is impossible to expand $f(x + h)$ without introducing negative or fractional powers. These cases are considered by themselves, and the values of~$x$ which produce them are called \emph{singular} values. \index{Singular values}% As the notion of a series which has no end of its terms, may be new to the student, we will now proceed to show that there may be series so constructed, that the addition of any number of their terms, however great, will always give a result less than some determinate quantity. Take the series \[ 1 + x + x^{2} + x^{3} + x^{4} + \etc., \] in which $x$~is supposed to be less than unity. The first two terms of this series may be obtained by dividing $1 - x^{2}$ by $1 - x$; the first three by dividing $1 - x^{3}$ by $1 - x$; and the first $n$~terms by dividing $1 - x^{n}$ by $1 - x$. If $x$~be less than unity, its successive powers decrease without limit;\footnote {This may be proved by means of the proposition established in \Title{Study of Mathematics} (Chicago: The Open Court Publishing~Co., Reprint Edition), page~247. For $\dfrac{m}{n} × \dfrac{n}{m}$ is formed (if $m$~be less than~$n$) by dividing $\dfrac{m}{n}$ into $n$~parts, and taking away $n - m$ of them.} that is, there is \PageSep{17} no quantity so small, that a power of~$x$ cannot be found which shall be smaller. Hence by taking $n$~sufficiently great, $\dfrac{1 - x^{n}}{1 - x}$ or $\dfrac{1}{1 - x} - \dfrac{x^{n}}{1 - x}$ may be brought as near to~$\dfrac{1}{1 - x}$ as we please, than which, however, it must always be less, since $\dfrac{x^{n}}{1 - x}$ can never entirely vanish, whatever value $n$~may have, and therefore there is always something subtracted from $\dfrac{1}{1 - x}$. It follows, nevertheless, that $1 + x + x^{2} + \etc.$, if we are at liberty to take as many terms as we please, can be brought as near as we please to~$\dfrac{1}{1 - x}$, and in this sense we say that \[ \frac{1}{1 - x} = 1 + x + x^{2} + x^{3} + \etc.,\quad\textit{ad infinitum}. \] \Subsection{Convergent and Divergent Series.} A series is said to be \emph{convergent} when the sum of its terms tends towards some limit; that is, when, by taking any number of terms, however great, we shall never exceed some certain quantity. On the other hand, a series is said to be \emph{divergent} when the sum of a number of terms may be made to surpass any quantity, however great. Thus of the two series, \[ 1 + \frac{1}{2} + \frac{1}{4} + \frac{1}{8} + \etc. \] and \[ 1 + 2 + 4 + 8 + \etc.\Add{,} \] the first is convergent, by what has been shown, and the second is evidently divergent. A series cannot be convergent, unless its separate terms decrease, so as, \PageSep{18} at last, to become less than any given quantity. And the terms of a series may at first increase and afterwards decrease, being apparently divergent for a finite number of terms, and convergent afterwards. It will only be necessary to consider the latter part of the series. Let the following series consist of terms decreasing without limit: \[ a + b + c + d + \dots + k + l + m + \dots, \] which may be put under the form \[ %[** TN: Small parentheses in the original here and below, as noted] a\left(1 + \frac{b}{a} + \frac{c}{b}\, \frac{b}{a} + \frac{d}{c}\, \frac{c}{b}\, \frac{b}{a} + \etc.\right); \] the same change of form may be made, beginning from any term of the series, thus: \[ %[** TN: Small ()] k + l + m + \etc. = k\left(1 + \frac{l}{k} + \frac{m}{l}\, \frac{l}{k} + \etc.\right). \] We have introduced the new terms, $\dfrac{b}{a}$,~$\dfrac{c}{b}$,~etc., or the ratios which the several terms of the original series bear to those immediately preceding. It may be shown (1)~that if the terms of the series $\dfrac{b}{a}$,~$\dfrac{c}{b}$,~$\dfrac{d}{c}$, etc., come at last to be less than unity, and afterwards either continue to approximate to a limit which is less than unity, or decrease without limit, the series $a + b + c + \etc.$, is convergent; (2)~if the limit of the terms $\dfrac{b}{a}$,~$\dfrac{c}{b}$,~etc., is either greater than unity, or if they increase without limit, the series is divergent. (1\ia). Let $\dfrac{l}{k}$~be the first which is less than unity, and let the succeeding ratios $\dfrac{m}{l}$,~etc., decrease, either with or without limit, so that $\dfrac{l}{k} > \dfrac{m}{l} > \dfrac{n}{m}$, etc.; whence it follows, that of the two series, \PageSep{19} \begin{align*} %[** TN: Small ()] k\biggl(1 &+ \frac{l}{k} + \frac{l}{k}\, \PadTo{\dfrac{m}{l}}{\dfrac{l}{k}} + \frac{l}{k}\, \PadTo{\dfrac{m}{l}}{\dfrac{l}{k}}\, \PadTo{\dfrac{n}{m}}{\dfrac{l}{k}} + \etc.\biggr), \\ k\biggl(1 &+ \frac{l}{k} + \frac{l}{k}\, \frac{m}{l} + \frac{l}{k}\, \frac{m}{l}\, \frac{n}{m} + \etc.\biggr), \end{align*} the first is greater than the second. But since $\dfrac{l}{k}$~is less than unity, the first can never surpass $k × \dfrac{1}{1 - \dfrac{l}{k}}$, or~$\dfrac{k^{2}}{k - l}$, and is convergent; the second is therefore convergent. But the second is no other than $k + l + m + \etc.$; therefore the series $a + b + c + \etc.$, is convergent from the term~$k$. \Chg{(1\ib.)}{(1\ib).} Let $\dfrac{l}{k}$~be less than unity, and let the successive ratios $\dfrac{l}{k}$,~$\dfrac{m}{l}$,~etc., increase, never surpassing a limit~$A$, which is less than unity. Hence of the two series, \begin{align*} %[** TN: Small ()] k(1 &+ \PadTo{\dfrac{l}{k}}{A} + \PadTo{\dfrac{l}{k}}{A}\,\PadTo{\dfrac{m}{l}}{A} + \PadTo{\dfrac{l}{k}}{A}\,\PadTo{\dfrac{m}{l}}{A}\,\PadTo{\dfrac{n}{m}}{A} + \etc.), \\ k\biggl(1 &+ \frac{l}{k} + \frac{l}{k}\, \frac{m}{l} + \frac{l}{k}\, \frac{m}{l}\, \frac{n}{m} + \etc.\biggr), \end{align*} the first is the greater. But since $A$~is less than unity, the first is convergent; whence, as before, $a + b + c + \etc.$, converges from the term~$k$. (2) The second theorem on the divergence of series we leave to the student's consideration, as it is not immediately connected with our object. \Subsection{Taylor's Theorem. Derived Functions.} We now proceed to the series \index{Derivatives}% \index{Derived Functions|EtSeq}% \index{Functions!derived|EtSeq}% \index{Taylor's Theorem|EtSeq}% \[ ph + qh^{2} + rh^{3} + sh^{4} + \etc., \] in which we are at liberty to suppose $h$ as small as we please. The successive ratios of the terms to those \PageSep{20} immediately preceding are $\dfrac{qh^{2}}{ph}$ or~$\dfrac{q}{p}h$, $\dfrac{rh^{3}}{qh^{2}}$ or~$\dfrac{r}{q}h$, $\dfrac{sh^{4}}{rh^{3}}$ or $\dfrac{s}{r}h$,~etc. If, then, the terms $\dfrac{q}{p}$,~$\dfrac{r}{q}$,~$\dfrac{s}{r}$, etc., are always less than a finite limit~$A$, or become so after a definite number of terms, $\dfrac{q}{p}h$,~$\dfrac{r}{q}h$,~etc., will always be, or will at length become, less than~$Ah$. And since $h$~may be what we please, it may be so chosen that $Ah$~shall be less than unity, for which $h$~must be less than~$\dfrac{1}{A}$. In this case, by theorem~(1\ib), the series is convergent; it follows, therefore, that a value of~$h$ can always be found so small that $ph + qh^{2} + rh^{3} + \etc.$, shall be convergent, at least unless the coefficients $p$,~$q$,~$r$,~etc., be such that the ratio of any one to the preceding increases without limit, as we take more distant terms of the series. This never happens in the developments which we shall be required to consider in the Differential Calculus. We now return to $\phi(x +h)$, which we have asserted (\PageRef{16}) can be expanded (with the exception of some particular values of~$x$) in a series of the form $\phi x + ph + qh^{2} + \etc$. The following are some instances of this development derived from the Differential Calculus, most of which are also to be found in treatises on algebra: \index{Logarithms}% {\scriptsize \begin{alignat*}{4} (x + h)^{n} &= x^{n} &+ nx^{n-1}h &&+ n(n - 1)x^{n-2} \frac{h^{2}}{2} &&+ n(n - 1)(n - 2)x^{n-3} \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} &\ \etc.\Add{,} \\ % a^{x + h} &= a^{x} &+ ka^{x} h\rlap{\normalsize\footnotemark[1]} &&+ k^{2} a^{x} \frac{h^{2}}{2} &&+ k^{3} a^{x} \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} &\ \etc.\Add{,} \\ % \log(x + h) &= \log x &+ \frac{1}{x}\, h &&- \frac{1}{x^{2}}\, \frac{h^{2}}{2} &&+ \frac{2}{x^{3}}\, \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} &\ \etc.\Add{,} \\ % \sin(x + h) &= \sin x &+ \cos x\, h &&- \sin x\, \frac{h^{2}}{2}\rlap{\normalsize\footnotemark[2]} &&- \cos x\, \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} &\ \etc.\Add{,} \\ % %[** TN: Moved up from top of page21] \cos(x + h) &= \cos x &- \sin x\, h &&- \cos x\, \frac{h^{2}}{2} &&+ \sin x\, \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} &\ \etc. \end{alignat*}}% \footnotetext[1]{Here $k$~is the Naperian or hyperbolic logarithm of~$a$; that is, the common logarithm of~$a$ divided by~$.434294482$.}% \footnotetext[2]{In the last two series the terms are positive and negative in pairs.} \PageSep{21} It appears, then, that the development of~$\phi(x + h)$ consists of certain functions of~$x$, the first of which is $\phi x$~itself, and the remainder of which are multiplied by $h$,~$\dfrac{h^{2}}{2}$, $\dfrac{h^{3}}{2·3}$, $\dfrac{h^{4}}{2·3·4}$, and so on. It is usual to denote the coefficients of these divided powers of~$h$ by $\phi' x$, $\phi'' x$, $\phi''' x$,\footnote {Called \emph{derived functions} or \emph{derivatives}.---\Ed.} \index{Derivatives}% \index{Derived Functions}% \index{Functions!derived}% etc., where $\phi'$,~$\phi''$,~etc., are merely functional symbols, as is $\phi$~itself; but it must be recollected that $\phi' x$,~$\phi'' x$,~etc., are rarely, if ever, employed to signify anything except the coefficients of~$h$, $\dfrac{h^{2}}{2}$,~etc., in the development of~$\phi(x + h)$. Hence this development is usually expressed as follows: \[ \phi(x + h) = \phi x + \phi' x\, h + \phi''x\, \frac{h^{2}}{2} + \phi''' x\, \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} + \etc. \] {\Loosen Thus, when $\phi x = x^{n}$, $\phi' x = nx^{n-1}$, $\phi'' x = n(n - 1)x^{n-2}$, etc.; when $\phi x = \sin x$, $\phi' x = \cos x$, $\phi'' x = -\sin x$,~etc. In the first case $\phi'(x + h) = n(x + h)^{n-1}$, $\phi''(x + h) = n(n - 1)(x + h)^{n-2}$; and in the second $\phi'(x + h) = \cos (x + h)$, $\phi''(x + h) = -\sin(x + h)$.} The following relation exists between $\phi x$,~$\phi' x$, $\phi'' x$,~etc. In the same manner as $\phi' x$~is the coefficient of~$h$ in the development of~$\phi(x + h)$, so $\phi'' x$~is the coefficient of~$h$ in the development of~$\phi'(x + h)$, and $\phi''' x$~is the coefficient of~$h$ in the development of~$\phi''(x + h)$; $\phi^{\text{iv}} x$~is the coefficient of~$h$ in the development of $\phi'''(x + h)$, and so on. The proof of this is equivalent to \emph{Taylor's Theorem} already alluded to (\PageRef{15}); and the fact may be verified in the examples already given. When $\phi x = a^{x}$, $\phi' x = ka^{x}$, and $\phi'(x + h) = ka^{x+h} = k(a^{x} + ka^{x}\, h + \etc.)$. The coefficient of~$h$ is here~$k^{2} a^{x}$, which is the \PageSep{22} same as~$\phi'' x$. (See the second example of the preceding table.) Again, $\phi''(x + h) = k^{2}a^{x+h} = k^{2}(a^{x} + ka^{x}\, h + \etc.)$, in which the coefficient of~$h$ is~$k^{3}a^{x}$, the same as~$\phi''' x$. Again, if $\phi x = \log x$, $\phi' x = \dfrac{1}{x}$, and $\phi'(x + h) = \dfrac{1}{x + h} = \dfrac{1}{x} - \dfrac{h}{x^{2}} + \etc.$, as appears by common division. Here the coefficient of~$h$ is~$-\dfrac{1}{x^{2}}$, which is the same as $\phi'' x$~in the third example. Also $\phi''(x + h) = -\dfrac{1}{(x + h)^{2}} = -(x + h)^{-2}$, which by the Binomial Theorem is $-(x^{-2} - 2x^{-3}\, h + \etc.)$. The coefficient of~$h$ is~$2x^{-3}$ or~$\dfrac{2}{x^{3}}$, which is~$\phi''' x$ in the same example. \Subsection{Differential Coefficients.} It appears, then, that if we are able to obtain the \index{Coefficients, differential|EtSeq}% \index{Differential coefficients|EtSeq}% coefficient of~$h$ in the development of \emph{any} function whatever of~$x + h$, we can obtain all the other coefficients, since we can thus deduce $\phi' x$ from~$\phi x$, $\phi'' x$ from~$\phi' x$, and so on. It is usual to call~$\phi' x$ the first differential coefficient of~$\phi x$, $\phi'' x$~the second differential coefficient of~$\phi x$, or the first differential coefficient of~$\phi' x$; $\phi''' x$~the third differential coefficient of~$\phi x$, or the second of~$\phi' x$, or the first of~$\phi'' x$; and so on.\footnote {The first, second, third, etc., differential coefficients, as thus obtained, are also called the first, second, third, etc., \emph{derivatives}.---\Ed.} \index{Derivatives}% The name is derived from a method of obtaining~$\phi' x$, etc., which we now proceed to explain. Let there be any function of~$x$, which we call~$\phi x$, in which $x$~is increased by an increment~$h$; the function then becomes \[ \phi x + \phi' x\, h + \phi'' x\, \frac{h^{2}}{2} + \phi''' x\, \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} + \etc. \] \PageSep{23} The original value~$\phi x$ is increased by the increment \[ \phi' x\, h + \phi'' x\, \frac{h^{2}}{2} x + \phi''' x\, \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} + \etc.; \] whence ($h$~being the increment of~$x$) \[ \frac{\emph{increment of } \phi x}{\emph{increment of } x} = \phi' x + \phi'' x\, \frac{h}{2} x + \phi''' x\, \frac{h^{2}}{2·3} + \etc., \] which is an expression for the ratio which the increment of a function bears to the increment of its variable. It consists of two parts. The one,~$\phi' x$, into which $h$~does not enter, depends on $x$~only; the remainder is a series, every term of which is multiplied by some power of~$h$, and which therefore diminishes as $h$~diminishes, and may be made as small as we please by making $h$~sufficiently small. To make this last assertion clear, observe that all the ratio, except its first term~$\phi' x$, may be written as follows: \[ %[** TN: Small () in the original] h\left(\phi'' x\, \frac{1}{2} + \phi''' x\, \frac{h}{2·3} + \etc.\right); \] the second factor of which (\PageRef{19}) is a convergent series whenever $h$~is taken less than~$\dfrac{1}{A}$, where $A$~is the limit towards which we approximate by taking the coefficients $\phi'' x × \dfrac{1}{2}$, $\phi''' x × \dfrac{1}{2·3}$,~etc., and forming the ratio of each to the one immediately preceding. This limit, as has been observed, is finite in every series which we have occasion to use; and therefore a value for~$h$ can be chosen so small, that for it the series in the last-named formula is convergent; still more will it be so for every smaller value of~$h$. Let the series be called~$P$. If $P$~be a finite quantity, which decreases when $h$~decreases, $Ph$~can be made as small as we please by sufficiently diminishing~$h$; \PageSep{24} whence $\phi' x + Ph$ can be brought as near as we please to~$\phi' x$. Hence the ratio of the increments of $\phi x$ and~$x$, produced by changing $x$ into~$x + h$, though never equal to~$\phi' x$, approaches towards it as $h$~is diminished, and may be brought as near as we please to it, by sufficiently diminishing~$h$. Therefore to find the coefficient of~$h$ in the development of~$\phi(x + h)$, find $\phi(x + h) - \phi x$, divide it by~$h$, and find the limit towards which it tends as $h$~is diminished. In any series such as \index{Series|EtSeq}% \[ a + bh + ch^{2} + \dots + kh^{n} + lh^{n+1} + mh^{n+2} + \etc. \] which is such that some given value of~$h$ will make it convergent, it may be shown that $h$~can be taken so small that any one term shall contain all the succeeding ones as often as we please. Take any one term, as~$kh^{n}$. It is evident that, be $h$ what it may, \[ kh^{n} : lh^{n+1} + mh^{n+2} + \etc.,\ ::\ k : lh + mh^{2} + \etc., \] the last term of which is $h(l + mh + \etc.)$. By reasoning similar to that in the last paragraph, we can show that this may be made as small as we please, since one factor is a series which is always finite when $h$~is less than~$\dfrac{1}{A}$, and the other factor~$h$ can be made as small as we please. Hence, since $k$~is a given quantity, independent of~$h$, and which therefore remains the same during all the changes of~$h$, the series $h(l + mh + \etc.)$ can be made as small a part of~$k$ as we please, since the first diminishes without limit, and the second remains the same. By the proportion above established, it follows then that $lh^{n+1} + mh^{n+2} + \etc.$, can be made as small a part as we please of~$kh^{n}$. It follows, therefore, that if, instead of the full development of~$\phi(x + h)$, we use only its two first \PageSep{25} terms $\phi x + \phi' x\, h$, the error thereby introduced may, by taking $h$ sufficiently small, be made as small a portion as we please of the small term~$\phi' x\, h$. \Subsection{The Notation of the Differential Calculus.} The first step usually made in the Differential Calculus \index{Calculus, notation of}% \index{Notation!of the Differential Calculus}% is the determination of~$\phi' x$ for all possible values of~$\phi x$, and the construction of general rules for that purpose. Without entering into these we proceed to explain the notation which is used, and to apply the principles already established to the solution of some of those problems which are the peculiar province of the Differential Calculus. When any quantity is increased by an increment, which, consistently with the conditions of the problem, may be supposed as small as we please, this increment is denoted, not by a separate letter, but by prefixing the letter~$d$, either followed by a full stop or not, to that already used to signify the quantity. For example, the increment of~$x$ is denoted under these circumstances by~$dx$; that of~$\phi x$ by~$d.\phi x$; that of~$x^{n}$ by~$d.x^{n}$. If instead of an increment a decrement be used, the sign of~$dx$, etc., must be changed in all expressions which have been obtained on the supposition of an increment; and if an increment obtained by calculation proves to be negative, it is a sign that a quantity which we imagined was increased by our previous changes, was in fact diminished. Thus, if $x$~becomes $x + dx$, $x^{2}$~becomes $x^{2} + d.x^{2}$. But this is also $(x + dx)^{2}$ or $x^{2} + 2x\, dx + (dx)^{2}$; whence $d.x^{2} = 2x\, dx + (dx)^{2}$. Care must be taken not to confound $d.x^{2}$, the increment of~$x^{2}$, with~$(dx)^{2}$, or, as it is often written,~$dx^{2}$, the square of the increment of~$x$. Again, \PageSep{26} if $x$~becomes $x + dx$, $\dfrac{1}{x}$ becomes $\dfrac{1}{x} + d.\dfrac{1}{x}$ and the change of~$\dfrac{1}{x}$ is $\dfrac{1}{x + dx} - \dfrac{1}{x}$ or $-\dfrac{dx}{x^{2} + x\, dx}$; showing that an increment of~$x$ produces a decrement in~$\dfrac{1}{x}$. It must not be imagined that because $x$~occurs in the symbol~$dx$, the value of the latter in any way depends upon that of the former: both the first value of~$x$, and the quantity by which it is made to differ from its first value, are at our pleasure, and the letter~$d$ must merely be regarded as an abbreviation of the words ``\emph{difference of}.'' In the first example, if we divide \index{Differences!of increments}% both sides of the resulting equation by~$dx$, we have $\dfrac{d.x^{2}}{dx} = 2x + dx$. The smaller $dx$~is supposed to be, the more nearly will this equation assume the form $\dfrac{d.x^{2}}{dx} = 2x$, and the ratio of $2x$ to~$1$ is the limit of the \index{Limits|EtSeq}% ratio of the increment of~$x^{2}$ to that of~$x$; to which this ratio may be made to approximate as nearly as we please, but which it can never actually reach. In the Differential Calculus, the limit of the ratio only is retained, to the exclusion of the rest, which may be explained in either of the two following ways: (1) The fraction $\dfrac{d.x^{2}}{dx}$ may be considered as standing, not for any value which it can actually have as long as $dx$~has a real value, but for the limit of all those values which it assumes while $dx$~diminishes. In this sense the equation $\dfrac{d.x^{2}}{dx} = 2x$ is strictly true. But here it must be observed that the algebraical meaning of the sign of division is altered, in such a way that it is no longer allowable to use the numerator and denominator separately, or even at all to consider \PageSep{27} them as quantities. If $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$~stands, not for the ratio of two quantities, but for the limit of that ratio, which cannot be obtained by taking any real value of~$dx$, however small, the whole $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$ may, by convention, have a meaning, but the separate parts $dy$ and~$dx$ have none, and can no more be considered as separate quantities whose ratio is~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$, than the two loops of the figure~$8$ can be considered as separate numbers whose sum is eight. This would be productive of no great inconvenience if it were never required to separate the two; but since all books on the Differential Calculus and its applications are full of examples in which deductions equivalent to assuming $dy = 2x\, dx$ are drawn from such an equation as $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = 2x$, it becomes necessary that the first should be explained, independently of the meaning first given to the second. It may be said, indeed, that if $y = x^{2}$, it follows that $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = 2x + dx$, in which, \emph{if we make $dx = 0$}, the result is $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = 2x$. But if $dx = 0$, $dy$~also~$= 0$, and this equation should be written $\dfrac{0}{0} = 2x$, as is actually done in some treatises on the Differential Calculus,\footnote {This practice was far more common in the early part of the century than now, and was due to the precedent of Euler (1755). For the sense in \index{Euler}% which Euler's view was correct, see the \Title{Encyclopedia Britannica}, art.\ \Title{Infinitesimal Calculus}, Vol.~XII, p.~14, 2nd~column.---\Ed.} to the great confusion of the learner. Passing over the difficulties\footnote {See \Title{Study of Mathematics} (Reprint Edition, Chicago: The Open Court Publishing~Co., 1898), page~126.} of the fraction~$\dfrac{0}{0}$, still the former objection recurs, that the equation $dy = 2x\, dx$ cannot be used \PageSep{28} (and it \emph{is} used even by those who adopt this explanation) without supposing that~$0$, which merely implies an absence of all magnitude, can be used in different senses, so that one~$0$ may be contained in another a certain number of times. This, even if it can be considered as intelligible, is a notion of much too refined a nature for a beginner. (2) The presence of the letter~$d$ is an indication, not only of an increment, but of an increment which we are at liberty to suppose as small as we please. The processes of the Differential Calculus are intended to deduce relations, not between the ratios of different increments, but between the limits to which those ratios approximate, when the increments are decreased. And it may be true of some parts of an equation, that though the taking of them away would alter the relation between $dy$ and~$dx$, it would not alter the limit towards which their ratio approximates, when $dx$ and~$dy$ are diminished. For example, $dy = 2x\, dx + (dx)^{2}$. If $x = 4$ and $dx = .01$, then $dy = .0801$ and $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = 8.01$. If $dx = .0001$, $dy = .00080001$ and $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = 8.0001$. The limit of this ratio, to which we shall come still nearer by making $dx$ still smaller, is~$8$. The term~$(dx)^{2}$, though its presence affects the value of~$dy$ and the ratio~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$, does not affect the limit of the latter, for in $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$ or $2x + dx$, the latter term~$dx$, which arose from the term~$(dx)^{2}$, diminishes continually and without limit. If, then, we throw away the term~$(dx)^{2}$, the consequence is that, make $dx$ what we may, we never obtain~$dy$ as it would be if correctly deduced from the equation $y = x^{2}$, but we obtain the limit of the ratio of~$dy$ to~$dx$. If we throw away all powers of~$dx$ \PageSep{29} above the first, and use the equations so obtained, all ratios formed from these last, or their consequences, are themselves the limiting ratios of which we are in search. \emph{The equations which we thus use are not absolutely true in any case, but may be brought as near as we please to the truth}, by making $dy$~and~$dx$ sufficiently small. If the student at first, instead of using $dy = 2x\, dx$, were to write it thus, $dy = 2x\, dx + \etc.$, the \emph{etc.}\ would remind him that there are other terms; \emph{necessary}, if the value of~$dy$ corresponding to any value of~$dx$ is to be obtained; \emph{unnecessary}, if the \emph{limit} of the ratio of $dy$ to~$dx$ is all that is required. We must adopt the first of these explanations when $dy$ and $dx$ appear in a fraction, and the second when they are on opposite sides of an equation. \Subsection{Algebraical Geometry.} If two straight lines be drawn at right angles to each other, dividing the whole of their plane into four parts, one lying in each right angle, the situation of any point is determined when we know, (1)~in which angle it lies, and (2)~its perpendicular distances from the two right lines. Thus (\Fig{2}) the point~$P$ lying in the angle~$AOB$, is known when $PM$~and~$PN$, or when $OM$~and~$PM$ are known; for, though there is an infinite number of points whose distance from~$OA$ only is the same as that of~$P$, and an infinite number of others, whose distance from~$OB$ is the same as that of~$P$, there is no other point whose distances from both lines are the same as those of~$P$. The line~$OA$ is called the axis of~$x$, because it is usual to denote any variable distance measured on or parallel to~$OA$ by the letter~$x$. For a similar reason, $OB$~is called \PageSep{30} \index{Co-ordinates}% the axis of~$y$. The \emph{co-ordinates}\footnote {The distances $OM$ and~$MP$ are called the \emph{co-ordinates} of the point~$P$. It is moreover usual to call the co-ordinate~$OM$, the \emph{abscissa}, and $MP$, the \emph{ordinate}, of the point~$P$.} or perpendicular distances of a point~$P$ which is supposed to vary its position, are thus denoted by $x$~and~$y$; hence $OM$ or~$PN$ is~$x$, and $PM$ or~$ON$ is~$y$. Let a linear unit be chosen, so that any number may be represented by a straight line. Let the point~$M$, setting out from~$O$, move in the direction~$OA$, always carrying with it the indefinitely extended line~$MP$ perpendicular to~$OA$. While this goes on, let $P$~move upon the line~$MP$ in such a way, that $MP$ or~$y$ is always equal to a given function of~$OM$ or~$x$; for example, let $y = x^{2}$, or let the number \index{Parabola, the}% \Figure{2} of units in~$PM$ be the square of the number of units in~$OM$. As $O$~moves towards~$A$, the point~$P$ will, by its motion on~$MP$, compounded with the motion of the line $MP$ itself, describe a curve~$OP$, in which $PM$~is less than, equal to, or greater than,~$OM$, according as $OM$~is less than, equal to, or greater than the linear unit. It only remains to show how the other branch of this curve is deduced from the equation $y = x^{2}$. And to this end we shall first have to interpolate a few remarks. \PageSep{31} \Subsection{On the Connexion of the Signs of Algebraical and the Directions of Geometrical Magnitudes.} It is shown in algebra, that if, through misapprehension \index{Signs|EtSeq}% of a problem, we measure in one direction, a line which ought to lie in the exactly opposite direction, or if such a mistake be a consequence of some previous misconstruction of the figure, any attempt to deduce the length of that line by algebraical reasoning, will give a negative quantity as the result. And conversely it may be proved by any number of examples, that when an equation in which $a$~occurs has been deduced strictly on the supposition that $a$~is a line measured in one direction, a change of sign in~$a$ will turn the equation into that which would have been deduced by the same reasoning, had we begun by measuring the line~$a$ in the contrary direction. Hence the change of~$+a$ into~$-a$, or of~$-a$ into~$+a$, corresponds in geometry to a change of direction of the line represented by~$a$, and \textit{vice versa}. In illustration of this general fact, the following \index{Circle, equation of|EtSeq}% \index{Circle cut by straight line, investigated|EtSeq}% problem may be useful. Having a circle of given radius, whose centre is in the intersection of the axes of $x$~and~$y$, and also a straight line cutting the axes in two given points, required the co-ordinates of the points (if any) in which the straight line cuts the circle. Let $OA$, the radius of the circle~$= r$, $OE = a$, $OF = b$, and let the co-ordinates of~$P$, one of the points of intersection required, be $OM = x$, $MP = y$. (\Fig{3}.) The point~$P$ being in the circle whose radius is~$r$, we have from the right-angled triangle~$OMP$, $x^{2} + y^{2} = r^{2}$, which equation belongs to the co-ordinates of every point in the circle, and is called \PageSep{32} the equation of the circle. Again, $EM : MP :: EO : OF$ by similar triangles; or $a - x : y :: a : b$, whence $ay + bx = ab$, which is true, by similar reasoning, for every point of the line~$EF$. But for a point~$P'$ lying in~$EF$ produced, we have $EM' : M'P' :: EO : OF$, or $x + a : y :: a : b$, whence $ay - bx = ab$, an equation which may be obtained from the former by changing the sign of~$x$; and it is evident that the direction of~$x$, in the \Figure{3} second case, is opposite to that in the first. Again, for a point~$P''$ in $FE$ produced, we have $EM'' : M''P'' :: EO : OF$, or $x - a : y :: a : b$, whence $bx - ay = ab$, which may be deduced from the first by changing the sign of~$y$; and it is evident that $y$~is measured in different directions in the first and third cases. Hence the equation $ay + bx = ab$ belongs to all parts of the straight line~$EF$, if we agree to consider $M''P''$ as negative, when $MP$~is positive, and $OM'$~as negative \PageSep{33} when $OM$~is positive. Thus, if $OE = 4$, and $OF = 5$, and $OM = 1$, we can determine~$MP$ from the equation $ay + bx = ab$, or $4y + 5 = 20$, which gives $y$~or $MP = 3\frac{3}{4}$. But if $OM'$~be $1$ in length, we can determine~$M'P'$ either by calling $OM'$,~$1$, and using the equation $ay - bx = ab$, or calling $OM'$,~$-1$, and using the equation $ay + bx = ab$, as before. Either gives $M'P' = 6\frac{1}{4}$. The latter method is preferable, inasmuch as it enables us to contain, in one investigation, all the different cases of a problem. We shall proceed to show that this may be done in the present instance. We have to determine the co-ordinates of the point~$P$, from the following equations: \begin{align*} ay + bx &= ab, \\ x^{2} + y^{2} &= r^{2}. \end{align*} Substituting in the second the value of~$y$ derived from the first, or $b\left(\dfrac{a - x}{b}\right)$, we have \[ x^{2} + b^{2}\, \frac{(a - x)^{2}}{a^{2}} = r^{2}, \] or \[ (a^{2} + b^{2}) x^{2} - 2ab^{2}x + a^{2}(b^{2} - r^{2}) = 0; \] and proceeding in a similar manner to find~$y$, we have \[ (a^{2} + b^{2}) y^{2} - 2a^{2}by + b^{2}(a^{2} - r^{2}) = 0, \] which \Typo{give}{gives} \begin{align*} x &= a\, \frac{b^{2} ħ \sqrt{(a^{2} + b^{2})r^{2} - a^{2}b^{2}}}{a^{2} + b^{2}}, \\ y &= b\, \frac{a^{2} \mp \sqrt{(a^{2} + b^{2})r^{2} - a^{2}b^{2}}}{a^{2} + b^{2}}; \end{align*} the upper or the lower sign to be taken in both. Hence when $(a^{2} + b^{2})r^{2} > a^{2}b^{2}$, that is, when $r$~is greater than the perpendicular let fall from~$O$ upon~$EF$, which perpendicular is \PageSep{34} \[ \frac{ab}{\sqrt{a^{2} + b^{2}}}, \] there are two points of intersection. When $(a^{2} + b^{2})r^{2} = a^{2}b^{2}$, the two values of~$x$ become equal, and also those of~$y$, and there is only one point in which the straight line meets the circle; in this case $EF$~is a tangent to the circle. And if $(a^{2} + b^{2})r^{2} < a^{2}b^{2}$, the values of $x$~and~$y$ are impossible, and the straight line does not meet the circle. Of these three cases, we confine ourselves to the first, in which there are two points of intersection. The product of the values of~$x$, with their proper sign, is\footnote {See \Title{Study of Mathematics} (Chicago: The Open Court Pub.~Co.), page~136.} \[ a^{2}\, \frac{b^{2} - r^{2}}{a^{2} + b^{2}}, \] and of~$y$, \[ b^{2}\, \frac{a^{2} - r^{2}}{a^{2} + b^{2}}, \] the signs of which are the same as those of~$b^{2} - r^{2}$, and $a^{2} - r^{2}$. If $b$~and~$a$ be both $> r$, the two values of~$x$ have the same sign; and it will appear from the figure, that the lines they represent are measured in the same direction. And this whether $b$~and~$a$ be positive or negative, since $b^{2} - r^{2}$ and $a^{2} - r^{2}$ are both positive when $a$~and~$b$ are numerically greater than~$r$, whatever their signs may be. That is, if our rule, connecting the signs of algebraical and the directions of geometrical magnitudes, be true, let the directions of $OE$ and $OF$ be altered in any way, so long as $OE$ and $OF$ are both greater than~$OA$, the two values of~$OM$ will have the same direction, and also those of~$MP$. This result may easily be verified from the figure. \PageSep{35} Again, the values of $x$~and~$y$ having the same sign, that sign will be (see the equations) the same as that of $2ab^{2}$ for~$x$, and of $2a^{2}b$ for~$y$, or the same as that of $a$~for~$x$ and of $b$~for~$y$. That is, when $OE$~and~$OF$ are both greater than~$OA$, the direction of each set of co-ordinates will be the same as those of $OE$ and~$OF$, which may also be readily verified from the figure. Many other verifications might thus be obtained of the same principle, viz., that any equation which corresponds to, and is true for, all points in the angle~$AOB$, may be used without error for all points lying in the other three angles, by substituting the proper numerical values, with a negative sign, for those co-ordinates whose directions are opposite to those of the co-ordinates in the angle~$AOB$. In this manner, if four points be taken similarly situated in the four angles, the numerical values of whose co-ordinates are $x = 4$ and $y = 6$, and if the co-ordinates of that point which lies in the angle~$AOB$, are called $+4$ and~$+6$; those of the points lying in the angle~$BOC$ will be $-4$~and~$+6$; in the angle~$COD$ $-4$~and~$-6$; and in the angle~$DOE$ $+4$~and~$-6$. To return to \Fig{2}, if, after having completed the branch of the curve which lies on the right of~$BC$, and whose equation is $y = x^{2}$, we seek that which lies on the left of~$BC$, we must, by the principles established, substitute $-x$ instead of~$x$, when the numerical value obtained for~$(-x)^{2}$ will be that of~$y$, and the sign will show whether $y$~is to be measured in a similar or contrary direction to that of~$MP$. Since $(-x)^{2} = x^{2}$, the direction and value of~$y$, for a given value of~$x$, remains the same as on the right of~$BC$; whence the remaining branch of the curve is similar and equal in all respects to~$OP$, only lying in the angle~$BOD$. \PageSep{36} And thus, if $y$ be any function of~$x$, we can obtain a geometrical representation of the same, by making $y$ the ordinate, and $x$~the abscissa of a curve, every ordinate of which shall be the linear representation of the numerical value of the given function corresponding to the numerical value of the abscissa, the linear unit being a given line. \Subsection{The Drawing of a Tangent to a Curve.} If the point~$P$ (\Fig{2}), setting out from~$O$, move along the branch~$OP$, it will continually change the \Figure[nolabel]{2} \emph{direction} of its motion, never moving, at one point, in \index{Direction}% the direction which it had at any previous point. Let the moving point have reached~$P$, and let $OM = x$, $MP = y$. Let $x$~receive the increment $MM' = dx$, in consequence of which $y$ or $MP$ becomes~$M'P'$, and receives the increment $QP' = dy$; so that $x + dx$ and $y + dy$ are the co-ordinates of the moving point~$P$, when it arrives at~$P'$. Join~$PP'$, which makes, with $PQ$ or~$OM$, an angle, whose tangent is $\dfrac{P'Q}{PQ}$ or~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$. Since the relation $y = x^{2}$ is true for the co-ordinates of every point in the curve, we have $y + dy = (x + dx)^{2}$, \PageSep{37} the subtraction of the former equation from which gives $dy = 2x\, dx + (dx)^{2}$, or $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = 2x + dx$. If the point~$P'$ be now supposed to move backwards towards~$P$, the chord~$PP'$ will diminish without limit, and the inclination of $PP'$ to $PQ$ will also diminish, but not without limit, since the tangent of the angle~$P'PQ$, or~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$, \index{Tangent}% is always greater than the limit~$2x$. If, therefore, a line~$PV$ be drawn through~$P$, making with~$PQ$ an angle whose tangent is~$2x$, the chord~$PP'$ will, as $P'$~approaches towards~$P$, or as $dx$~is diminished, continually approximate towards~$PV$, so that the angle~$P'PV$ may be made smaller than any given angle, by sufficiently diminishing~$dx$. And the line~$PV$ cannot again meet the curve on the side of~$PP'$, nor can any straight line be drawn between it and the curve, the proof of which we leave to the student. Again, if $P'$~be placed on the other side of~$P$, so that its co-ordinates are $x - dx$ and $y - dy$, we have $y - dy = (x - dx)^{2}$, which, subtracted from $y = x^{2}$, gives $dy = 2x\, dx - (dx)^{2}$, or $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = 2x - dx$. By similar reasoning, if the straight line~$PT$ be drawn in continuation of~$PV$, making with~$PN$ an angle, whose tangent is~$2x$, the chord~$PP'$ will continually approach to this line, as before. The line~$TPV$ indicates the direction in which the point~$P$ is proceeding, and is called the \emph{tangent} of the curve at the point~$P$. If the curve were the interior of a small solid tube, in which an atom of matter were made to move, being projected into it at~$O$, and if all the tube above~$P$ were removed, the line~$PV$ is in the direction which the atom would take on emerging at~$P$, and is the line which it would describe. The angle \PageSep{38} which the tangent makes with the axis of~$x$ in any \index{Tangent}% curve, may be found by giving $x$ an increment, finding the ratio which the corresponding increment of~$y$ bears to that of~$x$, and determining the limit of that ratio, or the \emph{differential coefficient}. This limit is the \index{Coefficients, differential}% \index{Differential coefficients}% trigonometrical tangent\footnote {There is some confusion between these different uses of the word tangent. The geometrical tangent is, as already defined, the line between which and a curve no straight line can be drawn; the trigonometrical tangent has reference to an angle, and is the ratio which, in any right-angled triangle, the side opposite the angle bears to that which is adjacent.} of the angle which the geometrical tangent makes with the axis of~$x$. If $y = \phi x$, $\phi' x$~is this trigonometrical tangent. Thus, if the curve be such that the ordinates are the Naperian logarithms\footnote {It may be well to notice that in analysis the Naperian logarithms are \index{Logarithms}% the only ones used; while in practice the common, or Briggs's logarithms, are always preferred.} of the abscissĉ, or $y = \log x$, and $y + dy = \log x + \dfrac{1}{x}\, dx - \dfrac{1}{2x^{2}}\, dx^{2}$, etc., the geometrical tangent of any point whose abscissa is~$x$, makes with the axis an angle whose trigonometrical tangent is~$\dfrac{1}{x}$. This problem, of drawing a tangent to any curve, was one, the consideration of which gave rise to the methods of the Differential Calculus. \Subsection{Rational Explanation of the Language of Leibnitz.} As the peculiar language of the theory of infinitely \index{Infinitely small, the notion of|EtSeq}% \index{Leibnitz}% small quantities is extensively used, especially in works of natural philosophy, it has appeared right to us to introduce it, in order to show how the terms which are used may be made to refer to some natural and rational mode of explanation. In applying this language to \Fig{2}, it would be said that the curve~$OP$ is a polygon consisting of an infinite number of \index{Polygon}% \PageSep{39} infinitely small sides, each of which produced is a tangent to the curve; also that if $MM'$ be taken infinitely small, the chord and arc~$PP'$ coincide with \index{Arc and its chord, a continuously decreasing|EtSeq}% one of these rectilinear elements; and that an infinitely small arc coincides with its chord. All which must be interpreted to mean that, the chord and arc being diminished, approach more and more nearly to a ratio of equality as to their lengths; and also that the greatest separation between an arc and its chord may be made as small a part as we please of the whole chord or arc, by sufficiently diminishing the chord. We shall proceed to a strict proof of this; but in the meanwhile, as a familiar illustration, imagine a small arc to be cut off from a curve, and its extremities joined by a chord, thus forming an arch, of which the chord is the base. From the middle point of the chord, erect a perpendicular to it, meeting the arc, which will thus represent the height of the arch. Imagine this figure to be magnified, without distortion or alteration of its proportions, so that the larger figure may be, as it is expressed, a true picture of the smaller one. However the original arc may be diminished, let the magnified base continue of a given length. This is possible, since on any line a figure may be constructed similar to a given figure. If the original curve could be such that the height of the arch could never be reduced below a certain part of the chord, say one thousandth, the height of the magnified arch could never be reduced below one thousandth of the magnified chord, since the proportions of the two figures are the same. But if, in the original curve, an arc can be taken so small that the height of the arch is as small a part as we please of the chord, it will follow that in the magnified figure where \PageSep{40} the chord is always of one length, the height of the arch can be made as small as we please, seeing that it can be made as small a part as we please of a given line. It is possible in this way to conceive a whole curve so magnified, that a given arc, however small, shall be represented by an arc of any given length, however great; and the proposition amounts to this, that let the dimensions of the magnified curve be any \index{Curve, magnified}% \index{Magnified curve}% given number of times the original, however great, an arch can be taken upon the original curve so small, that the height of the corresponding arch in the magnified figure shall be as small as we please. \Figure{4} Let $PP'$ (\Fig{4}) be a part of a curve, whose equation is $y = \phi(x)$, that is, $PM$~may always be found by substituting the numerical value of~$OM$ in a given function of~$x$. Let $OM = x$ receive the increment $MM' = dx$, which we may afterwards suppose as small as we please, but which, in order to render the figure more distinct, is here considerable. The value of $PM$ or~$y$ is~$\phi x$, and that of $P'M'$ or $y + dy$ is~$\phi(x + dx)$. Draw $PV$, the tangent at~$P$, which, as has been \index{Tangent}% shown, makes, with~$PQ$, an angle, whose trigonometrical tangent is the limit of the ratio~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$, when $x$~is decreased, or~$\phi' x$. Draw the chord~$PP'$, and from any \PageSep{41} point in it, for example, its middle point~$p$, draw~$pv$ parallel to~$PM$, cutting the curve in~$a$. The value of~$P'Q$, or~$dy$, or $\phi(x + dx) - \phi x$ is %[** TN: This line displayed in the orig] \[ P'Q = \phi' x\, dx + \phi'' x\, \frac{(dx)^{2}}{2} + \phi''' x\, \frac{(dx)^{3}}{2·3} + \etc. \] But $\phi' x\, dx$~is $\tan VPQ·PQ = VQ$. Hence $VQ$~is the first term of this series, and $P'V$~the aggregate of the rest. But it has been shown that $dx$~can be taken so small, that any one term of the above series shall contain the rest, as often as we please. Hence $PQ$~can be taken so small that $VQ$~shall contain~$VP'$ as often as we please, or the ratio of $VQ$ to~$VP'$ shall be as great as we please. And the ratio $VQ$ to~$PQ$ continues finite, being always~$\phi' x$; hence $P'V$~also decreases without limit as compared with~$PQ$. Next, the chord~$PP'$ or $\sqrt{(dx)^{2} + (dy)^{2}}$, or \[ dx \sqrt{1 + \left(\frac{dy}{dx}\right)^{2}} \] is to~$PQ$ or~$dx$ in the ratio of $\sqrt{1 + \left(\dfrac{dy}{dx}\right)^{2}} : 1$, which, as $PQ$~is diminished, continually approximates to that of $\sqrt{1 + (\phi' x)^{2}} : 1$, which is the ratio of~$PV : PQ$. Hence the ratio of~$PP' : PV$ continually approaches to unity, or $PQ$~may be taken so small that the difference of $PP'$~and~$PV$ shall be as small a part of either of them as we please. Finally, the arc~$PP'$ is greater than the chord~$PP'$ and less than $PV + VP'$. Hence $\dfrac{\arc PP'}{\chord PP'}$ lies between $1$~and $\dfrac{PV}{PP'} + \dfrac{VP'}{PP'}$, the former of which two fractions can be brought as near as we please to unity, and the latter can be made as small as we please; for \PageSep{42} since $P'V$~can be made as small a part of~$PQ$ as we please, still more can it be made as small a part as we please of~$PP'$, which is greater than~$PQ$. Therefore the arc and chord~$PP'$ may be made to have a ratio as nearly equal to unity as we please. And because $pa$~is less than~$pv$, and therefore less than~$P'V$, it follows that $pa$~may be made as small a part as we please of~$PQ$, and still more of~$PP'$. In these propositions is contained the rational explanation of the proposition of Leibnitz, that ``an infinitely \index{Leibnitz}% small arc is equal to, and coincides with, its chord.'' \Subsection{Orders of Infinity.} Let there be any number of series, arranged in \index{Infinity, orders of|EtSeq}% \index{Orders of infinity|EtSeq}% powers of~$h$, so that the lowest power is first; let them contain none but whole powers, and let them all be such, that each will be convergent, on giving to~$h$ a sufficiently small value: as follows, \begin{alignat*}{4} Ah + Bh^{2} &{}+{}& Ch^{3} &{}+{}& Dh^{4} &{}+{}& Eh^{5} &+ \etc. \Tag{(1)} \\ B'h^{2} &{}+{}& C'h^{3} &{}+{}& D'h^{4} &{}+{}& E'h^{5} &+ \etc. \Tag{(2)} \\ && C''h^{3} &{}+{}& D''h^{4} &{}+{}& E''h^{5} &+ \etc. \Tag{(3)} \\ &&&& D'''h^{4} &{}+{}& E'''h^{5} &+ \etc. \Tag{(4)} \\ &&&&&& \etc. & \tag*{\etc.} \end{alignat*} As $h$~is diminished, all these expressions decrease without limit; but the first \emph{increases} with respect to the second, that is, contains it more times after a decrease of~$h$ than it did before. For the ratio of \Eq{(1)} to~\Eq{(2)} is that of $A + Bh + Ch^{2} + \etc.$ to $B'h + C'h^{2} + \etc.$, the ratio of the two not being changed by dividing both by~$h$. The first term of the latter ratio approximates continually to~$A$, as $h$~is diminished, and the second can be made as small as we please, and therefore can be contained in the first as often as \PageSep{43} we please. Hence the ratio \Eq{(1)}~to~\Eq{(2)} can be made as great as we please. By similar reasoning, the ratio \Eq{(2)}~to~\Eq{(3)}, of \Eq{(3)}~to~\Eq{(4)}, etc., can be made as great as we please. We have, then, a series of quantities, each of which, by making $h$ sufficiently small, can be made as small as we please. Nevertheless this decrease increases the ratio of the first to the second, of the second to the third, and so on, and the increase is without limit. Again, if we take \Eq{(1)}~and~$h$, the ratio of \Eq{(1)}~to~$h$ is that of $A + Bh + Ch^{2} + \etc.$ to~$1$, which, by a sufficient decrease of~$h$, may be brought as near as we please to that of $A$~to~$1$. But if we take \Eq{(1)}~and~$h^{2}$, the ratio of \Eq{(1)}~to~$h^{2}$ is that of $A + Bh + \etc.$ to~$h$, which, by previous reasoning, may be increased without limit; and the same for any higher power of~$h$. Hence \Eq{(1)}~is said to be \emph{comparable} to the first power of~$h$, or \emph{of the first order}, since this is the only power of~$h$ whose ratio to~\Eq{(1)} tends towards a finite limit. By the same reasoning, the ratio of \Eq{(2)}~to~$h^{2}$, which is that of $B' + C'h + \etc.$ to~$1$, continually approaches that of $B'$~to~$1$; but the ratio \Eq{(2)}~to~$h$, which is that of $B'h + C'h^{2} + \etc.$ to~$1$, diminishes without limit, as $h$~is decreased, while the ratio of \Eq{(2)}~to~$h^{2}$, or of $B' + C'h + \etc.$ to~$h$, increases without limit. Hence \Eq{(2)}~is said to be \emph{comparable} to the second power of~$h$, or \emph{of the second order}, since this is the only power of~$h$ whose ratio to~\Eq{(2)} tends towards a finite limit. In the language of Leibnitz if $h$~be an infinitely small quantity, \Eq{(1)}~is an infinitely small quantity of the first order, \Eq{(2)}~is an infinitely small quantity of the second order, and so on. We may also add that the ratio of two series of the same order continually approximates to the ratio \PageSep{44} of their lowest terms. For example, the ratio of $Ah^{3} + Bh^{4} + \etc.$ to $A'h^{3} + B'h^{4} + \etc.$ is that of $A + Bh + \etc.$ to $A' + B'h + \etc.$, which, as $h$~is diminished, continually approximates to the ratio of $A$ to~$A'$, which is also that of $Ah^{3}$ to~$A'h^{3}$, or the ratio of the lowest terms. In \Fig{4}, $PQ$~or $dx$ being put in place of~$h$, $QP'$, or $\phi' x\, dx + \phi'' x\, \dfrac{(dx)^{2}}{2}$, etc., is of the first order, as are~$PV$, and the chord~$PP'$; while $P'V$, or $\phi'' x\, \dfrac{(dx)^{2}}{2} + \etc.$, is of the second order. The converse proposition is readily shown, that if the ratio of two series arranged in powers of~$h$ continually approaches to some finite limit as $h$~is diminished, the two series are of the same order, or the exponent of the lowest power of~$h$ is the same in both. Let $Ah^{a}$ and $Bh^{b}$ be the lowest powers of~$h$, whose ratio, as has just been shown, continually approximates to the actual ratio of the two series, as $h$~is diminished. The hypothesis is that the ratio of the two series, and therefore that of $Ah^{a}$ to~$Bh^{b}$, has a finite limit. This cannot be if $a > b$, for then the ratio of $Ah^{a}$ to $Bh^{b}$ is that of $Ah^{a-b}$ to~$B$, which diminishes without limit; neither can it be when $a < b$, for then the same ratio is that of $A$ to~$Bh^{b-a}$, which increases without limit; hence $a$~must be equal to~$b$. We leave it to the student to prove strictly a proposition assumed in the preceding; viz., that if the ratio of $P$~to~$Q$ has unity for its limit, when $h$~is diminished, the limiting ratio of $P$~to~$R$ will be the same as the limiting ratio of $Q$~to~$R$. We proceed further to illustrate the Differential Calculus as applied to Geometry. \PageSep{45} \Subsection[A Geometrical Illustration: Limit of the Intersections of Two Coinciding Straight Lines.] {A Geometrical Illustration.} Let $OC$ and~$OD$ (\Fig{5}) be two axes at right angles to one another, and let a line~$AB$ of given length be placed with one extremity in each axis. Let this line move from its first position into that of~$A'B'$ on one side, and afterwards into that of~$A''B''$ on the other side, always preserving its first length. The motion of a ladder, one end of which is against a wall, and the other on the ground, is an instance. Let $A'B'$ and $A''B''$ intersect~$AB$ in $P'$~and~$P''$. If \index{Ladder against wall|EtSeq}% $A''B''$~were gradually moved from its present position into that of~$A'B'$, the point~$P''$ would also move gradually \Figure{5} from its present position into that of~$P'$, passing, in its course, through every point in the line~$P'P''$. But here it is necessary to remark that $AB$~is itself one of the positions intermediate between $A'B'$ and~$A''B''$, and when two lines are, by the motion of one of them, brought into one and the same straight line, they intersect one another (if this phrase can be here applied at all) in every point, and all idea of one distinct point of intersection is lost. Nevertheless $P''$~describes one part of~$P''P'$ before $A''B''$~has come into the position~$AB$, and the rest afterwards, when it is between $AB$ and~$A'B'$. \PageSep{46} Let $P$~be the point of separation; then every point of~$P'P''$, except~$P$, is a real point of intersection of~$AB$, with one of the positions of~$A''B''$, and when $A''B''$~has moved very near to~$AB$, the point~$P''$ will be very near to~$P$; and there is no point so near to~$P$, that it may not be made the intersection of $A''B''$ and~$AB$, by bringing the former sufficiently near to the latter. This point~$P$ is, therefore, the \emph{limit} of the intersections \index{Intersections, limit of|EtSeq}% \index{Limit of intersections|EtSeq}% of $A''B''$~and~$AB$, and cannot be found by the ordinary application of algebra to geometry, but may be made the subject of an inquiry similar to those \Figure[nolabel]{5} which have hitherto occupied us, in the following manner: Let $OA = a$, $OB = b$, $AB = A'B' = A''B'' = l$. Let $AA' = da$, $BB' = db$, whence $OA' = a + da$, $OB' = b - db$. We have then $a^{2} + b^{2} = l^{2}$, and $(a + da)^{2} + (b - db)^{2} = l^{2}$; subtracting the former of which from the development of the latter, we have \[ 2a\, da + (da)^{2} - 2b\, db + (db)^{2} = 0\Add{,} \] or \[ \frac{db}{da} = \frac{2a + da}{2b - db}\Add{.} \Tag{(1)} \] As $A'B'$ moves towards~$AB$, $da$~and~$db$ are diminished without limit, $a$~and~$b$ remaining the same; hence the limit of the ratio~$\dfrac{db}{da}$ is $\dfrac{2a}{2b}$ or~$\dfrac{a}{b}$. \PageSep{47} Let the co-ordinates\footnote {The lines $OM'$ and $M'P'$ are omitted, to avoid crowding the figure.} of~$P'$ be $OM' = x$ and $M'P = y$. Then (\PageRef{32}) the co-ordinates of any point in~$AB$ have the equation \[ ay + bx = ab\Add{.} \Tag{(2)} \] The point~$P'$ is in this line, and also in the one which cuts off $a + da$ and $b - db$ from the axes, whence \[ (a + da)y + (b - db)x = (a + da)(b - db)\Add{;} \Tag{(3)} \] subtract \Eq{(2)} from~\Eq{(3)} after developing the latter, which gives \[ y\, da - x\, db = b\, da - a\, db - da\, db\Add{.} \Tag{(4)} \] If we now suppose $A'B'$~to move towards~$AB$, equation~\Eq{(4)} gives no result, since each of its terms diminishes without limit. If, however, we divide~\Eq{(4)} by~$da$, and substitute in the result the value of~$\dfrac{db}{da}$ obtained from~\Eq{(1)} we have \[ y - x\, \frac{2a + da}{2b - db} = b - a\, \frac{2a + da}{2b - db} - db\Add{.} \Tag{(5)} \] From this and~\Eq{(2)} we might deduce the values of $y$ and~$x$, for the point~$P'$, as the figure actually stands. Then by diminishing $db$~and $da$ without limit, and observing the limit towards which $x$~and~$y$ tend, we might deduce the co-ordinates of~$P$, the limit of the intersections. The same result may be more simply obtained, by diminishing $da$~and~$db$ in equation~\Eq{(5)}, before obtaining the values of $y$~and~$x$. This gives \[ y - \frac{a}{b}\, x = b - \frac{a^{2}}{b} \quad\text{or}\quad by - ax = b^{2} - a^{2}\Add{.} \Tag{(6)} \] From \Eq{(6)}~and~\Eq{(2)} we find (\Fig{6}) \[ x = OM = \frac{a^{3}}{a^{2} + b^{2}} = \frac{a^{3}}{l^{2}} \quad\text{and}\quad y = MP = \frac{b^{3}}{a^{2} + b^{2}} = \frac{b^{3}}{l^{2}}. \] \PageSep{48} This limit of the intersections is different for every different position of the line~$AB$, but may be determined, in every case, by the following simple construction. Since (\Fig{6}) $BP: PN$, or $OM :: BA : AO$, we have $BP = OM\, \dfrac{BA}{AO} = \dfrac{a^{3}}{l^{2}}\, \dfrac{l}{a} = \dfrac{a^{2}}{l}$; and, similarly, $PA = \dfrac{b^{2}}{l}$. Let $OQ$~be drawn perpendicular to~$BA$; then since $OA$~is a mean proportional between $AQ$ and~$AB$, we have $AQ = \dfrac{a^{2}}{l}$, and similarly $BQ = \dfrac{b^{2}}{l}$. Hence $BP = AQ$ and $AP = BQ$, or the point~$P$ is as far from either extremity of~$AB$ as $Q$~is from the other. \Figure{6} \Subsection{The Same Problem Solved by the Principles of Leibnitz.} We proceed to solve the same problem, using the \index{Leibnitz}% principles of Leibnitz, that is, supposing magnitudes can be taken so small, that those proportions may be regarded as absolutely correct, which are not so in reality, but which only approach more nearly to the truth, the smaller the magnitudes are taken. The inaccuracy of this supposition has been already pointed out; yet it must be confessed that this once got over, \PageSep{49} the results are deduced with a degree of simplicity and consequent clearness, not to be found in any other method. The following cannot be regarded as a demonstration, except by a mind so accustomed to the subject that it can readily convert the various inaccuracies into their corresponding truths, and see, at one glance, how far any proposition will affect the final result. The beginner will be struck with the extraordinary assertions which follow, given in their most naked form, without any attempt at a less startling mode of expression. \Figure{7} Let $A'B'$ (\Fig{7}) be a position of~$AB$ infinitely \index{Infinitely small, the notion of}% near to it; that is, let $A'PA$~be an infinitely small angle. With the centre~$P$, and the radii $PA'$ and~$PB$, describe the infinitely small arcs $A'a$,~$Bb$. An infinitely small arc of a circle is a straight line perpendicular to its radius; hence $A'aA$~and~$BbB'$ are right-angled triangles, the first similar to~$BOA$, the two having the angle~$A$ in common, and the second similar to~$B'OA'$. Again, since the angles of~$BOA$, which are finite, only differ from those of~$B'OA'$ by the infinitely small angle~$A'PA$, they may be regarded as \PageSep{50} equal; whence $A'aA$~and~$B'bB$ are similar to~$BOA$, and to one another. Also $P$~is the point of which we are in search, or infinitely near to it; and since $BA = B'A'$, of which $BP = bP$ and $aP = A'P$, the remainders $B'b$~and~$Aa$ are equal. Moreover, $Bb$~and~$A'a$ being arcs of circles subtending equal angles, are in the proportion of the radii $BP$~and~$PA'$. Hence we have the following proportions: \begin{gather*} Aa : A'a :: OA : OB :: a : b \\ Bb : B'b :: OA : OB :: a : b\rlap{.} \end{gather*} The composition of which gives, since $Aa = B'b$: \[ \PadTo[r]{BP + Pa}{Bb} : A'a :: \PadTo[l]{a^{2} + b^{2}}{a^{2}} : b^{2}. \] Also \[ \PadTo[r]{BP + Pa}{Bb} : A'a :: \PadTo[l]{a^{2} + b^{2}}{BP} : Pa, \] whence \[ \PadTo[r]{BP + Pa}{BP} : Pa :: \PadTo[l]{a^{2} + b^{2}}{a^{2}} : b^{2}, \] and \[ BP + Pa : Pa :: a^{2} + b^{2} : b^{2}. \] But $Pa$~only differs from~$PA$ by the infinitely small quantity~$Aa$, and $BP + PA = l$, and $a^{2} + b^{2} = l^{2}$; whence \[ l : PA :: l^{2} : b^{2},\quad\text{or}\quad PA = \frac{b^{2}}{l}, \] which is the result already obtained. In this reasoning we observe four independent errors, from which others follow: (1)~that $Bb$~and~$A'a$ are straight lines at right-angles to~$Pa$; (2)~that $BOA$\Add{,}~$B'OA'$ are similar triangles; (3)~that $P$~is really the point of which we are in search; (4)~that $PA$~and~$Pa$ are equal. But at the same time we observe that every one of these assumptions approaches the truth, as we diminish the angle~$A'PA$, so that there is no magnitude, line or angle, so small that the linear or angular errors, arising from the above-mentioned suppositions, may not be made smaller. We now proceed to put the same demonstration \PageSep{51} in a stricter form, so as to neglect no quantity during the process. This should always be done by the beginner, until he is so far master of the subject as to be able to annex to the inaccurate terms the ideas necessary for their rational explanation. To the former figure add $B\beta$ and~$A\alpha$, the real perpendiculars, with which the arcs have been confounded. Let $\angle A'PA = d\theta$, \index{Angle, unit employed in measuring an}% $PA = p$, $Aa = dp$, $BP = q$, $B'b = dq$; and $OA = a$, $OB = b$, and $AB = l$. Then\footnote {For the unit employed in measuring an angle, see \Title{Study of Mathematics} (Chicago, 1898), pages 273--277.} $A'a = (p - dp)\, d\theta$, $Bb = q\, d\theta$, and the triangles $A'A\alpha$ and $B'B\beta$ are similar to \Figure[nolabel]{7} $BOA$~and~$B'OA'$. The perpendiculars $A'\alpha$ and~$B\beta$ are equal to $PA' \sin d\theta$ and $PB \sin d\theta$, or $(p - dp) \sin d\theta$ and $q \sin d\theta$. Let $a\alpha = \mu$ and $b\beta = \nu$. These (\PageRef[p.]{9}) will diminish without limit as compared with $A'\alpha$ and~$B\beta$; and since the ratios of $A'\alpha$ to~$\alpha A$ and $B\beta$ to~$\beta B'$ continue finite (these being sides of triangles similar to $AOB$ and~$A'OB'$), $a\alpha$~and~$b\beta$ will diminish indefinitely with respect to $\alpha A$~and~$\beta B'$. Hence the ratio $A\alpha$ to~$\beta B'$ or $dp + \mu$ to $dq + \nu$ will continually approximate to that of $dp$ to~$dq$, or a ratio of equality. \PageSep{52} The exact proportions, to which those in the last page are approximations, are as follows: \begin{alignat*}{3} dp + \mu &: (p - dp) \sin d\theta &&:: a &&: b, \\ q \sin d\theta &: \PadTo{(p - dp) \sin d\theta}{dq + \nu} &&:: a - da &&: b + db; \end{alignat*} by composition of which, recollecting that $dp = dq$ (which is rigorously true) and dividing the two first terms of the resulting proportion by~$dp$, we have \[ q\left(1 + \frac{\mu}{dp}\right) : (p - dp)\left(1 + \frac{\nu}{dp}\right) :: a(a - da) : b(b + db). \] If $d\theta$ be diminished without limit, the quantities $da$,~$db$, and~$dp$, and also the ratios $\dfrac{\mu}{dp}$ and~$\dfrac{\nu}{dp}$, as above-mentioned, are diminished without limit, so that the limit of the proportion just obtained, or the proportion which gives the limits of the lines into which $P$~divides~$AB$, is \begin{alignat*}{3} q &: p &&:: a^{2} &&: b^{2}, \\ \intertext{hence} q + p = l &: p &&:: a^{2} + b^{2} = l^{2} &&: b^{2}, \end{alignat*} the same as before. \Subsection[An Illustration from Dynamics: Velocity, Acceleration, etc.] {An Illustration from Dynamics.} We proceed to apply the preceding principles to dynamics, or the theory of motion. Suppose a point moving along a straight line uniformly; that is, if the whole length described be divided into any number of equal parts, however great, each of those parts is described in the same time. Thus, whatever length is described in the first second of time, or in any part of the first second, the same is described in any other second, or in the same part of any other second. The number of units of length described in a unit of time is called the \emph{velocity}; thus \index{Velocity!linear|EtSeq}% a velocity of $3.01$~feet in a second means that the \PageSep{53} point describes three feet and one hundredth in each second, and a proportional part of the same in any part of a second. Hence, if $v$~be the velocity, and $t$~the units of time elapsed from the beginning of the motion, $vt$~is the length described; and if any length described be known, the velocity can be determined by dividing that length by the time of describing it. Thus, a point which moves uniformly through $3$~feet in $1\frac{1}{2}$~second, moves with a velocity of $3 ÷ 1\frac{1}{2}$, or $2$~feet per~second. Let the point not move uniformly; that is, let different \index{Continuous quantities}% \index{Quantities, continuous}% parts of the line, having the same length, be described in different times; at the same time let the motion be \emph{continuous}, that is, not suddenly increased or decreased, as it would be if the point were composed of some hard matter, and received a blow while it was moving. This will be the case if its motion be represented by some algebraical function of the time, or if, $t$~being the number of units of time during which the point has moved, the number of units of length described can be represented by~$\phi t$. This, for example, we will suppose to be~$t + t^{2}$, the unit of time being one second, and the unit of length one inch; so that $\frac{1}{2} + \frac{1}{4}$, or $\frac{3}{4}$~of an inch, is described in the first half second; $1 + 1$, or two inches, in the first second; $2 + 4$, or six inches, in the first two seconds, and so on. Here we have no longer an evident measure of the velocity of the point; we can only say that it obviously increases from the beginning of the motion to the end, and is different at every two different points. Let the time~$t$ elapse, during which the point will describe the distance $t + t^{2}$; let a further time~$dt$ elapse, during which the point will increase its distance to $t + dt + (t + dt)^{2}$, which, diminished by~$t + t^{2}$, gives \PageSep{54} $dt + 2t\, dt + (dt)^{2}$ for the length described during the increment of time~$dt$. This varies with the value of~$t$; thus, in the interval~$dt$ after the first second, the length described is $3\, dt + dt^{2}$; after the second second, it is $5\, dt + (dt)^{2}$, and so on. Nor can we, as in the case of uniform motion, divide the length described, by the time, and call the result the velocity with which that length is described; for no length, however small, is here uniformly described. If we were to divide a length by the time in which it is described, and also its first and second halves by the times in which they are respectively described, the three results would be all different from one another. Here a difficulty arises, similar to that already noticed, when a point moves along a curve; in which, as we have seen, it is improper to say that it is moving in any one direction through an arc, however small. Nevertheless a straight line was found at every point, which did, more nearly than any other straight line, represent the direction of the motion. So, in this case, though it is incorrect to say that there is any uniform velocity with which the point continues to move for any portion of time, however small, we can, at the end of every time, assign a uniform velocity, which shall represent, more nearly than any other, the rate at which the point is moving. If we say that, at the end of the time~$t$, the point is moving with a velocity~$v$, we must not now say that the length~$v\, dt$ is described in the succeeding interval of time~$dt$; but we mean that $dt$~may be taken so small, that $v\, dt$~shall bear to the distance actually described a ratio as near to equality as we please. Let the point have moved during the time~$t$, after which let successive intervals of time elapse, each \PageSep{55} \index{Coefficients, differential}% \index{Differential coefficients}% equal to~$dt$. At the end of the times, $t$,~$t + dt$, $t + 2\, dt$, $t + 3\, dt$,~etc., the whole lengths described will be $t + t^{2}$, $t + dt + (t + dt)^{2}$, $t + 2\, dt + (t + 2\, dt)^{2}$, $t + 3\, dt + (t + 3\, dt)^{2}$, etc.; the differences of which, or $dt + 2t\, dt + (dt)^{2}$, $dt + 2t\, dt + 3(dt)^{2}$, $dt + 2t\, dt + 5(dt)^{2}$, etc., are the lengths described in the first, second, third, etc., intervals~$dt$. These are not equal to one another, as would be the case if the velocity were uniform; but by making $dt$ sufficiently small, their ratio may be brought as near to equality as we please, since the terms $(dt)^{2}$,~$3(dt)^{2}$,~etc., by which they all differ from the common part $(1 + 2t)\, dt$, may be made as small as we please, in comparison of this common part. If we divide the above-mentioned lengths by~$dt$, which does not alter their ratio, they become $1 + 2t + dt$, $1 + 2t + 3\, dt$, $1 + 2t + 5\, dt$, etc., which may be brought as near as we please to equality, by sufficient diminution of~$dt$. Hence $1 + 2t$ is said to be the velocity of the point after the time~$t$; and if we take a succession of equal intervals of time, each equal to~$dt$, and sufficiently small, the lengths described in those intervals will bear to $(1 + 2t)\, dt$, the length which would be described in the same interval with the uniform velocity $1 + 2t$, a ratio as near to equality as we please. And observe, that if $\phi t$ is $t + t^{2}$, $\phi' t$~is $1 + 2t$, or the coefficient of~$h$ in $(t + h) + (t + h)^{2}$. In the same way it may be shown, that if the point moves so that $\phi t$~always represents the length described in the time~$t$, the differential coefficient of~$\phi t$\Add{,} or~$\phi' t$, is the velocity with which the point is moving at the end of the time~$t$. For the time~$t$ having elapsed, the whole lengths described at the end of the times $t$ and $t + dt$ are $\phi t$ and $\phi(t + dt)$; whence the length described during the time~$dt$ is \PageSep{56} \[ \phi(t + dt) - \phi t, \quad\text{or}\quad \phi't\, dt + \phi'' t\, \frac{(dt)^{2}}{2} + \etc. \] Similarly, the length described in the next interval $dt$ is \begin{gather*} \phi(t + 2\, dt) - \phi(t + dt); \quad\text{or}, \displaybreak[0] \\ \phi t + \phi' t\, 2\, dt + \phi'' t\, \frac{(2\, dt)^{2}}{2} + \etc. \displaybreak[0] \\ -(\phi t + \phi' t\, dt + \phi'' t\, \frac{(dt)^{2}}{2} + \etc.), \displaybreak[0] \\ \intertext{which is} \phi' t\, dt + 3\phi'' t\, \frac{(dt)^{2}}{2} + \etc.; \end{gather*} the length described in the third interval~$dt$ is $\phi' t\, dt + 5\phi'' t\, \dfrac{(dt)^{2}}{2} + \etc.$,~etc. Now, it has been shown for each of these, that the first term can be made to contain the aggregate of all the rest as often as we please, by making $dt$ sufficiently small; this first term is $\phi' t\, dt$ in all, or the length which would be described in the time~$dt$ by the velocity $\phi' t$ continued uniformly: it is possible, therefore, to take $dt$ so small, that the lengths actually described in a succession of intervals equal to~$dt$, shall be as nearly as we please in a ratio of equality with those described in the same intervals of time by the velocity~$\phi' t$. For example, it is observed in bodies which fall \index{Falling bodies}% to the earth from a height above it, when the resistance of the air is removed, that if the time be taken in seconds, and the distance in feet, the number of feet fallen through in $t$~seconds is always~$at^{2}$, where $a = 16\frac{1}{12}$ very nearly; what is the velocity of a body which has fallen \textit{in~vacuo} for four seconds? Here $\phi t$ being~$at^{2}$, we find, by substituting $t + h$, or $t + dt$, instead of~$t$, that $\phi' t$~is~$2at$, or $2 × 16\frac{1}{12} × t$; which, at \PageSep{57} the end of four seconds, is $32\frac{1}{6} × 4$, or $128\frac{2}{3}$~feet. That is, at the end of four seconds a falling body moves at the rate of $128\frac{2}{3}$~feet per~second. By which we do not mean that it continues to move with this velocity for any appreciable time, since the rate is always varying; but that the length described in the interval~$dt$ after the fourth second, may be made as nearly as we please in a ratio of equality with $128\frac{2}{3} × dt$, by taking $dt$ sufficiently small. This velocity~$2at$ is said to be \emph{uniformly} accelerated; since in each second the \index{Accelerated motion}% \index{Uniformly accelerated}% same velocity~$2a$ is gained. And since, when $x$~is the space described, $\phi' t$~is the limit of~$\dfrac{dx}{dt}$, the velocity is also this limit; that is, when a point does not move uniformly, the velocity is not represented by any increment of length divided by its increment of time, but by the limit to which that ratio continually tends, as the increment of time is diminished. \Subsection{Simple Harmonic Motion.} We now propose the following problem: A point \index{Motion!simple harmonic}% \index{Simple harmonic motion}% moves uniformly round a circle; with what velocities do the abscissa and ordinate increase or decrease, at any given point? (\Fig{8}.) Let the point~$P$, setting out from~$A$, describe the arc~$AP$, etc., with the uniform velocity of $a$~inches per~second. Let $OA = r$, $\angle A0P = \theta$, $\angle POP' = d\theta$, $0M = x$, $MP = y$, $MM' = dx$, $QP' = dy$. From the first principles of trigonometry \begin{alignat*}{4}%[** TN: Re-aligned from the original] &x &&= r \cos\theta\Add{,} \\ &x - dx &&= r \cos(\theta + d\theta) &&= r \cos\theta \cos d\theta - r \sin\theta \sin d\theta\Add{,} \displaybreak[0] \\ &y &&= r \sin\theta\Add{,} \\ &y + dy &&= r \sin(\theta + d\theta) &&= r \sin\theta \cos d\theta + r \cos\theta \sin d\theta. \end{alignat*} \PageSep{58} Subtracting the second from the first, and the third from the fourth, we have \begin{alignat*}{2} dx &= r \sin\theta \sin d\theta + r \cos\theta(1 - \cos d\theta)\Add{,} \Tag{(1)} \\ dy &= r \cos\theta \sin d\theta + r \sin\theta(1 - \cos d\theta)\Add{.} \Tag{(2)} \\ \end{alignat*} But if $d\theta$ be taken sufficiently small, $\sin d\theta$, and~$d\theta$, may be made as nearly in a ratio of equality as we please, and $1 - \cos d\theta$ may be made as small a part as we please, either of $d\theta$ or $\sin d\theta$. These follow from \Fig{1}, in which it was shown that $BM$ and the arc~$BA$, or (if $OA = r$ and $AOB = d\theta$), $r \sin d\theta$ and~$r\, d\theta$, may be brought as near to a ratio of equality as we \Figure{8} please, which is therefore true of $\sin d\theta$ and~$d\theta$. Again, it was shown that~$AM$, or $r - r \cos d\theta$, can be made as small a part as we please, either of~$BM$ or the arc~$BA$, that is, either of $r \sin d\theta$, or~$r\, d\theta$; the same is therefore true of $1 - \cos d\theta$, and either $\sin d\theta$ or~$d\theta$. Hence, if we write equations \Eq{(1)}~and~\Eq{(2)} thus, \[ dx = r \sin\theta\, d\theta\quad (1)\qquad\qquad dy = r \cos\theta\, d\theta\quad (2), \] we have equations, which, though never exactly true, are such that by making $d\theta$ sufficiently small, the errors may be made as small parts of~$d\theta$ as we please. Again, since the arc~$AP$ is uniformly described, so also is the angle~$POA$; and since an arc~$a$ is described \PageSep{59} in one second, the angle~$\dfrac{a}{r}$ is described in the same \index{Velocity!angular}% time; this is, therefore, the \emph{angular velocity}.\footnote {The same considerations of velocity which have been applied to the motion of a point along a line may also be applied to the motion of a line round a point. If the angle so described be always increased by equal angles in equal portions of time, the angular velocity is said to be uniform, and is measured by the number of angular units described in a unit of time. By similar reasoning to that already described, if the velocity with which the angle increases be not uniform, so that at the end of the time~$t$ the angle described is $\theta = \phi t$, the angular velocity is~$\phi' t$, or the limit of the ratio~$\dfrac{d\theta}{dt}$.} If we divide equations \Eq{(1)}~and~\Eq{(2)} by~$dt$, we have \[ %[** TN: Signs OK; De Morgan absorbs the - in dx/dt at the bottom of p. 57] \frac{dx}{dt} = r \sin\theta\, \frac{d\theta}{dt}\qquad \frac{dy}{dt} = r \cos\theta\, \frac{d\theta}{dt}; \] these become more nearly true as $dt$~and~$d\theta$ are diminished, so that if for $\dfrac{dx}{dt}$,~etc., the limits of these ratios be substituted, the equations will become rigorously true. But these limits are the velocities of $x$,~$y$, and~$\theta$, the last of which is also~$\dfrac{a}{r}$; hence \begin{alignat*}{2} \text{velocity of~$x$} &= r \sin\theta × \frac{a}{r} &&= a \sin\theta, \\ \text{velocity of~$y$} &= r \cos\theta × \frac{a}{r} &&= a \cos\theta; \end{alignat*} that is, the point~$M$ moves towards~$O$ with a variable velocity, which is always such a part of the velocity of~$P$, as $\sin\theta$~is of unity, or as $PM$~is of~$OB$; and the distance~$PM$ increases, or the point~$N$ moves from~$O$, with a velocity which is such a part of the velocity of~$P$ as $\cos\theta$~is of unity, or as $OM$~is of~$OA$. [The motion of the point~$M$ or the point~$N$ is called in physics a \emph{simple harmonic motion}.] In the language of Leibnitz, the results of the two \index{Leibnitz}% foregoing sections would be expressed thus: If a point move, but not uniformly, it may still be considered as moving uniformly for any infinitely small \index{Infinitely small, the notion of}% \PageSep{60} time; and the velocity with which it moves is the infinitely small space thus described, divided by the infinitely small time. \Subsection{The Method of Fluxions.} The foregoing process contains the method employed \index{Fluxions}% by Newton, known by the name of the \emph{Method \index{Newton}% of Fluxions}. If we suppose $y$ to be any function of~$x$, and that $x$~increases with a given velocity, $y$~will also increase or decrease with a velocity depending: (1)~upon the velocity of~$x$; (2)~upon the function which $y$ is of~$x$. These velocities Newton called the fluxions of $y$~and~$x$, and denoted them by $\dot{y}$~and~$\dot{x}$. Thus, if $y = x^{2}$, and if in the interval of time~$dt$, $x$~becomes $x + dx$, and $y$~becomes $y + dy$, we have $y + dy = (x + dx)^{2}$, and $dy = 2x\, dx + (dx)^{2}$, or $\dfrac{dy}{dt} = 2x\, \dfrac{dx}{dt} + \dfrac{dx}{dt}\, dx$. If we diminish~$dt$, the term $\dfrac{dx}{dt}\, dx$ will diminish without limit, since one factor continually approaches to a given quantity, viz., the velocity of~$x$, and the other diminishes without limit. Hence we obtain the velocity of $y = 2x × \text{the velocity of~$x$}$, or $\dot{y} = 2x\, \dot{x}$, which is used in the method of fluxions instead of $dy = 2x\, dx$ considered in the manner already described. The processes are the same in both methods, since the ratio of the velocities is the limiting ratio of the corresponding increments, or, according to Leibnitz, the ratio of the infinitely small increments. \index{Leibnitz}% We shall hereafter notice the common objection to the Method of Fluxions. \Subsection{Accelerated Motion.} When the velocity of a material point is suddenly \index{Accelerated motion}% \index{Motion!accelerated}% \index{Uniformly accelerated}% increased, an \emph{impulse} is said to be given to it, and the \index{Impulse}% \PageSep{61} magnitude of the impulse or impulsive force is in proportion \index{Force|(}% to the velocity created by it. Thus, an impulse which changes the velocity from $50$ to $70$~feet per~second, is twice as great as one which changes it from $50$ to $60$~feet. When the velocity of the point is altered, not suddenly but continuously, so that before the velocity can change from $50$ to $70$~feet, it goes through all possible intermediate velocities, the point is said to be acted on by an \emph{accelerating force}. \emph{Force} is a name given to that which causes a change in the velocity of a body. It is said to act uniformly, when the velocity acquired by the point in any one interval of time is the same as that acquired in any other interval of equal duration. It is plain that we cannot, by supposing any succession of impulses, however small, and however quickly repeated, arrive at a uniformly accelerated motion; because the length described between any two impulses will be uniformly described, which is inconsistent with the idea of continually accelerated velocity. Nevertheless, by diminishing the magnitude of the impulses, and increasing their number, we may come as near as we please to such a continued motion, in the same way as, by diminishing the magnitudes of the sides of a polygon, and increasing their number, we may approximate as near as we please to a \Typo{continous}{continuous} curve. Let a point, setting out from a state of rest, increase its velocity uniformly, so that in the time~$t$, it may acquire the velocity~$v$---what length will have been described during that time~$t$? Let the time~$t$ and the velocity~$v$ be both divided into $n$~equal parts, each of which is $t'$ and~$v'$, so that $nt' = t$, and $nv' = v$. Let the velocity~$v'$ be communicated to the point at rest; after an interval of~$t'$ let another velocity~$v'$ be \PageSep{62} communicated, so that during the second interval~$t'$ the point has a velocity~$2v'$; during the third interval let the point have the velocity~$3v'$, and so on; so that in the last or $n$\th~interval the point has the velocity~$nv'$. The space described in the first interval is, therefore,~$v't'$; in the second,~$2v't'$; in the third~$3v't'$; and so on, till in the $n$\th~interval it is~$nv't'$. The whole space described is, therefore, \[ v't' + 2v't' + 3v't' + \dots + (n - 1)v't' + nv't'\Add{,} \] or \[ [1 + 2 + 3 \Add{+} \dots + (n - 1) + n]v't' = n · \frac{(n + 1)}{2}\, v't' = \frac{n^{2} v't' + nv't'}{2}. \] In this substitute $v$ for~$nv'$, and $t$ for~$nt'$, which gives for the space described $\frac{1}{2}v(t + t')$. The smaller we suppose~$t'$, the more nearly will this approach to~$\frac{1}{2}vt$. But the smaller we suppose~$t'$, the greater must be~$n$, the number of parts into which $t$~is divided; and the more nearly do we render the motion of the point uniformly accelerated. Hence the limit to which we approximate by diminishing~$t'$ without limit, is the length described in the time~$t$ by a uniformly accelerated velocity, which shall increase from~$0$ to~$v$ in that time. This is~$\frac{1}{2}vt$, or half the length which would have been described by the velocity~$v$ continued uniformly from the beginning of the motion. It is usual to measure the accelerating force by the \index{Accelerating force}% velocity acquired in one second. Let this be~$g$; then since the same velocity is acquired in every other second, the velocity acquired in $t$~seconds will be~$gt$, or $v = gt$. Hence the space described is $\frac{1}{2}gt × t$, or~$\frac{1}{2}gt^{2}$. If the point, instead of being at rest at the beginning of the acceleration, had had the velocity~$a$, the lengths \PageSep{63} described in the successive intervals would have been $at' + v't'$, $at' + 2v't'$, etc.; so that to the space described by the accelerated motion would have been added~$nat'$, or~$at$, and the whole length would have been $at + \frac{1}{2}gt^{2}$. By similar reasoning, had the force been a uniformly \emph{retarding} force, that is, one which diminished \index{Force|)}% the initial velocity~$a$ equally in equal times, the length described in the time~$t$ would have been $at - \frac{1}{2}gt^{2}$. Now let the point move in such a way, that the velocity is accelerated or retarded, but not uniformly; that is, in different times of equal duration, let different velocities be lost or gained. For example, let the point, setting out from a state of rest, move in such a \Figure{9} way that the number of inches passed over in $t$~seconds is always~$t^{3}$. Here $\phi t = t^{3}$, and the velocity acquired by the body at the end of the time~$t$, is the coefficient of~$dt$ in $(t + dt)^{3}$, or $3t^{2}$~inches per~second. Let the point (\Fig{9}) be at~$A$ at the end of the time~$t$; and let $AB$,~$BC$, $CD$,~etc., be lengths described in successive equal intervals of time, each of which is~$dt$. Then the velocities at $A$,~$B$,~$C$,~etc., are $3t^{2}$, $3(t + dt)^{2}$, $3(t + 2\, dt)^{3}$, etc., and the lengths $AB$,~$BC$, $CD$,~etc., are $(t + dt)^{3} - t^{3}$, $(t + 2\, dt)^{2} - (t + dt)^{3}$, $(t + 3\, dt)^{3} - (t + 2\, dt)^{3}$, etc. \[ \ArrayCompress \begin{array}{cl} \ColHead{VELOCITY AT} & \\ A & 3t^{2}\Add{,} \\ B & 3t^{2} + \Z6t\, dt + \Z3(dt)^{2}\Add{,} \\ C & 3t^{2} + 12t\, dt + 12(dt)^{2}\Add{,} \\ \PageSep{64} \ColHead{LENGTH OF} & \\ AB & 3t^{2}\, dt + \Z3t(dt)^{2} + \Z\Z(dt)^{3}\Add{,} \\ BC & 3t^{2}\, dt + \Z9t(dt)^{2} + \Z 7(dt)^{3}\Add{,} \\ CD & 3t^{2}\, dt + 15t(dt)^{2} + 19(dt)^{3}\Add{.} \end{array} \] If we could, without error, reject the terms containing~$(dt)^{2}$ in the velocities, and those containing~$(dt)^{3}$ in the lengths, we should then reduce the motion of the point to the case already considered, the initial velocity being~$3t^{2}$, and the accelerating force~$6t$. For we have already shown that $a$~being the initial velocity, and $g$~the accelerating force, the space described in the time~$t$ is $at + \frac{1}{2}gt^{2}$. Hence, $3t^{2}$~being the initial velocity, and $6t$~the accelerating force, the space in the time~$dt$ is $3t^{2}\, dt + 3t(dt)^{2}$, which is the same as~$AB$ after $(dt)^{3}$~is rejected. The velocity acquired is~$gt$, and the whole velocity is, therefore, $a + gt$, or making the same substitutions $3t^{2} + 6t\, dt$. This is the velocity at~$B$, after the term~$3(dt)^{2}$ is rejected. Again, the velocity being $3t^{2} + 6t\, dt$, and the force~$6t$, the space described in the time~$dt$ is $(3t^{2} + 6t\, dt)\, dt + 3t(dt)^{2}$, or $3t^{2}\, dt + 9t(dt)^{2}$. This is what the space~$BC$ becomes after $7(dt)^{3}$~is rejected. The velocity acquired is~$6t\, dt$; and the whole velocity is $3t^{2} + 6t\, dt + 6t\, dt$, or $3t^{2} + 12t\, dt$; which is the velocity at~$C$ after $12(dt)^{2}$~is rejected. But as the terms involving $(dt)^{2}$ in the velocities, etc., cannot be rejected without error, the above supposition of a uniform force cannot be made. Nevertheless, as we may take $dt$ so small that these terms shall be as small parts as we please of those which precede, the results of the erroneous and correct suppositions may be brought as near to equality as we please; hence we conclude, that though there is no force, which, continued uniformly, would preserve \PageSep{65} the motion of the point~$A$, so that $OA$~should always be~$t^{2}$ in inches, yet an interval of time may be taken so small, that the length actually described by~$A$ in that time, and the one which would be described if the force~$6t$ were continued uniformly, shall have a ratio as near to equality as we please. Hence, on a principle similar to that by which we called~$3t^{3}$ the velocity at~$A$, though, in truth, no space, however small, is described with that velocity, we call~$6t$ the accelerating force at~$A$. And it must be observed that $6t$~is the differential coefficient of~$3t^{2}$, or the coefficient of~$dt$, in the development of~$3(t + dt)^{2}$. Generally, let the point move so that the length described in any time~$t$ is~$\phi t$. Hence the length described at the end of the time $t + dt$ is $\phi(t + dt)$, and that described in the interval~$dt$ is $\phi(t + dt) - \phi t$, or \[ \phi' t\, dt + \phi'' t\, \frac{(dt)^{2}}{2} + \phi''' t\, \frac{(dt)^{3}}{2·3} + \etc.\Add{,} \] in which $dt$ may be taken so small, that either of the first two terms shall contain the aggregate of all the rest, as often as we please. These two first terms are $\phi' t\, dt + \frac{1}{2}\phi'' t (dt)^{2}$, and represent the length described during~$dt$, with a uniform velocity~$\phi' t$, and an accelerating force~$\phi'' t$. The interval~$dt$ may then generally be taken so small, that this supposition shall represent the motion during that interval as nearly as we please. \Subsection{Limiting Ratios of Magnitudes that Increase Without Limit.} We have hitherto considered the limiting ratio of \index{Increase without limit|EtSeq}% \index{Limiting ratios|EtSeq}% \index{Ratios, limiting|EtSeq}% quantities only as to their state of \emph{decrease}: we now proceed to some cases in which the limiting ratio of different magnitudes which \emph{increase} without limit is investigated. \PageSep{66} It is easy to show that the increase of two magnitudes may cause a decrease of their ratio; so that, as the two increase without limit, their ratio may diminish without limit. The limit of any ratio may be found by rejecting any terms or aggregate of terms~($Q$) which are connected with another term~($P$) by the sign of addition or subtraction, provided that by increasing~$x$, $Q$~may be made as small a part of~$P$ as we please. For example, to find the limit of $\dfrac{x^{2} + 2x + 3}{2x^{2} + 5x}$, when $x$~is increased without limit. By increasing~$x$ we can, as will be shown immediately, cause $2x + 3$ and~$5x$ to be contained in $x^{2}$ and~$2x^{2}$, as often as we please; rejecting these terms, we have $\dfrac{x^{2}}{2x^{2}}$, or~$\frac{1}{2}$, for the limit. The demonstration is as follows: Divide both numerator and denominator by~$x^{2}$, which gives $1 + \dfrac{2}{x} + \dfrac{3}{x^{2}}$, and $2 + \dfrac{5}{x}$, for the numerator and denominator of a fraction equal in value to the one proposed. These can be brought as near as we please to $1$~and~$2$ by making $x$ sufficiently great, or $\dfrac{1}{x}$~sufficiently small; and, consequently, their ratio can be brought as near as we please to~$\dfrac{1}{2}$. We will now prove the following: That in any series of decreasing powers of~$x$, any one term will, if $x$~be taken sufficiently great, contain the aggregate of all which follow, as many times as we please. Take, for example, \[ % [** TN: On two lines in the original] ax^{m} + bx^{m-1} + cx^{m-2} + \dots + px + q + \frac{r}{x} + \frac{s}{x^{2}} + \etc. \] \PageSep{67} The ratio of the several terms will not be altered if we divide the whole by~$x^{m}$, which gives \[ a + \frac{b}{x} + \frac{c}{x^{2}} + \dots + \frac{p}{x^{m-1}} + \frac{q}{x^{m}} + \frac{r}{x^{m+1}} + \frac{s}{x^{m+2}} + \etc. \] It has been shown that by taking $\dfrac{1}{x}$ sufficiently small, that is, by taking $x$ sufficiently great, any term of this series may be made to contain the aggregate of the succeeding terms, as often as we please; which relation is not altered if we multiply every term by~$x^{m}$, and so restore the original series. It follows from this, that $\dfrac{(x + 1)^{m}}{x^{m}}$ has unity for its limit when $x$~is increased without limit. For $(x + 1)^{m}$ is $x^{m} + mx^{m-1} + \etc.$, in which $x^{m}$~can be made as great as we please with respect to the rest of the series. Hence $\dfrac{(x + 1)^{m}}{x^{m}} = 1 + \dfrac{mx^{m-1} + \etc.}{x^{m}}$, the numerator of which last fraction decreases indefinitely as compared with its denominator. In a similar way it may be shown that the limit of $\dfrac{x^{m}}{(x + 1)^{m+1} - x^{m+1}}$, when $x$~is increased, is~$\dfrac{1}{m + 1}$. For since $(x + 1)^{m+1} = x^{m+1} + (m + 1)x^{m} + \frac{1}{2}(m + 1)m x^{m-1} + \etc.$, this fraction is \[ \frac{x^{m}}{(m + 1)x^{m} + \frac{1}{2}(m + 1)m x^{m-1} + \etc.} \] in which the first term of the denominator may be made to contain all the rest as often as we please; that is, if the fraction be written thus, $\dfrac{x^{m}}{(m + 1)x^{m} + A}$, $A$~can be made as small a part of~$(m + 1)x^{m}$ as we \PageSep{68} please. Hence this fraction can, by a sufficient increase of~$x$, be brought as near as we please to $\dfrac{x^{m}}{(m + 1)x^{m}}$, or~$\dfrac{1}{m + 1}$. A similar proposition may be shown of the fraction $\dfrac{(x + b)^{m}}{(x + a)^{m+1} - x^{m+1}}$, which may be immediately reduced to the form $\dfrac{x^{m} + B}{(m + 1)ax^{m} + A}$, where $x$~may be taken so great that $x^{m}$~shall contain $A$~and~$B$ any number of times. We will now consider the sums of $x$~terms of the following series, each of which may evidently be made as great as we please, by taking a sufficient number of its terms, \begin{alignat*}{7} &1 &&+ 2 &&+ 3 &&+ 4 &&+ \dots &&+ \; x - 1 &&+ x\Add{,} \tag*{(1)} \\ &1^{2} &&+ 2^{2} &&+ 3^{2} &&+ 4^{2} &&+ \dots &&+ (x - 1)^{2} &&+ x^{2}\Add{,} \tag*{(2)} \displaybreak[0]\\ &1^{3} &&+ 2^{3} &&+ 3^{3} &&+ 4^{3} &&+ \dots &&+ (x - 1)^{3} &&+ x^{3}\Add{,} \tag*{(3)} \\ \DotRow{14} \displaybreak[0]\\ &1^{m} &&+ 2^{m} &&+ 3^{m} &&+ 4^{m} &&+ \dots &&+ (x - 1)^{m} &&+ x^{m}\Add{.} \tag*{($m$)} \end{alignat*} We propose to inquire what is the limiting ratio of any one of these series to the last term of the succeeding one; that is, to what do the ratios of $(1 + 2 + \dots + x)$ to~$x^{2}$, of $(1^{2} + 2^{2}\Add{+} \dots + x^{2})$ to~$x^{3}$, etc., approach, when $x$~is increased without limit. To give an idea of the method of increase of these series, we shall first show that $x$~may be taken so great, that the last term of each series shall be as small a part as we please of the sum of all those which precede. To simplify the symbols, let us take the third series $1^{3} + 2^{3} + \dots + x^{3}$, in which we are to show that $x^{3}$~may be made less than any given part\Typo{.}{,} \PageSep{69} say one thousandth, of the sum of those which precede, or of $1^{3} + 2^{3} \Add{+} \dots + (x - 1)^{3}$. First, $x$~may be taken so great that $x^{3}$ and $(x - 1000)^{3}$ shall have a ratio as near to equality as we please. For the ratio of these quantities being the same as that of $1$ to $\left(1 - \dfrac{1000}{x}\right)^{3}$, and $\dfrac{1000}{x}$ being as small as we please if $x$ may be as great as we please, it follows that $1 - \dfrac{1000}{x}$, and, consequently, $\left(1 - \dfrac{1000}{x}\right)^{3}$ may be made as near to unity as we please, or the ratio of $1$ to $\left(1 - \dfrac{1000}{x}\right)^{3}$, may be brought as near as we please to that of $1$ to~$1$, or a ratio of equality. But this ratio is that of $x^{3}$ to~$(x - 1000)^{3}$. Similarly the ratios of $x^{3}$ to~$(x - 999)^{3}$, of $x^{3}$ to~$(x - 998)^{3}$, etc., up to the ratio of $x^{3}$ to~$(x - 1)^{3}$ may be made as near as we please to ratios of equality; there being one thousand in all. If, then, $(x - 1)^{3} = \alpha x^{3}$, $(x - 2)^{3} = \beta x^{3}$, etc., up to $(x - 1000)^{3} = \omega x^{3}$, $x$~can be taken so great that each of the fractions $\alpha$,~$\beta$,~etc., shall be as near to unity, or $\alpha + \beta + \dots + \omega$ as near\footnote {Observe that this conclusion depends upon the \emph{number} of quantities $\alpha$,~$\beta$,~etc., being \emph{determinate}. If there be \emph{ten} quantities, each of which can be brought as near to unity as we please, their sum can be brought as near to~$10$ as we please; for, take any fraction~$A$, and make each of those quantities differ from unity by less than the tenth part of~$A$, then will the sum differ from~$10$ by less than~$A$. This argument fails, if the number of quantities be unlimited.} to~$1000$ as we please. Hence %[** TN: In-line in the original] \[ \frac{1}{\alpha + \beta + \dots + \omega}\Add{,} \] which is \[ \frac{x^{3}}{\alpha x^{3} + \beta x^{3} + \dots + \omega x^{3}}, \] or \[ \frac{x^{3}}{(x - 1)^{3} + (x - 2)^{2} + \dots + (x - 1000)^{3}}, \] \PageSep{70} can be brought as near to~$\dfrac{1}{1000}$ as we please; and by the same reasoning, the fraction \[ \frac{x^{3}}{(x - 1)^{3} + \dots + (x - 1001)^{3}} \] may be brought as near to~$\dfrac{1}{1001}$ as we please; that is, may be made less than~$\dfrac{1}{1000}$. Still more then may \[ \frac{x^{3}}{(x - 1)^{3} + \dots + (x - 1001)^{3} + \dots + 2^{3} + 1^{3}} \] be made less than~$\dfrac{1}{1000}$, or $x^{3}$~may be less than the thousandth part of the sum of all the preceding terms. In the same way it may be shown that a term may be taken in any one of the series, which shall be less than any given part of the sum of all the preceding terms. It is also true that the difference of any two succeeding terms may be made as small a part of either as we please. For $(x + 1)^{m} - x^{m}$, when developed, will only contain exponents less than~$m$, being $mx^{m-1} + m\dfrac{m - 1}{2}\, x^{m-2} + \etc.$; and we have shown (\PageRef{66}) that the sum of such a series may be made less than any given part of~$x^{m}$. It is also evident that, whatever number of terms we may sum, if a sufficient number of succeeding terms be taken, the sum of the latter shall exceed that of the former in any ratio we please. Let there be a series of fractions \[ \frac{a}{pa + b},\quad \frac{a'}{pa' + b'},\quad \frac{a''}{pa'' + b''},\quad \etc., \] in which $a$,~$a'$,~etc., $b$,~$b'$,~etc., increase without limit; but in which the ratio of $b$~to~$a$, $b'$~to~$a'$, etc., diminishes without limit. If it be allowable to begin by \PageSep{71} supposing $b$~as small as we please with respect to~$a$, or $\dfrac{b}{a}$~as small as we please, the first, and all the succeeding fractions, will be as near as we please to~$\dfrac{1}{p}$, which is evident from the equations \[ \frac{a}{pa + b} = \frac{1}{p + \dfrac{b}{a}},\quad \frac{a'}{pa' + b'} = \frac{1}{p + \dfrac{b'}{a'}},\quad \etc. \] Form a new fraction by summing the numerators and denominators of the preceding, such as \[ \frac{a + a' + a'' + \etc.} {p(a + a' + a'' + \etc.) + b + b' + b'' + \etc.\Typo{,}{}}, \] the \emph{etc.}\ extending to any given number of terms. This may also be brought as near to~$\dfrac{1}{p}$ as we please. For this fraction is the same as \[ \text{$1$~divided by } p + \frac{b + b' + \etc.}{a + a' + \etc.}; \] and it can be shown\footnote {See \Title{Study of Mathematics} (Reprint Edition, Chicago: The Open Court Publishing Co.), page~270.} that \[ \frac{b + b' + \etc.}{a + a' + \etc.} \] must lie between the least and greatest of the fractions $\dfrac{b}{a}$,~$\dfrac{b'}{a'}$,~etc. If, then, each of these latter fractions can be made as small as we please, so also can \[ \frac{b + b' + \etc.}{a + a' + \etc.}. \] No difference will be made in this result, if we use the following fraction, \[ \frac{A + (a + a' + a'' + \etc.)} {B + p(a + a' + a'' + \etc.) + b + b' + b'' + \etc.}\Add{,} \Tag{(1)} \] \PageSep{72} $A$~and~$B$ being given quantities; provided that we can take a number of the original fractions sufficient to make $a + a' + a'' + \etc.$, as great as we please, compared with $A$~and~$B$. This will appear on dividing the numerator and denominator of~\Eq{(1)} by $a + a' + a'' + \etc$. Let the fractions be \begin{gather*} \frac{(x + 1)^{3}}{(x + 1)^{4} - x^{4}},\quad \frac{(x + 2)^{3}}{(x + 2)^{4} - (x + 1)^{4}}, \\ \frac{(x + 3)^{3}}{(x + 3)^{4} - (x + 2)^{4}},\quad \etc. \end{gather*} The first of which, or $\dfrac{(x + 1)^{3}}{4x^{3} + \etc.}$ may, as we have shown, be within any given difference of~$\dfrac{1}{4}$, and the others still nearer, by taking a value of~$x$ sufficiently great. Let us suppose each of these fractions to be within $\dfrac{1}{100000}$ of~$\dfrac{1}{4}$. The fraction formed by summing the numerators and denominators of these fractions ($n$~in number) will be within the same degree of nearness to~$\frac{1}{4}$. But this is \[ \frac{(x + 1)^{3} + (x + 2)^{3} + \dots + (x + n)^{3}}{(x + 1)^{4} - x^{4}}\Add{,} \Tag{(2)} \] all the terms of the denominator disappearing, except two from the first and last. If, then, we add~$x^{4}$ to the denominator, and $1^{3} + 2^{3} + 3^{3} \Add{+} \dots + x^{3}$ to the numerator, we can still take $n$ so great that $(x + 1)^{3} + \dots + (x + n)^{3}$ shall contain $1^{3} + \dots + x^{3}$ as often as we please, and that $(x + n)^{4} - x^{4}$ shall contain~$x^{4}$ in the same manner. To prove the latter, observe that the ratio of $(x + n)^{4} - x^{4}$ to~$x^{4}$ being $\left(1 + \dfrac{n}{x}\right)^{4}$, can be made as great as we please, if it be permitted \PageSep{73} to take for~$n$ a number containing~$x$ as often as we please. Hence, by the preceding reasoning, the fraction, with its numerator and denominator thus increased, or \[ \frac{1^{3} + 2^{3} + 3^{3} + \dots + x^{3} + (x + 1)^{3} + \dots + (x + n)^{3}} {(x + n)^{4}} \Tag{(3)} \] may be brought to lie within the same degree of nearness to~$\frac{1}{4}$ as~\Eq{(2)}; and since this degree of nearness could be named at pleasure, it follows that \Eq{(3)}~can be brought as near to~$\frac{1}{4}$ as we please. Hence the limit of the ratio of $(1^{3} + 2^{3} + \dots + x^{3})$ to~$x^{4}$, as $x$~is increased without limit, is~$\frac{1}{4}$; and, in a similar manner, it may be proved that the limit of the ratio of $(1^{m} + 2^{m} + \dots + x^{m})$ to~$x^{m+1}$ is the same as that of $\dfrac{(x + 1)^{m}}{(x + 1)^{m+1} - x^{m+1}}$ or $\dfrac{1}{m + 1}$. This result will be of use when we come to the first principles of the integral calculus. It may also \index{Integral Calculus}% be noticed that the limits of the ratios which $x\, \dfrac{x - 1}{2}$, $x\, \dfrac{x - 1}{2}\, \dfrac{x - 2}{3}$, etc., bear to $x^{2}$,~$x^{3}$, etc., are severally $\dfrac{1}{2}$, $\dfrac{1}{2·3}$, etc.; the limit being that to which the ratios approximate as $x$~increases without limit. For $x\, \dfrac{x - 1}{2} ÷ x^{2} = \dfrac{x - 1}{2x}$, $x\, \dfrac{x - 1}{2}\, \dfrac{x - 2}{3} ÷ x^{3} = \dfrac{x - 1}{2x}\, \dfrac{x - 2}{3x}$, etc., and the limits of $\dfrac{x - 1}{2}$, $\dfrac{x - 2}{3}$, are severally equal to unity. We now resume the elementary principles of the Differential Calculus. \PageSep{74} \Subsection[Recapitulation of Results Reached in the Theory of Functions.] {Recapitulation of Results.} The following is a recapitulation of the principal results which have hitherto been noticed in the general theory of functions: \index{Functions!recapitulation of results in the theory of}% (1) That if in the equation $y = \phi(x)$, the variable~$x$ receives an increment~$dx$, $y$~is increased by the series \[ \phi' x\, dx + \phi'' x\, \frac{(dx)^{2}}{2} + \phi''' x\, \frac{(dx)^{3}}{2·3} + \etc. \] (2) That $\phi'' x$ is derived in the same manner from~$\phi' x$, that $\phi' x$~is from~$\phi x$; viz., that in like manner as $\phi' x$~is the coefficient of~$dx$ in the development of $\phi(x + dx)$, so $\phi'' x$~is the coefficient of~$dx$ in the development of $\phi'(x + dx)$; similarly $\phi''' x$~is the coefficient of~$dx$ in the development of~$\phi''(x + dx)$, and so on. (3) That $\phi' x$ is the limit of~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$, or the quantity to which the latter will approach, and to which it may be brought as near as we please, when $dx$~is diminished. It is called the differential coefficient of~$y$. (4) That in every case which occurs in practice, $dx$~may be taken so small, that any term of the series above written may be made to contain the aggregate of those which follow, as often as we please; whence, though $\phi' x\, dx$~is not the actual increment produced by changing~$x$ into~$x + dx$ in the function~$\phi x$, yet, by taking $dx$ sufficiently small, it may be brought as near as we please to a ratio of equality with the actual increment. \Subsection[Approximations by the Differential Calculus.] {Approximations.} The last of the above-mentioned principles is of the greatest utility, since, by means of it, $\phi' x\, dx$~may \PageSep{75} \index{Errors, in the valuation of quantities}% be made as nearly as we please the actual increment; and it will generally happen in practice, that $\phi' x\, dx$ may be used for the increment of~$\phi x$ without sensible error; that is, if in~$\phi x$, $x$~be changed into $x + dx$, $dx$~being very small, $\phi x$~is changed into $\phi x + \phi' x\, dx$, very nearly. Suppose that $x$ being the correct value of the variable, $x + h$ and $x + k$ have been successively substituted for it, or the errors $h$~and~$k$ have been committed in the valuation of~$x$, $h$~and~$k$ being very small. Hence $\phi(x + h)$ and $\phi(x + k)$ will be erroneously used for~$\phi x$. But these are nearly $\phi x + \phi' x\, h$ and $\phi x + \phi' x\, k$, and the errors committed in taking~$\phi x$ are $\phi' x\, h$ and $\phi' x\, k$, very nearly. These last are in the proportion of $h$ to~$k$, and hence results a proposition of the utmost importance in every practical application of mathematics, viz., that if two different, but small, errors be committed in the valuation of any quantity, the errors arising therefrom at the end of any process, in which both the supposed values of~$x$ are successively adopted, are very nearly in the proportion of the errors committed at the beginning. For example, let there be a right-angled triangle, whose base is~$3$, and whose other side should be~$4$, so that the hypothenuse should be $\sqrt{3^{2} + 4^{2}}$ or~$5$. But suppose that the other side has been twice erroneously measured, the first measurement giving $4.001$, and the second $4.002$, the errors being $.001$ and~$.002$. The two values of the hypothenuse thus obtained are \[ \sqrt{3^{2} + 4.001^{2}}, \quad\text{or}\quad \sqrt{25.008001}, \] and \[ \sqrt{3^{2} + 4.002^{2}}, \quad\text{or}\quad \sqrt{25.016004}, \] which are very nearly $5.0008$ and $5.0016$. The errors of the hypothenuse are then $.0008$ and $.0016$ nearly; and these last are in the proportion of $.001$ and~$.002$. \PageSep{76} It also follows, that if $x$~increase by successive equal steps, any function of~$x$ will, for a few steps, increase so nearly in the same manner, that the supposition of such an increase will not be materially wrong. For, if $h$,~$2h$,~$3h$, etc., be successive small increments given to~$x$, the successive increments of~$\phi x$ will be $\phi' x\, h$, $\phi' x\, 2h$, $\phi' x\, 3h$,~etc.\ nearly; which being proportional to $h$,~$2h$,~$3h$, etc., the increase of the function is nearly doubled, trebled, etc., if the increase of~$x$ be doubled, trebled,~etc. This result may be rendered conspicuous by reference to any astronomical ephemeris, in which the \index{Astronomical ephemeris}% positions of a heavenly body are given from day to day. The intervals of time at which the positions are given differ by $24$~hours, or nearly $\frac{1}{365}$\th~part of the whole year. And even for this interval, though it can hardly be called \emph{small} in an astronomical point of view, the increments or decrements will be found so nearly the same for four or five days together, as to enable the student to form an idea how much more near they would be to equality, if the interval had been less, say one hour instead of twenty-four. For example, the sun's longitude on the following days at noon is written \index{Sun's longitude}% underneath, with the increments from day to day. \[ \ArrayCompress \begin{array}{c*{2}{>{\ }c}c} \ColHead[September]{1834 \\ September} & \ColHead[Sun's longitude]{Sun's longitude \\ at noon.} & \ColHead{Increments.} & \ColHead[Proportion which the differences]{Proportion which the differences \\ of the increments bear to the \\ whole increments.} \\ % 1\text{st} & 158\rlap{$°$}\ \ 30\rlap{$'$}\ \ 35\rlap{$''$} & \Low{58\rlap{$'$}\ \Z9\rlap{$''$}} & \\ 2\text{nd} & 159\ \ 28\ \ 44 & \Low{58\ 12} & \frac{3}{3489} \\ 3\text{rd} & 160\ \ 26\ \ 56 & \Low{58\ 13} & \frac{1}{3492} \\ 4\text{th} & 161\ \ 25\ \ \Z9 & \Low{58\ 14} & \frac{1}{3493} \\ 5\text{th} & 162\ \ 23\ \ 23 \end{array} \] The sun's longitude is a function of the time; that is, the number of years and days from a given epoch being given, and called~$x$, the sun's longitude can be \PageSep{77} found by an algebraical expression which may be called~$\phi x$. If we date from the first of January,~1834, $x$~is~$.666$, which is the decimal part of a year between the first days of January and September. The increment is one day, or nearly $.0027$~of a year. Here $x$~is successively made equal to~$.666$, $.666 + 0027$, $.666 + 2 × .0027$, etc.; and the intervals of the corresponding values of~$\phi x$, if we consider only minutes, are the same; but if we take in the seconds, they differ from one another, though only by very small parts of themselves, as the last column shows. \Subsection[Solution of Equations by the Differential Calculus.] {Solution of Equations.} This property is also used\footnote {See \Title{Study of Mathematics} (Reprint Edition, Chicago: The Open Court Publishing Co., 1898), page~169 et~seq.} in finding logarithms \index{Equations, solution of}% intermediate to those given in the tables; and may be applied to find a nearer solution to an equation, than one already found. For example, suppose it required to find the value of~$x$ in the equation $\phi x = 0$, $a$~being a near approximation to the required value. Let $a + h$ be the real value, in which $h$~will be a small quantity. It follows that $\phi(a + h) = 0$, or, which is nearly true, $\phi a + \phi' a\, h = 0$. Hence the real value of~$h$ is nearly~$-\dfrac{\phi a}{\phi' a}$, or the value $a - \dfrac{\phi a}{\phi' a}$ is a nearer approximation to the value of~$x$. For example, let $x^{2} + x - 4 = 0$ be the equation. Here $\phi x = x^{2} + x - 4$, and $\phi(x + h) = (x + h)^{2} + x + h - 4 = x^{2} + x - 4 + (2x + 1)h + h^{2}$; so that $\phi' x = 2x + 1$. A near value of~$x$ is~$1.57$; let this be~$a$. Then $\phi a = .0349$, and $\phi' a = 4.14$. Hence $-\dfrac{\phi a}{\phi' a} = -.00843$. Hence $1.57 - .00843$, or~$1.56157$, is a nearer value of~$x$. If \PageSep{78} we proceed in the same way with~$1.5616$, we shall find a still nearer value of~$x$, viz., $1.561553$. We have here chosen an equation of the second degree, in order that the student may be able to verify the result in the common way; it is, however, obvious that the same method may be applied to equations of higher degrees, and even to those which are not to be treated by common algebraical method, such as $\tan x = ax$. \Subsection{Partial and Total Differentials.} We have already observed, that in a function of \index{Differentials!partial|EtSeq}% \index{Differentials!total|EtSeq}% \index{Partial!differentials|EtSeq}% \index{Total!differentials|EtSeq}% more quantities than one, those only are mentioned which are considered as variable; so that all which we have said upon functions of one variable, applies \index{Functions!of several variables|EtSeq}% equally to functions of several variables, so far as a \index{Variables!functions of several|EtSeq}% change in one only is concerned. Take for example $x^{2} y + 2xy^{3}$. If $x$~be changed into $x + dx$, $y$~remaining the same, this function is increased by $2xy\, dx + 2y^{3}\, dx + \etc.$, in which, as in \PageRef{29}, no terms are contained in the~\emph{etc.}\ except those which, by diminishing~$dx$, can be made to bear as small a proportion as we please to the first terms. Again, if $y$~be changed into $y + dy$, $x$~remaining the same, the function receives the increment $x^{2}\, dy + 6xy^{2}\, dy + \etc.$; and if $x$~be changed into $x + dx$, $y$~being at the same time changed into $y + dy$, the increment of the function is $(2xy + 2y^{3})\, dx + (x^{2} + 6xy^{2})\, dy + \etc$. If, then, $u = x^{2} y + 2xy^{3}$, and $du$~denote the increment of~$u$, we have the three following equations, answering to the various suppositions above mentioned, \\ (1) when $x$~only varies, \[ du = (2xy + 2y^{3})\, dx + \etc. \] \PageSep{79} (2) when $y$~only varies, \[ du = (x^{2} + 6xy^{2})\, dy + \etc. \] (3) when both $x$~and~$y$ vary, \[ du = (2xy + 2y^{3})\, dx + (x^{2} + 6xy^{2})\, dy + \etc. \] in which, however, it must be remembered, that $du$~does not stand for the same thing in any two of the three equations: it is true that it always represents an increment of~$u$, but as far as we have yet gone, we have used it indifferently, whether the increment of~$u$ was the result of a change in $x$~only, or $y$~only, or both together. To distinguish the different increments of~$u$, we must therefore seek an additional notation, which, \index{Calculus, notation of|EtSeq}% \index{Notation!of the Differential Calculus|EtSeq}% without sacrificing the~$du$ that serves to remind us that it was $u$ which received an increment, may also point out from what supposition the increment arose. For this purpose we might use $d_{x}u$~and~$d_{y}u$, and $d_{x,y}u$, to distinguish the three; and this will appear to the learner more simple than the one in common use, which we shall proceed to explain. We must, however, remind the student, that though in matters of reasoning, he has a right to expect a solution of every difficulty, in all that relates to notation, he must trust entirely to his instructor; since he cannot judge between the convenience or inconvenience of two symbols without a degree of experience which he evidently cannot have had. Instead of the notation above described, the increments arising from a change in $x$ and~$y$ are severally denoted by $\dfrac{du}{dx}\, dx$ and $\dfrac{du}{dy}\, dy$, on the following principle: If there be a number of results obtained by the same species of process, but on different suppositions with regard to the quantities \PageSep{80} used; if, for example, $p$~be derived from some supposition with regard to~$a$, in the same manner as are $q$ and~$r$ with regard to $b$~and~$c$, and if it be inconvenient and unsymmetrical to use separate letters $p$,~$q$, and~$r$, for the three results, they may be distinguished by using the same letter~$p$ for all, and writing the three results thus, $\dfrac{p}{a}\, a$, $\dfrac{p}{b}\, b$, $\dfrac{p}{c}\, c$. Each of these, in common algebra, is equal to~$p$, but the letter~$p$ does not stand for the same thing in the three expressions. The first is the~$p$, so to speak, which belongs to~$a$, the second that which belongs to~$b$, the third that which belongs to~$c$. Therefore the numerator of each of the fractions $\dfrac{p}{a}$,~$\dfrac{p}{b}$, and~$\dfrac{p}{c}$, must never be separated from its denominator, because the value of the former depends, in part, upon the latter; and one~$p$ cannot be distinguished from another without its denominator. The numerator by itself only indicates what operation is to be performed, and on what quantity; the denominator shows what quantity is to be made use of in performing it. Neither are we allowed to say that $\dfrac{p}{a}$ divided by~$\dfrac{p}{b}$ is~$\dfrac{b}{a}$; for this supposes that $p$~means the same thing in both quantities. In the expressions $\dfrac{du}{dx}\, dx$, and $\dfrac{du}{dy}\, dy$, each denotes that $u$~has received an increment; but the first points out that~$x$, and the second that~$y$, was supposed to increase, in order to produce that increment; while $du$~by itself, or sometimes $d.u$, is employed to express the increment derived from both suppositions at once. And since, as we have already remarked, it is not the ratios of the increments themselves, but the limits of those ratios, which are the objects of investigation in \PageSep{81} the Differential Calculus, here, as in \PageRef{28}, $\dfrac{du}{dx}\, dx$, and $\dfrac{du}{dy}\, dy$, are generally considered as representing those terms which are of use in obtaining the limiting ratios, and do not include those terms, which, from \index{Limiting ratios}% \index{Ratios, limiting}% their containing higher powers of $dx$~or~$dy$ than the first, may be made as small as we please with respect to $dx$~or~$dy$. Hence in the example just given, where $u = x^{2} y + 2xy^{3}$, we have \begin{align*} &\dfrac{du}{dx}\, dx = (2xy + 2y^{3})\, dx, &&\text{or}\quad \frac{du}{dx} = 2xy + 2y^{3}\Add{,} \\ &\dfrac{du}{dy}\, dy = (x^{2} + 6xy^{2})\, dy, &&\text{or}\quad \frac{du}{dy} = x^{2} + 6xy^{2}\Add{,} \\ &du \quad\text{or}\quad d.u = \frac{du}{dx}\, dx + \frac{du}{dy}\,dy. \end{align*} The last equation gives a striking illustration of the method of notation. Treated according to the common rules of algebra, it is $du = du + du$, which is absurd, but which appears rational when we recollect that the second~$du$ arises from a change in $x$~only, the third from a change in $y$~only, and the first from a change in both. The same equation may be proved to be generally true for all functions of $x$~and~$y$, if we bear in mind that no term is retained, or need be retained, as far as the limit is concerned, which, when $dx$~or~$dy$ is diminished, diminishes without limit as compared with them. In using $\dfrac{du}{dx}$ and $\dfrac{du}{dy}$ as differential coefficients of~$u$ with respect to $x$~and~$y$, the objection (\PageRef{27}) against considering these as the limits of the ratios, and not the ratios themselves, does not hold, since the numerator is not to be separated from its denominator. \PageSep{82} Let $u$ be a function of $x$~and~$y$, represented\footnote {The symbol $\phi(x, y)$ must not be confounded with~$\phi(xy)$. The former represents any function of $x$~and~$y$; the latter a function in which $x$~and~$y$ only enter so far as they are contained in their product. The second is therefore a particular case of the first; but the first is not necessarily represented by the second. For example, take the function $xy + \sin xy$, which, though it contains both $x$~and~$y$, yet can only be altered by such a change in $x$~and~$y$ as will alter their product, and if the product be called~$p$, will be $p + \sin p$. This may properly be represented by~$\phi(xy)$; whereas $x + xy^{2}$ cannot be represented in the same way, since other functions besides the product are contained in it.} by~$\phi(x, y)$. It is indifferent whether $x$~and~$y$ be changed \index{Coefficients, differential}% \index{Differential coefficients}% at once into $x + dx$ and $y + dy$, or whether $x$~be first changed into $x + dx$, and $y$~be changed into $y + dy$ in the result. Thus, $x^{2} y + y^{3}$ will become $(x + dx)^{2}(y + dy) + (y + dy)^{3}$ in either case. If $x$~be changed into $x + dx$, $u$~becomes $u + \ux\, dx + \etc.$, (where $\ux$~is what we have called the differential coefficient of~$u$ with respect to~$x$, and is itself a function of $x$~and~$y$; and the corresponding increment of~$u$ is $\ux\, dx + \etc.$)\Add{.} If in this result $y$~be changed into $y + dy$, $u$~will assume the form $u + \uy\, dy + \etc.$, where $\uy$~is the differential coefficient of~$u$ with respect to~$y$; and the increment which $u$~receives will be $\uy + \etc$. Again, when $y$~is changed into $y + dy$, $\ux$,~which is a function of $x$~and~$y$, will assume the form $\ux + p\, dy + \etc.$; and $u + \ux\, dx + \etc.$\ becomes $u + \uy\, dy + \etc. + (\ux + p\, dy + \etc.)\, dx + \etc.$, or $u + \uy\, dy + \ux\, dx + p\, dx\, dy + \etc.$, in which the term $p\, dx\, dy$ is useless in finding the limit. For since $dy$~can be made as small as we please, $p\, dx\, dy$ can be made as small a part of~$p\, dx$ as we please, and therefore can be made as small a part of~$dx$ as we please. Hence on the three suppositions already made, we have the following results: %[** TN: Re-formatted] \begin{itemize} \item[(1)] when $x$~only is changed into~$x + dx$, $u$~receives the increment $\ux\, dx + \etc$.\Add{,} \item[(2)] when $y$~only is changed into~$y + dy$, $u$~receives the increment $\uy\, dy + \etc$.\Add{,} \item[(3)] when $x$~becomes $x + dx$ and $y$~becomes $y + dy$ at once, $u$~receives the increment $\ux\, dx + \uy\, dy + \etc$.\Add{,} \end{itemize} \PageSep{83} the \emph{etc.}\ in each case containing those terms only which can be made as small as we please, with respect to the preceding terms. In the language of Leibnitz, \index{Leibnitz}% we should say that if $x$~and~$y$ receive infinitely small \index{Infinitely small, the notion of}% increments, the sum of the infinitely small increments of~$u$ obtained by making these changes separately, is equal to the infinitely small increment obtained by making them both at once. As before, we may correct this inaccurate method of speaking. The several increments in (1),~(2), and~(3), maybe expressed by $\ux\, dx + P$, $\uy\, dy + Q$, and $\ux\, dx + \uy\, dy + R$; where $P$,~$Q$, and~$R$ can be made such parts of $dx$~or~$dy$ as we please, by taking $dx$~or~$dy$ sufficiently small. The sum of the two first is $\ux\, dx + \uy\, dy + P + Q$, which differs from the third by $P + Q - R$; which, since each of its terms can be made as small a part of $dx$~or~$dy$ as we please, can itself be made less than any given part of $dx$~or~$dy$. This theorem is not confined to functions of two variables only, but may be extended to those of any number whatever. Thus, if $z$~be a function of $p$,~$q$,~$r$, and~$s$, we have \[ d.z \quad\text{or}\quad dz = \frac{dz}{dp}\, dp + \frac{dz}{dq}\, dq + \frac{dz}{dr}\, dr + \frac{dz}{ds}\, ds + \etc. \] in which $\dfrac{dz}{dp}\, dp + \etc.$\ is the increment which a change in $p$~\emph{only} gives to~$z$, and so on. The \emph{etc.}\ is the representative of an infinite series of terms, the aggregate of which diminishes continually with respect to $dp$,~$dq$,~etc., as the latter are diminished, and which, therefore, \PageSep{84} has no effect on the \emph{limit} of the ratio of~$d.z$ to any other quantity. \Subsection[Application of the Theorem for Total Differentials to the Determination of Total Resultant Errors.] {Practical Application of the Preceding Theorem.} We proceed to an important practical use of this \index{Errors, in the valuation of quantities}% theorem. If the increments $dp$,~$dq$,~etc., be small, this last-mentioned equation, (the terms included in the \emph{etc.}\ being omitted,) though not actually true, is sufficiently near the truth for all practical purposes; which renders the proposition, from its simplicity, of the highest use in the applications of mathematics. For if any result be obtained from a set of \textit{data}, no one of which is exactly correct, the error in the result would be a very complicated function of the errors in the \textit{data}, if the latter were considerable. When they are small, the error in the results is very nearly the sum of the errors which would arise from the error in each \textit{datum}, if all the others were correct. For if $p$,~$q$,~$r$, and~$s$, are the \emph{presumed} values of the \textit{data}, which give a certain value~$z$ to the function required to be found; and if $p + dp$, $q + dq$, etc., be the \emph{correct} values of the \textit{data}, the correction of the function~$z$ will be very nearly made, if $z$~be increased by $\dfrac{dz}{dp}\, dp + \dfrac{dz}{dq}\, dq + \dfrac{dz}{dr}\, dr + \dfrac{dz}{ds}\, ds$, being the sum of terms which would arise from each separate error, if each were made in turn by itself. For example: A transit instrument is a telescope \index{Transit instrument}% mounted on an axis, so as to move in the plane of the meridian only, that is, the line joining the centres of the two glasses ought, if the telescope be moved, to pass successively through the zenith and the pole. Hence can be determined the exact time, as shown by a clock, at which any star passes a vertical thread, \PageSep{85} fixed inside the telescope so as apparently to cut the field of view exactly in half, which thread will always cover a part of the meridian, if the telescope be correctly adjusted. In trying to do this, three errors may, and generally will be committed, in some small degree. (1)~The axis of the telescope may not be exactly level; (2)~the ends of the same axis may not be exactly east and west; (3)~the line which joins the centres of the two glasses, instead of being perpendicular to the axis of the telescope, may be inclined to it. If each of these errors were considerable, and the time at which a star passed the thread were observed, the calculation of the time at which the same star passes the real meridian would require complicated formulĉ, and be a work of much labor. But if the errors exist in small quantities only, the calculation is very much simplified by the preceding principle. For, suppose only the first error to exist, and calculate the corresponding error in the time of passing the thread. Next suppose only the second error, and then only the third to exist, and calculate the effect of each separately, all which may be done by simple formulĉ. The effect of all the errors will then be the sum of the effects of each separate error, at least with sufficient accuracy for practical purposes. The formulĉ employed, like the equations in \PageRef{28}, are not actually true in any case, but approach more near to the truth as the errors are diminished. \Subsection{Rules for Differentiation.} In order to give the student an opportunity of exercising \index{Differentiation!of the common functions}% himself in the principles laid down, we will so far anticipate the treatises on the Differential Calculus as to give the results of all the common rules \PageSep{86} for differentiation; that is, assuming $y$~to stand for various functions of~$x$, we find the increment of~$y$ arising from an increment in the value of~$x$, or rather, that term of the increment which contains the first power of~$dx$. This term, in theory, is the only one on which the \emph{limit} of the ratio of the increments depends; in practice, it is sufficiently near to the real increment of~$y$, if the increment of~$x$ be small. {\Loosen (1) $y = x^{m}$, where $m$~is either whole or fractional, \index{Differentiation!of the common functions}% positive or negative; then $dy = mx^{m-1}\, dx$. Thus the increment of~$x^{\efrac{2}{3}}$ or the first term of $(x + dx)^{\efrac{2}{3}} - x^{\efrac{2}{3}}$ is $\frac{2}{3}x^{\efrac{2}{3}-1}\, dx$, or~$\dfrac{2\, dx}{3x^{\efrac{1}{3}}}$. Again, if $y = x^{8}$, $dy = 8x^{7}\, dx$. When the exponent is negative, or when $y = \dfrac{1}{x^{m}}$, $dy = -\dfrac{m\, dx}{x^{m+1}}$, or when $y = x^{-m}$, $dy = -mx^{-m-1}\, dx$, which is according to the rule. The negative sign indicates that an increase in~$x$ decreases the value of~$y$; which, in this case, is evident.} (2) $y = a^{x}$. Here $dy = a^{x}\log a\, dx$ where the logarithm (as is always the case in analysis, except where the contrary is specially mentioned) is the Naperian or hyperbolic logarithm. When $a$~is the base of these logarithms, that is when $a = 2.7182818 = e$, \index{Logarithms}% or when $y = e^{x}$, $dy = e^{x}\, dx$. (3) $y = \log x$ (the Naperian logarithm). Here $dy = \dfrac{dx}{x}$. If $y = \text{common log}~x$, $dy = -.4342944\, \dfrac{dx}{x}$. (4) $y = \sin x$, $dy = \cos x\, dx$; $y = \cos x$, $dy = -\sin x\, dx$; $y = \tan x$, $dy = \dfrac{dx}{\cos^{2} x}$. \Subsection[Illustration of the Rules for Differentiation.] {Illustration of the Preceding Formulĉ.} At the risk of being tedious to some readers, we will proceed to illustrate these formulĉ by examples \PageSep{87} from the tables of logarithms and sines, let $y = \text{common log}~x$. \index{Logarithms}% \index{Sines}% If $x$~be changed into $x + dx$, the real increment of~$y$ is \[ .4342944 \left(\frac{dx}{x} - \tfrac{1}{2}\, \frac{(dx)^{2}}{x^{2}} + \tfrac{1}{3}\, \frac{(dx)^{3}}{x^{3}} - \etc.\right), \] in which the law of continuation is evident. The corresponding series for Naperian logarithms is to be found in \PageRef{20}. From the first term of this the limit of the ratio of $dy$~to~$dx$ can be found; and if $dx$~be \index{Ratio!of two increments}% small, this will represent the increment with sufficient accuracy. Let $x = 1000$, whence $y = \text{common log}~ 1000 =3$; and let $dx = 1$, or let it be required to find the common logarithm of $1000 + 1$, or~$1001$. The first term of the series is therefore $.4342944 × \frac{1}{1000}$, or $.0004343$, taking seven decimal places only. Hence $\log 1001 = \log 1000 + .0004343$ or $3.0004343$ nearly. The tables give $3.0004341$, differing from the former only in the $7$\Chg{th}{\th}~place of decimals. {\Loosen Again, let $y = \sin x$; from which, by \PageRef{20}, as before, if $x$~be increased by~$dx$, $\sin x$~is increased by $\cos x\, dx - \frac{1}{2}\sin x\, (dx)^{2} - \etc.$, of which we take only the first term. Let $x = 16°$, in which case $\sin x = .2756374$, and $\cos x = .9612617$.} Let $dx = 1'$, or, as it is represented in analysis, where the angular unit is that angle whose arc is equal to the radius,\footnote {See \Title{Study of Mathematics} (Chicago; The Open Court Pub. Co.), page~273 et~seq.} $\frac{60}{206265}$. Hence $\sin 16°\, 1' = \sin 16° + .9612617 × \frac{60}{206265} = .2756374 + .0002797 = .2759171$, nearly. The tables give~$.2759170$. These examples may serve to show how nearly the real ratio of two increments approaches to their limit, when the increments themselves are small. \PageSep{88} \Subsection{Differential Coefficients of Differential Coefficients.} When the differential coefficient of a function of~$x$ \index{Coefficients, differential}% \index{Differential coefficients!of higher orders}% \index{Finite differences|EtSeq}% \index{Orders, differential coefficients of higher}% \index{Successive differentiation|EtSeq}% has been found, the result, being a function of~$x$, may be also differentiated, which gives the differential coefficient of the differential coefficient, or, as it is called, the \emph{second} differential coefficient. Similarly the differential coefficient of the second differential coefficient is called the third differential coefficient, and so on. We have already had occasion to notice these successive differential coefficients in \PageRef{22}, where it appears that $\phi' x$~being the first differential coefficient of~$\phi x$, $\phi'' x$~is the coefficient of~$h$ in the development $\phi'(x + h)$, and is therefore the differential coefficient of~$\phi' x$, or what we have called the second differential coefficient of~$\phi x$. Similarly $\phi''' x$~is the third differential coefficient of~$\phi x$. If we were strictly to adhere to our system of notation, we should denote the several differential coefficients of~$\phi x$ or~$y$ by \[ \frac{dy}{dx}\Add{,}\quad \frac{d.\dfrac{dy}{dx}}{dx}\Add{,}\quad \frac{d.\dfrac{d.\frac{dy}{dx}}{dx}}{dx}\Add{,}\quad \etc. \] In order to avoid so cumbrous a system of notation, the following symbols are usually preferred, \[ \frac{dy}{dx}\Add{,}\quad \frac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}\Add{,}\quad \frac{d^{3} y}{dx^{3}}\Add{,}\quad \etc. \] \Subsection{Calculus of Finite Differences. Successive Differentiation.} We proceed to explain the manner in which this \index{Differentiation!successive|EtSeq}% notation is connected with our previous ideas on the subject. \PageSep{89} When in any function of~$x$, an increase is given to~$x$, \index{Differences!calculus of}% which is not supposed to be as small as we please, it is usual to denote it by~$\Delta x$ instead of~$dx$, and the corresponding increment of~$y$ or~$\phi x$, by~$\Delta y$ or~$\Delta\phi x$, instead of~$dy$ or~$d\phi x$. The symbol~$\Delta x$ is called the \emph{difference} of~$x$, being the difference between the value of the variable~$x$, before and after its increase. Let $x$ increase at successive steps by the same difference; that is, let a variable, whose first value is~$x$, successively become $x + \Delta x$, $x + 2\Delta x$, $x + 3\Delta x$, etc., and let the successive values of~$\phi x$ corresponding to these values of~$x$ be $y$,~$y_{1}$, $y_{2}$,~$y_{3}$,~etc.; that is, $\phi x$~is called~$y$, $\phi(x + \Delta x)$ is~$y_{1}$, $\phi(x + 2\Delta x)$ is~$y_{2}$, etc., and, generally, $\phi(x + m\Delta x)$ is~$y_{m}$. Then, by our previous definition $y_{1} - y$ is~$\Delta y$, $y_{2} - y_{1}$ is~$\Delta y_{1}$, $y_{3} - y_{2}$ is~$\Delta y_{2}$, etc., the letter~$\Delta$ before a quantity always denoting the increment it would receive if $x + \Delta x$ were substituted for~$x$. Thus $y_{3}$ or $\phi(x + 3\Delta x)$ becomes $\phi(x + \Delta x + 3\Delta x)$, or $\phi(x + 4\Delta x)$, when $x$~is changed into $x + \Delta x$, and receives the increment $\phi(x + 4\Delta x) - \phi(x + 3\Delta x)$, or $y_{4} - y_{3}$. If $y$~be a function which decreases when $x$~is increased, $y_{1} - y$, or $\Delta y$ is negative. It must be observed, as in \PageRef{26}, that $\Delta x$~does not depend upon~$x$, because $x$~occurs in it; the symbol merely signifies an increment given to~$x$, which increment is not necessarily dependent upon the value of~$x$. For instance, in the present case we suppose it a given quantity; that is, when $x + \Delta x$ is changed into $x + \Delta x + \Delta x$, or $x + 2\Delta x$, $x$~is changed, and $\Delta x$~is not. In this way we get the two first of the columns underneath, in which each term of the \emph{second} column is formed by subtracting the term which immediately precedes it in the first column from the one which immediately \PageSep{90} follows. Thus $\Delta y$ is $y_{1} - y$, $\Delta y_{1}$ is $y_{2} - y_{1}$, etc. \begin{gather*}%**** Tall, bad page break \left. \begin{alignedat}{2} & \PadTo[l]{\phi(x + 4\Delta x)}{\phi(x)} && y \\ & \phi(x + \Z\Delta x)\qquad && y_{1} \\ & \phi(x + 2\Delta x) && y_{2} \\ & \phi(x + 3\Delta x) && y_{3} \\ & \phi(x + 4\Delta x) && y_{4} \end{alignedat}\ \right| % \left. \begin{aligned} & \Delta y \\ & \Delta y_{1} \\ & \Delta y_{2} \\ & \Delta y_{3} \end{aligned}\ \right| % \left. \begin{aligned} & \Delta^{2} y \\ & \Delta^{2} y_{1} \\ & \Delta^{2} y_{2} \end{aligned}\ \right| % \left. \begin{aligned} & \Delta^{3} y \\ & \Delta^{3} y_{1} \end{aligned}\ \right| % \begin{aligned} & \Delta^{4} y \end{aligned} \\ \PadTo{\phi(x + 4\Delta x)}{\etc.}\phantom{\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad\qquad} \end{gather*} In the first column is to be found a series of successive values of the same function~$\phi x$, that is, it contains terms produced by substituting successively in~$\phi x$ the quantities $x$, $x + \Delta x$, $x + 2\Delta x$, etc., instead of~$x$. The second column contains the successive values of another function $\phi(x + \Delta x) - \phi x$, or~$\Delta \phi x$, made by the same substitutions; if, for example, we substitute $x + 2\Delta x$ for~$x$, we obtain $\phi(x + 3\Delta x) - \phi(x + 2\Delta x)$, or $y_{3} - y_{2}$, or~$\Delta y_{2}$. If, then, we form the successive differences of the terms in the second column, we obtain a new series, which we might call the differences of the differences of the first column, but which are called the \emph{second differences} of the first column. And as we have denoted the operation which deduces the second column from the first by~$\Delta$, so that which deduces the third from the second may be denoted by~$\Delta\Delta$, which is abbreviated into~$\Delta^{2}$. Hence as $y_{1} - y$ was written~$\Delta y$, $\Delta y_{1} - \Delta y$ is written~$\Delta\Delta y$, or~$\Delta^{2} y$. And the student must recollect, that in like manner as $\Delta$~is not the symbol of a number, but of an operation, so $\Delta^{2}$~does not denote a number multiplied by itself, but an operation repeated upon its own result; just as the logarithm of the logarithm of~$x$ might be written $\log^{2} x$; $(\log x)^{2}$~being reserved to signify the square of the logarithm of~$x$. We do not enlarge on this notation, as the subject is discussed in most treatises on \PageSep{91} algebra.\footnote {The reference of the original text is to ``the treatise on \Title{Algebraical Expressions},'' Number~105 of the Library of Useful Knowledge,---the same series in which the present work appeared. The first six pages of this treatise are particularly recommended by De~Morgan in relation to the present point.---\Ed.} Similarly the terms of the fourth column, or the differences of the second differences, have the prefix~$\Delta\Delta\Delta$ abbreviated into~$\Delta^{3}$, so that $\Delta^{2} y_{1} - \Delta^{2} y = \Delta^{3} y$, etc. When we have occasion to examine the results which arise from supposing $\Delta x$~to diminish without limit, we use~$dx$ instead of~$\Delta x$, $dy$~instead of~$\Delta y$, $d^{2} y$~instead of~$\Delta^{2} y$, and so on. If we suppose this case, we can show that the ratio which the term in any column bears to its corresponding term in any preceding column, diminishes without limit. Take for example, $d^{2} y$~and~$dy$. The latter is $\phi(x + dx) - \phi x$, which, as we have often noticed already, is of the form $p\, dx + q\, (dx)^{2} + \etc.$, in which $p$,~$q$,~etc., are also functions of~$x$. To obtain~$d^{2} y$, we must, in this series, change~$x$ into $x + dx$, and subtract $p\, dx + q\, (dx)^{2} + \etc.$\ from the result. But since $p$,~$q$,~etc., are functions of~$x$, this change gives them the form \[ p + p'\, dx + \etc.,\quad q + q'\, dx + \etc.; \] so that $d^{2} y$~is \begin{gather*} (p + p'\, dx + \etc.)\, dx + (q + q'\, dx + \etc.)(dx)^{2} + \etc. \\ {} - (p\, dx + q\, (dx)^{2} + \etc.) \end{gather*} in which the first power of~$dx$ is destroyed. Hence (\PageRefs{42}{44}), the ratio of $d^{2} y$ to~$dx$ diminishes without limit, while that of $d^{2} y$ to~$(dx)^{2}$ has a finite limit, except in those particular cases in which the second power of~$dx$ is destroyed, in the previous subtraction, as well as the first. In the same way it may be shown that the ratio of $d^{3} y$ to $dx$~and $(dx)^{2}$ decreases without limit, while that of $d^{3} y$ to~$(dx)^{3}$ remains finite; and so \PageSep{92} on. Hence we have a succession of ratios $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$, $\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}$, $\dfrac{d^{3} y}{dx^{3}}$, etc., which tend towards finite limits when $dx$~is diminished. {\Loosen We now proceed to show that in the development of $\phi(x + h)$, which has been shown to be of the form} \[ \phi x + \phi' x\, h + \phi'' x\, \frac{h^{2}}{2} + \phi''' x\, \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} + \etc., \] in the same manner as $\phi' x$~is the limit of~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$ (\PageRef{23}), so $\phi'' x$~is the limit of~$\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}$, $\phi''' x$~is that of~$\dfrac{d^{3} y}{dx^{3}}$, and so forth. From the manner in which the preceding table was formed, the following relations are seen immediately: \begin{gather*} \begin{alignedat}{4} y_{1} &= y &&+ \Delta y & \Delta y_{1} &= \Delta y &&+ \Delta^{2} y\Add{,} \\ y_{2} &= y_{1} &&+ \Delta y_{1}\qquad & \Delta y_{2} &= \Delta y_{1} &&+ \Delta^{2} y_{1}\Add{,} \end{alignedat} \\ \begin{alignedat}{3} \Delta^{2} y_{1} &= \Delta^{2} y &&+ \Delta^{3} y && \etc.\Add{,} \\ \Delta^{2} y_{2} &= \Delta^{2} y_{1} &&+ \Delta^{3} y_{1}\ && \etc. \end{alignedat} \end{gather*} Hence $y_{1}$,~$y_{2}$,~etc., can be expressed in terms of $y$,~$\Delta y$, $\Delta^{2} y$,~etc. For $y_{1} = y + \Delta y$; %[** TN: Next two displays in-line in the original] \begin{align*} y_{2} = y_{1} + \Delta y_{1} &= (y + \Delta y) + (\Delta y + \Delta^{2} y) = y + 2\Delta y + \Delta^{2} y. \displaybreak[0] \intertext{In the same way $\Delta y_{2} = \Delta y + 2\Delta^{2} y + \Delta^{3} y$; hence} y_{3} = y_{2} + \Delta y_{2} &= (y + 2\Delta y + \Delta^{2} y) + (\Delta y + 2\Delta^{2} y + \Delta^{3} y) \\ &= y + 3\Delta y + 3\Delta^{2} y + \Delta^{3} y. \end{align*} Proceeding in this way we have \begin{alignat*}{5} y_{1} = y &{}+{}& \Delta y\Add{\rlap{,}} \\ y_{2} = y &{}+{}&2\Delta y &{}+{}& \Delta^{2} y\Add{\rlap{,}} \\ y_{3} = y &{}+{}&3\Delta y &{}+{}& 3\Delta^{2} y &{}+{}& \Delta^{3} y\Add{\rlap{,}} \\ y_{4} = y &{}+{}&4\Delta y &{}+{}& 6\Delta^{2} y &{}+{}& 4\Delta^{3} y &{}+{}& \Delta^{5} y\Add{\rlap{,}} \\ y_{5} = y &{}+{}&5\Delta y &{}+{}&10\Delta^{2} y &{}+{}&10\Delta^{3} y &{}+{}&5\Delta^{5} y &+ \Delta^{6} y,\ \etc.\Add{,} \end{alignat*} from the whole of which it appears that $y_{n}$ or $\phi(x + n\Delta x)$ is a series consisting of $y$,~$\Delta y$,~etc., up to~$\Delta^{n} y$, severally multiplied by the coefficients which occur in the expansion $(1 + a)^{n}$, or \PageSep{93} \begin{align*}%[** TN: Re-formatted] y_{n} &= \phi(x + n\Delta x) \\ &= y + n\Delta y + n\frac{n - 1}{2}\, \Delta^{2} y + n\frac{n - 1}{2}\, \frac{n - 2}{3}\, \Delta^{3} y + \etc. \end{align*} Let us now suppose that $x$~becomes $x + h$ by $n$~equal steps; that is, $x$,~$x + \dfrac{h}{n}$, $x + \dfrac{2h}{n}$, etc.~\dots\ $x + \dfrac{nh}{h}$ or~$x + h$, are the successive values of~$x$, so that $n\Delta x = h$. Since the product of a number of factors is not altered by multiplying one of them, provided we divide another of them by the same quantity, multiply every factor which contains~$n$ by~$\Delta x$, and divide the accompanying difference of~$y$ by $\Delta x$ as often as there are factors which contain~$n$, substituting~$h$ for~$n\Delta x$, which gives \begin{align*} \phi(x + n\Delta x) &= y + n\Delta x\, \frac{\Delta y}{\Delta x} + n\Delta x\, \frac{n\Delta x - \Delta x}{2}\, \frac{\Delta^{2} y}{(\Delta x)^{2}} \\ &\quad+ n\Delta x\, \frac{n\Delta x - \Delta x}{2}\, \frac{n\Delta x - 2\Delta x}{3}\, \frac{\Delta^{3} y}{(\Delta x)^{3}} + \etc.\Add{,} \end{align*} or \begin{align*} \iffalse %[** TN: Commented code matches the original] \phi(x + h) &= \PadTo{y + n\Delta x}{y + h}\, \frac{\Delta y}{\Delta x} + \PadTo{n\Delta x}{h}\, \PadTo{\dfrac{n\Delta x - \Delta x}{2}}{\dfrac{h - \Delta x}{2}}\, \frac{\Delta^{2} y}{(\Delta x)^{2}} \\ &+ \PadTo{n\Delta x}{h}\, \PadTo{\dfrac{n\Delta x - \Delta x}{2}}{\dfrac{h - \Delta x}{2}}\, \PadTo{\dfrac{n\Delta x - 2\Delta x}{3}}{\dfrac{h - 2\Delta x}{3}}\, \frac{\Delta^{3} y}{(\Delta x)^{3}} + \etc. \fi \phi(x + h) = y &+ h\, \frac{\Delta y}{\Delta x} + h\, \frac{h - \Delta x}{2}\, \frac{\Delta^{2} y}{(\Delta x)^{2}} \\ &+ h\, \frac{h - \Delta x}{2}\, \frac{h - 2\Delta x}{3}\, \frac{\Delta^{3} y}{(\Delta x)^{3}} + \etc. \end{align*} If $h$ remain the same, the more steps we make between $x$~and~$x + h$, the smaller will each of those steps be, and the number of steps may be increased, until each of them is as small as we please. We can therefore suppose $\Delta x$ to decrease without limit, without affecting the truth of the series just deduced. Write $dx$ for~$\Delta x$, etc., and recollect that $h - dx$, $h - 2\, dx$, etc., continually approximate to~$h$. The series then becomes \[ \phi(x + h) = y + \frac{dy}{dx}\, h + \frac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}\, \frac{h^{2}}{2} + \frac{d^{3} y}{dx^{3}}\, \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} + \etc.\Add{,} \] \PageSep{94} in which, according to the view taken of the symbols $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$~etc.\ in \PageRefs{26}{27}, $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$~stands for the \emph{limit} of the ratio of the increments, $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$~is $\phi' x$, $\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}$~is $\phi'' x$,~etc. According to the method proposed in \PageRefs{28}{29}, the series written above is the first term of the development of~$\phi(x + h)$, the remaining terms (which we might include under an additional~$+$ etc.)\ being such as to diminish without limit in comparison with the first, when $dx$~is diminished without limit. And we may show that the limit of~$\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}$ is the differential coefficient of the limit of~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$; or if by these fractions themselves are understood their limits, that $\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}$ is the differential coefficient of~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$: for since $dy$, or $\phi(x + dx) - \phi x$, becomes $dy + d^{2} y$, when $x$~is changed into $x + dx$; and since $dx$~does not change in this process, $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$ will become $\dfrac{dy}{dx} + \dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx}$, or its increment is~$\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx}$. The ratio of this to~$dx$ is~$\dfrac{d^{2} y}{(dx)^{2}}$, the limit of which, in the definition of \PageRef{22}, is the differential coefficient of~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$. Similarly the limit of~$\dfrac{d^{3} y}{dx^{3}}$ is the differential coefficient of the limit of~$\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}$; and so on. \Subsection{Total and Partial Differential Coefficients. Implicit Differentiation.} We now proceed to apply the principles laid down, \index{Differentiation!implicit|EtSeq}% \index{Implicit!differentiation|EtSeq}% to some cases in which the variable enters into its function in a less direct and more complicated manner. \PageSep{95} For example, let $z$ be a given function of $x$~and~$y$, and let $y$~be another given function of~$x$; so that $z$ contains $x$ both directly and indirectly; the latter as it contains~$y$, which is a function of~$x$. This will be the case if $z = x\log y$, where $y = \sin x$. If we were to substitute for~$y$ its value in terms of~$x$, the value of~$z$ would then be a function of $x$~only; in the instance just given it would be $x\log\sin x$. But if it be not convenient to combine the two equations at the beginning of the process, let us first consider $z$ as a function of $x$~and~$y$, in which the two variables are independent. In this case, if $x$~and~$y$ respectively receive the increments $dx$~and~$dy$, the whole increment of~$z$, or~$d.z$, (or at least that part which gives the limit of the ratios) is represented by \[ \frac{dz}{dx}\, dx + \frac{dz}{dy}\, dy. \] If $y$ be now considered as a function of~$x$, the consequence is that $dy$, instead of being independent of~$dx$, is a series of the form $p\, dx + q\, (dx)^{2} + \etc.$, in which $p$~is the differential coefficient of~$y$ with respect to~$x$. Hence \[ d.z = \frac{dz}{dx}\, dx + \frac{dz}{dy}\, p\, dx \quad\text{or}\quad \frac{d.z}{dx} = \frac{dz}{dx} + \frac{dz}{dx}\, p, \] in which the difference between $\dfrac{d.z}{dx}$ and $\dfrac{dz}{dx}$ is this, that in the second, $x$~is only considered as varying where it is directly contained in~$z$, or $z$~is considered in the form in which it first appeared, as a function of $x$~and~$y$, where $y$~is independent of~$x$; in the first, or $\dfrac{d.z}{dx}$, the \emph{total variation} of~$z$ is denoted, that is, $y$~is \index{Total!variations}% \index{Variations, total}% now considered as a function of~$x$, by which means if $x$ become $x + dx$, $z$~will receive a different increment \PageSep{96} from that which it would have received, had $y$ been independent of~$x$. {\Loosen In the instance above cited, where $z = x\log y$ and $y = \sin x$, if the first equation be taken, and $x$ becomes $x + dx$, $y$~remaining the same, $z$~becomes $x\log y + \log y\, dx$ or $\dfrac{dz}{dx}$ is~$\log y$.} If $y$~only varies, since (\PageRef{20}) $z$~will then become \[ x\log y + x\, \frac{dy}{y} - \etc., \] $\dfrac{dz}{dy}$ is~$\dfrac{x}{y}$ And $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$~is $\cos x$ when $y = \sin x$ (\PageRef{20}). Hence $\dfrac{dz}{dx} + \dfrac{dz}{dy}\, p$, or $\dfrac{dz}{dx} + \dfrac{dz}{dy}\, \dfrac{dy}{dx}$ is $\log y + \dfrac{x}{y} \cos x$, or $\log\sin x + \dfrac{x}{\sin x} \cos x$. This is~$\dfrac{d.z}{dx}$, which might have been obtained by a more complicated process, if $\sin x$ had been substituted for~$y$, before the operation commenced. It is called the \emph{complete} or \emph{total} differential \index{Coefficients, differential}% \index{Complete Differential Coefficients}% coefficient with respect to~$x$, the word \emph{total} indicating that every way in which $z$ contains~$x$ has been used; in opposition to~$\dfrac{dz}{dx}$, which is called the \emph{partial} \index{Partial!differential coefficients}% differential coefficient, $x$~having been considered as varying only where it is directly contained in~$z$. Generally, the complete differential coefficient of~$z$ with respect to~$x$, will contain as many terms as there are different ways in which $z$ contains~$x$. From looking at a complete differential coefficient, we may see in what manner the function contained its variable. Take, for example, the following, \[ \frac{d.z}{dx} = \frac{dz}{dx} + \frac{dz}{dy}\, \frac{dy}{dx} + \frac{dz}{da}\, \frac{da}{dy}\, \frac{dy}{dx} + \frac{dz}{da}\, \frac{da}{dx}. \] Before proceeding to demonstrate this formula, we will collect from itself the hypothesis from which it \PageSep{97} \index{Functions!direct and indirect}% must have arisen. When $x$~is contained in~$z$, we shall say that $z$~is a \emph{direct}\footnote {It may be right to warn the student that this phraseology is new, to the best of our knowledge. The nomenclature of the Differential Calculus has by no means kept pace with its wants; indeed the same may be said of algebra generally. [Written in~1832.---\Ed.]} function of~$x$. When $x$~is contained in~$y$, and $y$~is contained in~$z$, we shall say that $z$~is an indirect function of~$x$ \emph{through}~$y$. It is evident \index{Indirect function}% that an indirect function may be reduced to one which is direct, by substituting for the quantities which contain~$x$, their values in terms of~$x$. The first side of the equation~$\dfrac{d.z}{dx}$ is shown by the point to be a complete differential coefficient, and indicates that $z$~is a function of~$x$ in several ways; either directly, and indirectly through one quantity at least, or indirectly through several. If $z$~be a direct function \index{Direct function}% only, or indirectly through one quantity only, the symbol~$\dfrac{dz}{dx}$, without the point, would represent its total differential coefficient with respect to~$x$. On the second side of the equation we see: (1) $\dfrac{dz}{dx}$: which shows that $z$~is a direct function of~$x$, and is that part of the differential coefficient which we should get by changing $x$ into $x + dx$ throughout~$z$, not supposing any other quantity which enters into~$z$ to contain~$x$. (2) $\dfrac{dz}{dy}\, \dfrac{dy}{dx}$: which shows that $z$~is an indirect function of~$x$ through~$y$. If $x$~and~$y$ had been supposed to vary independently of each other, the increment of~$z$, (or those terms which give the limiting ratio of this increment to any other,) would have been $\dfrac{dz}{dx}\, dx + \dfrac{dz}{dy}\, dy$, in which, if $dy$~had arisen from~$y$ being a function \PageSep{98} of~$x$, $dy$~would have been a series of the form $p\, dx + q\, (dx)^{2} + \etc.$, of which only the differential coefficient~$p$ would have appeared in the limit. Hence $\dfrac{dz}{dy}\, dy$ would have given~$\dfrac{dz}{dy}\, p$, or~$\dfrac{dz}{dy}\, \dfrac{dy}{dx}$. (3) $\dfrac{dz}{da}\, \dfrac{da}{dy}\, \dfrac{dy}{dx}$: this arises from $z$ containing~$a$, which contains~$y$, which contains~$x$. If $z$~had been differentiated with respect to $a$~only, the increment would have been represented by~$\dfrac{dz}{da}\, da$; if $da$~had arisen from an increment of~$y$, this would have been expressed by $\dfrac{dz}{da}\, \dfrac{da}{dy}\, dy$; if~$y$ had arisen from an increment given to~$x$, this would have been expressed by $\dfrac{dz}{da}\, \dfrac{da}{dy}\, \dfrac{dy}{dx}\, dx$, which, after $dx$~has been struck out, is the part of the differential coefficient answering to that increment. (4) $\dfrac{dz}{da}\, \dfrac{da}{dx}$: arising from $a$~containing $x$~directly, and $z$~therefore containing $x$ indirectly through~$a$. Hence $z$~is directly a function of $x$,~$y$, and~$a$, of which $y$~is a function of~$x$, and $a$~of $y$~and~$x$. If we suppose $x$,~$y$ and~$a$ to vary independently, we have \[ d.z = \frac{dz}{dx}\, dx + \frac{dz}{dy}\, dy + \frac{dz}{da}\, da + \etc. \quad\text{(\PageRefs{28}{29})}. \] But as $a$~varies as a function of $y$~and~$x$, \[ da = \frac{da}{dx}\, dx + \frac{da}{dy}\, dy. \] If we substitute this instead of~$da$, and divide by~$dx$, taking the limit of the ratios, we have the result first given. For example, let (1) $z = x^{2} ya^{3}$, (2) $y = x^{2}$, and (3) $a = x^{3} y$. Taking the first equation only, and substituting \PageSep{99} $x + dx$ for~$x$ etc., we find $\dfrac{dz}{dx} = 2xya^{3}$, $\dfrac{dz}{dy} = x^{2} a^{3}$, and $\dfrac{dz}{da} = 3x^{2} ya^{2}$. From the second $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = 2x$, and from the third $\dfrac{da}{dx} = 3x^{2} y$, and $\dfrac{da}{dy} = x^{3}$. Substituting these in the value of~$\dfrac{d.z}{dx}$, we find \begin{alignat*}{3} %[** TN: Reformatted first line] \frac{d.z}{dx} \text{ \ or \ } \frac{dz}{dx} &+ \frac{dz}{dy}\, \frac{dy}{dx} &&+ \frac{dz}{da}\, \frac{da}{dy}\, \frac{dy}{dx} &&+ \frac{dz}{da}\, \frac{da}{dx} \\ = 2xya^{3} &+ x^{2} a^{3} × 2x &&+ 3x^{2} ya^{2} × x^{3} × 2x &&+ 3x^{2} ya^{2} × 3x^{2} y \\ = 2xya^{3} &+ 2x^{3} a^{3} &&+ 6x^{6} ya^{2} &&+ 9x^{4} y^{2} a^{2}\Add{.} \end{alignat*} If for $y$~and~$a$ in the first equation we substitute their values $x^{2}$ and~$x^{3} y$, or~$x^{5}$, we have $z = x^{19}$, the differential coefficient of which\Add{ is}~$19x^{18}$. This is the same as arises from the formula just obtained, after $x^{2}$~and~$x^{5}$ have been substituted for $y$~and~$a$; for this formula then becomes \[ 2x^{18} + 2x^{18} + 6x^{18} + 9x^{18} \quad\text{or}\quad 19x^{18}. \] In saying that $z$~is a function of $x$~and~$y$, and that $y$~is a function of~$x$, we have first supposed~$x$ to vary, $y$~remaining the same. The student must not imagine that $y$~is \emph{then} a function of~$x$; for if so, it would vary when $x$~varied. There are two parts of the total differential coefficient, arising from the direct and indirect manner in which $z$ contains~$x$. That these two parts may be obtained separately, and that their sum constitutes the complete differential coefficient, is the theorem we have proved. The first part~$\dfrac{dz}{dx}$ is what \emph{would} have been obtained if $y$~had \emph{not} been a function of~$x$; and on this supposition we therefore proceed to find it. The other part $\dfrac{dz}{dy}\, \dfrac{dy}{dx}$ is the product (1)~of~$\dfrac{dz}{dy}$, which would have resulted from a variation of $y$~only, not considered as a function of~$x$; and (2)~of~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$, \PageSep{100} the coefficient which arises from considering~$y$ as a function of~$x$. These partial suppositions, however useful in obtaining the total differential coefficient, \index{Coefficients, differential}% \index{Total!differential coefficient}% cannot be separately admitted or used, except for this purpose; since if $y$~be a function of~$x$, $x$~and~$y$ must vary together. If $z$~be a function of~$x$ in various ways, the theorem obtained may be stated as follows: Find the differential coefficient belonging to each of the ways in which $z$ will contain~$x$, as if it were the only way; the sum of these results (with their proper signs) will be the total differential coefficient. Thus, if $z$~only contains $x$ indirectly through~$y$, $\dfrac{dz}{dx}$~is $\dfrac{dz}{dy}\, \dfrac{dy}{dx}$. If $z$ contains~$a$, which contains~$b$, which contains~$x$, $\dfrac{dz}{dx} = \dfrac{dz}{da}\, \dfrac{da}{db}\, \dfrac{db}{dx}$. This theorem is useful in the differentiation of complicated \index{Differentiation!of complicated functions|EtSeq}% functions; for example, let $z = \log(x^{2} + a^{2})$. If we make $y = x^{2} + a^{2}$, we have $z = \log y$, and $\dfrac{dz}{dy} = \dfrac{1}{y}$; while from the first equation $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = 2x$. Hence $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$ or $\dfrac{dz}{dy}\, \dfrac{dy}{dx}$ is $\dfrac{2x}{y}$ or $\dfrac{2x}{x^{2} + a^{2}}$. %[** TN: \log\log\sin x is never real valued when x is real] If $z = \log\log\sin x$, or the logarithm of the logarithm of~$\sin x$, let $\sin x = y$ and $\log y = a$; whence $z= \log a$, and contains~$x$, because $a$ contains~$y$, which contains~$x$. Hence \[ \frac{dz}{dx} = \frac{dz}{da}\, \frac{da}{dy}\, \frac{dy}{dx}; \] but since $z = \log a$, \[ \frac{dz}{da} = \frac{1}{a}; \] \PageSep{101} since $a = \log y$, \[ \frac{da}{dy} = \frac{1}{y}; \] and since $y = \sin x$, \[ \frac{dy}{dx} = \cos x. \] Hence \[ \frac{dz}{dx} = \frac{dz}{da}\, \frac{da}{dy}\, \frac{dy}{dx} = \frac{1}{a}\, \frac{1}{y} \cos x = \frac{\cos x}{\log\sin x \sin x}. \] We now put some rules in the form of applications of this theorem, though they may be deduced more simply. \Subsection[Applications of the Theorem for Implicit Differentiation.] {Applications of the Preceding Theorem.} (1) Let $z = ab$, where $a$~and~$b$ are functions of~$x$. The general formula, since $z$ contains~$x$ indirectly through $a$~and~$b$, is (in this case as well as in those which follow,) \[ \frac{dz}{dx} = \frac{dz}{da}\, \frac{da}{dx} + \frac{dz}{db}\, \frac{db}{dx}. \] We must leave $\dfrac{da}{dx}$ and $\dfrac{db}{dx}$ as we find them, until we know \emph{what} functions $a$~and~$b$ are of~$x$; but as we know what function $z$~is of $a$~and~$b$, we substitute for $\dfrac{dz}{da}$ and~$\dfrac{dz}{db}$. Since $z = ab$, if $a$~becomes $a + da$, $z$~becomes $ab + b\, da$, whence $\dfrac{dz}{db} = b$. In this case, and part of the following, the limiting ratio of the increments is the same as that of the increments themselves. Similarly $\dfrac{dz}{db} = a$, whence from $z = ab$ follows \[ \frac{dz}{dx} = b\, \frac{da}{dx} + a\, \frac{db}{dx}. \] \PageSep{102} %[** TN: [sic] "become", twice] (2) Let $z = \dfrac{a}{b}$. If $a$~become $a + da$, $z$~becomes $\dfrac{a + da}{b}$ or $\dfrac{a}{b} + \dfrac{da}{b}$, and $\dfrac{dz}{da}$ is~$\dfrac{1}{b}$. If $b$~become $b + db$, $z$~becomes $\dfrac{a}{b + db}$, or $\dfrac{a}{b} - \dfrac{a\, db}{b^{2}} + \etc.$, whence $\dfrac{dz}{db}$ is~$-\dfrac{a}{b^{2}}$\Add{.} Hence from $z = \dfrac{a}{b}$ follows \[ \frac{dz}{dx} = \frac{1}{b}\, \frac{da}{dx} - \frac{a}{b^{2}}\, \frac{db}{dx} = \frac{b\, \dfrac{da}{dx} - a\, \dfrac{db}{dx}}{b^{2}}. \] (3) Let $z = a^{b}$. Here $(a + da)^{b} = a^{b} + ba^{b-1}\, da + \etc.$\ (\PageRef{21}), whence $\dfrac{dz}{da} = ba^{b-1}$. Again, $a^{b+db} = a^{b}\, a^{db} = a^{b}(1 + \log a\, db + \etc.)$ whence $\dfrac{dz}{db} = a^{b} \log a$. Therefore from $z = a^{b}$ follows \[ \frac{dz}{dx} = ba^{b-1}\, \frac{da}{dx} + a^{b} \log a\, \frac{db}{dx}. \] \Subsection{Inverse Functions.} If $y$~be a function of~$x$, such as $y = \phi x$, we may, \index{Functions!inverse|EtSeq}% \index{Inverse functions|EtSeq}% by solution of the equation, determine $x$ in terms of~$y$, or produce another equation of the form $x = \psi y$. For example, when $y = x^{2}$, $x = y^{\efrac{1}{2}}$. It is not necessary that we should be able to solve the equation $y = \phi x$ in finite terms, that is, so as to give a value of~$x$ without infinite series; it is sufficient that $x$~can be so expressed that the value of~$x$ corresponding to any value of~$y$ may be found as near as we please from $x = \psi y$, in the same manner as the value of~$y$ corresponding to any value of~$x$ is found from $y = \phi x$. The equations $y = \phi x$, and $x = \psi y$, are connected, being, in fact, the same relation in different forms; and if the value of~$y$ from the first be substituted in \PageSep{103} the second, the second becomes $x = \psi(\phi x)$, or as it is more commonly written, $\psi\phi x$. That is, the effect of the operation or set of operations denoted by~$\psi$ is destroyed by the effect of those denoted by~$\phi$; as in the instances $(x^{2})^{\efrac{1}{2}}$, $(x^{3})^{\efrac{1}{3}}$, $e^{\log x}$, angle whose sine is~$(\sin x)$, etc., each of which is equal to~$x$. By differentiating the first equation $y = \phi x$, we obtain $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = \phi' x$, and from the second $\dfrac{dx}{dy} = \psi' y$. But whatever values of $x$~and~$y$ together satisfy the first equation, satisfy the second also; hence, if when $x$~becomes $x + dx$ in the first, $y$~becomes $y + dy$; the same $y + dy$ substituted for~$y$ in the second, will give the same $x + dx$. Hence $\dfrac{dx}{dy}$ as deduced from the second, and $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$ as deduced from the first, are reciprocals for every value of~$dx$. The limit of one is therefore the reciprocal of the limit of the other; the student may easily prove that if $a$~is always equal to~$\dfrac{1}{b}$, and if $a$~continually approaches to the limit~$\alpha$, while $b$~at the same time approaches the limit~$\beta$, $\alpha$~is equal to~$\dfrac{1}{\beta}$. But $\dfrac{dx}{dy}$ or $\psi' y$, deduced from $x = \psi y$, is expressed in terms of~$y$, while $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$ or $\phi' x$, deduced from $y = \phi x$ is expressed in terms of~$x$. Therefore $\psi' y$ and $\phi' x$ are reciprocals for all such values of $x$~and~$y$ as satisfy either of the two first equations. For example let $y = e^{x}$, from which $x = \log y$. From the first (\PageRef{20}) $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = e^{x}$; from the second $\dfrac{dx}{dy} = \dfrac{1}{y}$; and it is evident that $e^{x}$~and~$\dfrac{1}{y}$ are reciprocals, whenever $y = e^{x}$. If we differentiate the above equations twice, we get \PageSep{104} $\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}} = \phi'' x$, and $\dfrac{d^{2} x}{dy^{2}} = \psi'' x$. There is no very obvious analogy between $\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}$ and $\dfrac{d^{2} x}{dy^{2}}$; indeed no such appears from the method in which these coefficients were first formed. Turn to the table in \PageRef{90}, and substitute $d$ for~$\Delta$ throughout, to indicate that the increments may be taken as small as we please. We there substitute in~$\phi x$ what we will call a set of \emph{equidistant} values \index{Equidistant values}% \index{Values!equidistant}% of~$x$, or values in arithmetical progression, viz., $x$,~$x + dx$, $x + 2\, dx$,~etc. The resulting values of~$y$, or $y$,~$y_{1}$, etc., are not equidistant, except in one function only, when $y = ax + b$, where $a$~and~$b$ are constant. Therefore $dy$,~$dy_{1}$, etc., are not equal; whence arises the next column of second differences, or $d^{2} y$, $d^{2} y_{1}$, etc. The limiting ratio of $d^{2} y$ to~$(dx)^{2}$, expressed by~$\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}$, is the second differential coefficient of~$y$ with respect to~$x$. If from $y = \phi x$ we deduce $x = \psi y$, and take a set of equidistant values of~$y$, viz., $y$,~$y + dy$, $y + 2\, dy$, etc., to which the corresponding values of~$x$ are $x$,~$x_{1}$, $x_{2}$,~etc., a similar table may be formed, which will give $dx$,~$dx_{1}$, etc., $d^{2} x$,~$d^{2} x_{1}$, etc., and the limit of the ratio of~$d^{2} x$ to~$(dy)^{2}$ or $\dfrac{d^{2} x}{dy^{2}}$ is the second differential coefficient of~$x$ with respect to~$y$. These are entirely different suppositions, $dx$~being given in the first table, and $dy$~varying; while in the second $dy$~is given and $dx$~varies. We may show how to deduce one from the other as follows: When, as before, $y = \phi x$ and $x = \psi y$, we have \[ \frac{dy}{dx} = \phi' x = \frac{1}{\psi' y} = \frac{1}{p}, \] if $\psi' y$ be called~$p$. Calling this~$u$, and considering it \PageSep{105} as a function of~$x$ from containing~$p$, which contains~$y$, which contains~$x$, we have \[ \frac{du}{dp}\, \frac{dp}{dy}\, \frac{dy}{dx} \] for its differential coefficient with respect to~$x$. But since \[ u = \frac{1}{p}, \] therefore \[ \frac{du}{dp} = -\frac{1}{p^{2}}; \] since $p = \psi' y$, therefore \[ \frac{dp}{dy} = \psi'' y; \] and $\psi'' y$ is the differential coefficient of~$\psi' y$, and is $\dfrac{d^{2} x}{dy^{2}}$. Also $\dfrac{1}{p^{2}}$~is \[ \frac{1}{(\psi' y)^{2}} \quad\text{or}\quad (\phi' x)^{2} \quad\text{or}\quad \left(\frac{dy}{dx}\right)^{2}. \] Hence the differential coefficient of $u$ or~$\dfrac{dy}{dx}$, with respect to~$x$, which is~$\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}$, is also \[ -\left(\frac{dy}{dx}\right)^{2} \frac{d^{2} x}{dy^{2}}\, \frac{dy}{dx} \quad\text{or}\quad -\left(\frac{dy}{dx}\right)^{3} \frac{d^{2} x}{dy^{2}}. \] {\Loosen If $y = e^{x}$, whence $x = \log y$, we have $\dfrac{dy}{dx} = e^{x}$ and $\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}} = e^{x}$. But $\dfrac{dx}{dy} = \dfrac{1}{y}$ and $\dfrac{d^{2} x}{dy^{2}} = -\dfrac{1}{y^{2}}$. Therefore} \[ -\left(\frac{dy}{dx}\right)^{3} \frac{d^{2} x}{dy^{2}} \quad\text{is}\quad -e^{3x} \left(-\frac{1}{y^{2}}\right) \quad\text{or}\quad \frac{e^{3x}}{y^{2}} \quad\text{or}\quad \frac{e^{3x}}{e^{2x}}, \] which is~$e^{x}$, the value just found for~$\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}$. \PageSep{106} In the same way $\dfrac{d^{3} y}{dx^{3}}$ might be expressed in terms of $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$, $\dfrac{d^{2} y}{dx^{2}}$, and~$\dfrac{d^{3} x}{dy^{3}}$; and so on. \Subsection{Implicit Functions.} The variable which appears in the denominator of the differential coefficients is called the \emph{independent} variable. In any function, one quantity at least is changed at pleasure; and the changes of the rest, with the limiting ratio of the changes, follow from the form of the function. The number of independent variables depends upon the number of quantities \index{Variables!independent and dependent}% which enter into the equations, and upon the number of equations which connect them. If there be only one equation, all the variables except one are independent, or may be changed at pleasure, without ceasing to satisfy the equation; for in such a case the common rules of algebra tell us, that as long as one quantity is left to be determined from the rest, it can be determined by one equation; that is, the values of all but one are at our pleasure, it being still in our power to satisfy one equation, by giving a proper value to the remaining one. Similarly, if there be two equations, all variables except two are independent, and so on. If there be two equations with two unknown quantities only, there are no variables; for by algebra, a finite number of values, and a finite number only, can satisfy these equations; whereas it is the nature of a variable to receive any value, or at least any value which will not give impossible values for other variables. If then there be $m$~equations containing $n$~variables, ($n$~must be greater than~$m$), we have $n - m$~independent variables, to each of which \index{Independent variables}% \PageSep{107} we may give what values we please, and by the equations, deduce the values of the rest. We have thus various sets of differential coefficients, arising out of the various choices which we may make of independent variables. If, for example, $a$,~$b$, $x$,~$y$, and~$z$, being variables, we have \begin{align*} \phi(a, b, x, y, z) &= 0, \\ \psi(a, b, x, y, z) &= 0, \\ \chi(a, b, x, y, z) &= 0, \end{align*} we have two independent variables, which may be either $x$~and~$y$, $x$~and~$z$, $a$~and~$b$, or any other combination. If we choose $x$~and~$y$, we should determine $a$,~$b$, and~$z$ in terms of $x$~and~$y$ from the three equations; in which case we can obtain \[ \frac{da}{dx},\quad \frac{da}{dy},\quad \frac{db}{dx},\quad \etc. \] When $y$~is a function of~$x$, as in $y = \phi x$, it is called \index{Explicit functions}% \index{Functions!implicit and explicit}% an \emph{explicit} function of~$x$. This equation tells us not only that $y$~is a function of~$x$, but also what function it is. The value of~$x$ being given, nothing more is necessary to determine the corresponding value of~$y$, than the substitution of the value of~$x$ in the several terms of~$\phi x$. But it may happen that though $y$~is a function of~$x$, \index{Implicit!function}% the relation between them is contained in a form from which $y$~must be deduced by the solution of an equation. For example, in $x^{2} - xy + y^{2} = a$, when $x$~is known, $y$~must be determined by the solution of an equation of the second degree. Here, though we know that $y$~must be a function of~$x$, we do not know, without further investigation, what function it is. In this case $y$~is said to be \emph{implicitly} a function of~$x$, or an implicit \PageSep{108} function. By bringing all the terms on one side of the equation, we may always reduce it to the form $\phi(x, y) = 0$. Thus, in the case just cited, we have $x^{2} - xy + y^{2} - a = 0$. {\Loosen We now want to deduce the differential coefficient $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$ from an equation of the form $\phi(x, y) = 0$. If we take the equation $u = \phi(x, y)$, in which when $x$~and~$y$ become $x + dx$ and $y + dy$, $u$~becomes $u + du$, we have, by our former principles,} \[ du = \ux\, dx + \uy\, dy + \etc., \text{(\PageRef{82})}, \] in which $\ux$~and~$\uy$ can be directly obtained from the equation, as in \PageRef{82}. Here $x$~and~$y$ are independent, as also $dx$~and~$dy$; whatever values are given to them, it is sufficient that $u$~and~$du$ satisfy the two last equations. But if $x$~and~$y$ must be always so taken that $u$ may~$= 0$, (which is implied in the equation $\phi(x, y) = 0$,) we have $u = 0$, and $du = 0$; and this, whatever may be the values of $dx$ and~$dy$. Hence $dx$ and~$dy$ are connected by the equation \[ 0 = \ux\, dx + \uy\, dy + \etc., \] and their limiting ratio must be obtained by the equation \[ \ux\, dx + \uy\, dy = 0, \quad\text{or}\quad \frac{dy}{dx} = -\frac{\ux}{\uy}; \] {\Loosen $y$~and~$x$ are no longer independent; for, one of them being given, the other must be so taken that the equation $\phi(x, y) = 0$ may be satisfied. The quantities $\ux$ \index{Functions!implicit and explicit}% \index{Implicit!function}% and~$\uy$ we have denoted by $\dfrac{du}{dx}$ and~$\dfrac{du}{dy}$, so that} \[ \frac{dy}{dx} = -\frac{\;\dfrac{du}{dx}\;}{\dfrac{du}{dy}}\Add{.} \Tag{(1)} \] \PageSep{109} We must again call attention to the different meanings of the same symbol~$du$ in the numerator and denominator of the last fraction. Had $du$, $dx$, and~$dy$ been common algebraical quantities, the first meaning the same thing throughout, the last equation would not have been true until the negative sign had been removed. We will give an instance in which $du$~shall mean the same thing in both. Let $u = \Chg{\phi(x)}{\phi x}$, and let $u = \psi y$, in which two equations is implied a third $\phi x = \psi y$; and $y$~is a function of~$x$. Here, $x$~being given, $u$~is known from the first equation; and $u$~being known, $y$~is known from the second. Again, $x$~and~$dx$ being given, $du$, which is $\phi(x + dx) - \phi x$ is known, and being substituted in the result of the second equation, we have $du = \psi(y + dy) - \psi y$, which $dy$~must be so taken as to satisfy. From the first equation we deduce $du = \phi'x\, dx + \etc.$\ and from the second $du = \psi' y\, dy + \etc.$, whence \[ \phi' x\, dx + \etc. = \psi' y\, dy + \etc.; \] the \emph{etc.}\ only containing terms which disappear in finding the limiting ratios. Hence, \[ \frac{dy}{dx} = \frac{\phi' x}{\psi' y} = \frac{\;\dfrac{du}{dx}\;}{\dfrac{du}{dy}}\Add{,} \Tag{(2)} \] a result in accordance with common algebra. But the equation~\Eq{(1)} was obtained from $u = \phi(x, y)$, on the supposition that $x$~and~$y$ were always so taken that $u$ should~$= 0$, while \Eq{(2)}~was obtained from $u = \Chg{\phi(x)}{\phi x}$ and $u = Sy$, in which no new supposition can be made; since one more equation between $u$,~$x$, and~$y$ would give three equations connecting these three quantities, in which case they would cease to be variable (\PageRef{106}). \PageSep{110} As an example of~\Eq{(1)} let $xy - x = 1$, or $xy - x - 1 = 0$. From $u = xy - x - 1$ we deduce (\PageRef{81}) $\dfrac{du}{dx} = y - 1$, $\dfrac{du}{dy} = x$; whence, by equation~\Eq{(1)}, \[ \frac{dy}{dx} = -\frac{y - 1}{x}. \Tag{(3)} \] By solution of $xy - x = 1$, we find $y = 1 + \dfrac{1}{x}$, and \[ dy = \left(1 + \frac{1}{x + dx}\right) - \left(1 + \frac{1}{x}\right) = -\frac{dx}{x^{2}} + \etc.\footnote{See \PageRef{26}.} \] Hence $\dfrac{dy}{dx}$ (meaning the limit) is~$-\dfrac{1}{x^{2}}$, which will also be the result of~\Eq{(3)} if $1 + \dfrac{1}{x}$ be substituted for~$y$. \Subsection{Fluxions, and the Idea of Time.} To follow this subject farther would lead us beyond \index{Time, idea of|EtSeq}% our limits; we will therefore proceed to some observations on the differential coefficient, which, at this stage of his progress, may be of use to the student, who should never take it for granted that because he has made some progress in a science, he understands the first principles, which are often, if not always, the last to be learned well. If the mind were so constituted as to receive with facility any perfectly new idea, as soon as the same was legitimately applied in mathematical demonstration, it would doubtless be an advantage not to have any notion upon a mathematical subject, previous to the time when it is to become a subject of consideration after a strictly mathematical method. This not being the case, it is a cause of embarrassment to the student, that he is introduced at once to a definition so refined as that of the limiting ratio which \PageSep{111} the increment of a function bears to the increment of its variable. Of this he has not had that previous experience, which is the case in regard to the words \emph{force}, \emph{velocity}, or \emph{length}. Nevertheless, he can easily \index{Velocity!linear}% conceive a mathematical quantity in a state of continuous increase or decrease, such as the distance between two points, one of which is in motion. The number which represents this line (reference being made to a given linear unit) is in a corresponding state of increase or decrease, and so is every function of this number, or every algebraical expression in the formation of which it is required. And the nature of the change which takes place in the function, that is, whether the function will increase or decrease when the variable increases; whether that increase or decrease corresponding to a given change in the variable will be smaller or greater, etc., depends on the manner in which the variable enters as a component part of its function. Here we want a new word, which has not been invented for the world at large, since none but mathematicians consider the subject; which word, if the change considered were change of place, depending upon change of time, would be \emph{velocity}. Newton adopted this word, and the corresponding idea, expressing many numbers in succession, instead of at once, by supposing a point to generate a straight line by its motion, which line would at different instants contain any different numbers of linear units. To this it was objected that the idea of \emph{time} is introduced, which is foreign to the subject. We may answer that the notion of time is only necessary, inasmuch as we are not able to consider more than one thing at a time. Imagine the diameter of a circle divided \PageSep{112} into a million of equal parts, from each of which a perpendicular is drawn meeting the circle. A mind which could at a view take in every one of these lines, and compare the differences between every two contiguous perpendiculars with one another, could, by subdividing the diameter still further, prove those propositions which arise from supposing a point to move uniformly along the diameter, carrying with it a perpendicular which lengthens or shortens itself so as always to have one extremity on the circle. But we, who cannot consider all these perpendiculars at once, are obliged to take one after another. If one perpendicular only were considered, and the differential coefficient of that perpendicular deduced, we might certainly appear to avoid the idea of time; but if all the states of a function are to be considered, corresponding to the different states of its variable, we have no alternative, with our bounded faculties, but to consider them in succession; and succession, disguise it as we may, is the identical idea of time introduced in Newton's Method of Fluxions. \index{Fluxions}% \Subsection{The Differential Coefficient Considered with Respect to its Magnitude.} The differential coefficient corresponding to a particular \index{Coefficients, differential}% \index{Contiguous values}% \index{Differential coefficients!as the index of the change of a function}% \index{Logarithms|EtSeq}% \index{Values!contiguous}% value of the variable, is, if we may use the phrase, the \emph{index} of the change which the function would receive if the value of the variable were increased. Every value of the variable, gives not only a different value to the function, but a different quantity of increase or decrease in passing to what we may call \emph{contiguous} values, obtained by a given increase of the variable. If, for example, we take the common logarithm of~$x$, \PageSep{113} and let $x$ be~$100$, we have common $\log 100 = 2$. If $x$~be increased by~$2$, this gives common $\log 102 = 2.0086002$, the ratio of the increment of the function \index{Increment}% to that of the variable being that of $.0086002$ to~$2$, or $.0043001$. In passing from $1000$ to~$1003$, we have the logarithms $3$ and~$3.0013009$, the above-mentioned ratio being~$.0004336$, little more than a tenth of the former. We do not take the increments themselves, but the proportion they bear to the changes in the variable which gave rise to them; so in estimating the rate of motion of two points, we either consider lengths described in the same time, or if that cannot be done, we judge, not by the lengths described in different times, but by the proportion of those lengths to the times, or the proportions of the units which express them. The above rough process, though from it some might draw the conclusion that the logarithm of~$x$ is increasing faster when $x = 100$ than when $x = 1000$, is defective; for, in passing from $100$ to~$102$, the change of the logarithm is not a sufficient index of the change which is taking place when $x$ is~$100$; since, for any thing we can be supposed to know to the contrary, the logarithm might be decreasing when $x = 100$, and might afterwards begin to increase between $x = 100$ and $x = 102$, so as, on the whole, to cause the increase above mentioned. The same objection would remain good, however small the increment might be, which we suppose $x$ to have. If, for example, we suppose $x$ to change from $x = 100$ to $x = 100.00001$, which increases the logarithm from~$2$ to~$2.00000004343$, we cannot yet say but that the logarithm may be decreasing when $x = 100$, and may begin to increase between $x = 100$ and $x = 100.00001$. \PageSep{114} In the same way, if a point is moving, so that at the end of $1$~second it is at $3$~feet from a fixed point, and at the end of $2$~seconds it is at $5$~feet from the fixed point, we cannot say which way it is moving at the end of one second. \emph{On the whole}, it increases its distance from the fixed point in the second second; but it is possible that at the end of the first second it may be moving back towards the fixed point, and may turn the contrary way during the second second. And the same argument holds, if we attempt to ascertain the way in which the point is moving by supposing any finite portion to elapse after the first second. But if on adding any interval, \emph{however small}, to the first second, the moving point does, during that interval, increase its distance from the fixed point, we can then certainly say that at the end of the first second the point is moving from the fixed point. On the same principle, we cannot say whether the logarithm of~$x$ is increasing or decreasing when $x$~increases and becomes~$100$, unless we can be sure that any increment, however small, added to~$x$, will increase the logarithm. Neither does the ratio of the increment of the function to the increment of its variable furnish any distinct idea of the change which is taking place when the variable has attained or is passing through a given value. For example, when $x$~passes from $100$ to~$102$, the difference between $\log 102$ and $\log 100$ is the united effect of all the changes which have taken place between $x = 100$ and $x = 100\frac{1}{10}$; $x = 100\frac{1}{10}$ and $x = 100\frac{2}{10}$, and so on. Again, the change which takes place between $x = 100$ and $x = 100\frac{1}{10}$ may be further compounded of those which take place between $x = 100$ and $x = 100\frac{1}{100}$; $x = 100\frac{1}{100}$ and $x = 100\frac{2}{100}$, and so on. The objection \PageSep{115} becomes of less force as the increment diminishes, but always exists unless we take the limit of the ratio of the increments, instead of that ratio. How well this answers to our previously formed ideas on such subjects as direction, velocity, and force, has already appeared. \Subsection{The Integral Calculus.} We now proceed to the Integral Calculus, which \index{Integral Calculus|EtSeq}% is the inverse of the Differential Calculus, as will afterwards appear. We have already shown, that when two functions \emph{increase} or \emph{decrease} without limit, their \emph{ratio} may either increase or decrease without limit, or may tend to some finite limit. Which of these will be the case depends upon the manner in which the functions are related to their variable and to one another. This same proposition may be put in another form, as follows: If there be two functions, the first of which \emph{decreases} without limit, on the same supposition which makes the second \emph{increase} without limit, the \emph{product} of the two may either remain finite, and never exceed a certain finite limit; or it may increase without limit, or diminish without limit. For example, take $\cos\theta$ and~$\tan\theta$. As the angle~$\theta$ \emph{approaches} a right angle, $\cos\theta$~diminishes without limit; it is nothing when $\theta$~\emph{is} a right angle; and any fraction being named, $\theta$~can be taken so near to a right angle that $\cos\theta$~shall be smaller. Again, as $\theta$~approaches to a right angle, $\tan\theta$~increases without limit; it is called \emph{infinite} when $\theta$~is a right angle, by which we mean that, let any number be named, however great, $\theta$~can be taken so near a right angle that $\tan\theta$~shall be greater. Nevertheless the product $\cos\theta × \tan\theta$, \PageSep{116} of which the first factor diminishes without limit, while the second increases without limit, is always finite, and tends towards the limit~$1$; for $\cos\theta × \tan\theta$ is always~$\sin\theta$, which last approaches to~$1$ as $\theta$~approaches to a right angle, and is~$1$ when $\theta$~\emph{is} a right angle. Generally, if $A$~diminishes without limit at the same time as $B$~increases without limit, the product~$AB$ may, and often will, tend towards a finite limit. This product~$AB$ is the representative of~$A$ divided by~$\dfrac{1}{B}$ or the ratio of $A$ to~$\dfrac{1}{B}$. If $B$~increases without limit, $\dfrac{1}{B}$~decreases without limit; and as $A$~also decreases without limit, the ratio of $A$ to~$\dfrac{1}{B}$ may have a finite limit. But it may also diminish without limit; as in the instance of $\cos^{2}\theta × \tan\theta$, when $\theta$~approaches to a right angle. Here $\cos^{2}\theta$~diminishes without limit, and $\tan\theta$~increases without limit; but $\cos^{2}\theta × \tan\theta$ being $\cos\theta × \sin\theta$, or a diminishing magnitude multiplied by one which remains finite, diminishes without limit. Or it may increase without limit, as in the case of $\cos\theta × \tan^{2}\theta$, which is also $\sin\theta × \tan\theta$; which last has one factor finite, and the other increasing without limit. We shall soon see an instance of this. If we take any numbers, such as $1$~and~$2$, it is evident that between the two we may interpose any number of fractions, however great, either in arithmetical progression, or according to any other law. Suppose, for example, we wish to interpose $9$~fractions in arithmetical progression between $1$~and~$2$. These are $1\frac{1}{10}$, $1\frac{2}{10}$,~etc., up to~$1\frac{9}{10}$; and, generally, if $m$~fractions in arithmetical progression be interposed between $a$~and~$a + h$, the complete series is \PageSep{117} \begin{multline*} a,\quad a + \frac{h}{m + 1},\quad a + \frac{2h}{m + 1},\quad \etc.\Add{,} \dots\\ \text{up to } a + \frac{mh}{m + 1},\quad a + h\Add{.} \Tag{(1)} \end{multline*} The sum of these can evidently be made as great as we please, since no one is less than the given quantity~$a$, and the number is as great as we please. Again, if we take~$\phi x$, any function of~$x$, and let the values just written be successively substituted for~$x$, we shall have the series \begin{multline*} \phi a,\quad \phi\left(a + \frac{h}{m + 1}\right),\quad \phi\left(a + \frac{2h}{m + 1}\right),\quad \etc.\Add{,} \dots\\ \text{up to } \phi(a + h); \Tag{(2)} \end{multline*} the sum of which may, in many cases, also be made as great as we please by sufficiently increasing the number of fractions interposed, that is, by sufficiently increasing~$m$. But though the two sums increase without limit when $m$~increases without limit, it does not therefore follow that their ratio increases without limit; indeed we can show that this cannot be the case when all the separate terms of~\Eq{(2)} remain finite. For let $A$~be greater than any term in~\Eq{(2)}, whence, as there are $(m + 2)$~terms, $(m + 2)A$~is greater than their sum. Again, every term of~\Eq{(1)}, except the first, being greater than~$a$, and the terms being $m + 2$~in number, $(m + 2)a$~is less than the sum of the terms in~\Eq{(1)}. Consequently, \[ \frac{(m + 2)A}{(m + 2)a} \text{ is greater than the ratio } \frac{\text{sum of terms in~\Eq{(2)}}}{\text{sum of terms in~\Eq{(1)}}}, \] since its numerator is greater than the last numerator, and its denominator less than the last denominator. But \PageSep{118} \[ \frac{(m + 2)A}{(m + 2)a} = \frac{A}{a}, \] which is independent of~$m$, and is a finite quantity. Hence the ratio of the sums of the terms is always finite, whatever may be the number of terms, at least unless the terms in~\Eq{(2)} increase without limit. As the number of interposed values increases, the interval or difference between them diminishes; if, therefore, we multiply this difference by the sum of the values, or form \begin{multline*} \frac{h}{m + 1} \Biggl[ \phi a + \phi\left(a + \frac{h}{m + 1}\right) + \\ \phi\left(a + \frac{2h}{m + 1}\right) \Add{+} \dots + \phi(a + h) \Biggr]\Add{,} \end{multline*} we have a product, one term of which diminishes, and the other increases, when $m$~is increased. The product \emph{may} therefore remain finite, or never pass a certain limit, when $m$~is increased without limit, and we shall show that this \emph{is} the case. As an example, let the given function of~$x$ be~$x^{2}$, and let the intermediate values of~$x$ be interposed between $x = a$ and $x = a + h$. Let $v = \dfrac{h}{m + 1}$, whence the above-mentioned product is \begin{multline*}%[** TN: Re-formatted from the original] v\bigl\{a^{2} + (a + v)^{2} + (a + 2v)^{2} + \dots + \bigl(a + (m + 1)v\bigr)^{2}\bigr\} \\ = (m + 2)va^{2} + 2av^{2} \{1 + 2 + 3 + \dots + (m + 1)\} \\ + v^{3} \{1^{2} + 2^{2} + 3^{2} + \dots + (m + 1)^{2}\}; \end{multline*} {\Loosen of which, $1 + 2 + \dots + (m + 1) = \frac{1}{2}(m + 1)(m + 2)$ and (\PageRef{73}), $1^{2} + 2^{2} + \dots + (m + 1)^{2}$ approaches without limit to a ratio of equality with $\frac{1}{3}(m + 1)^{3}$, when $m$~is increased without limit. Hence this last sum may be put under the form $\frac{1}{3}(m + 1)^{3} (1 + \alpha)$, \PageSep{119} where $\alpha$~diminishes without limit when $m$~is increased without limit. Making these substitutions, and putting for~$v$ its value $\dfrac{h}{m + 1}$, the above expression becomes} \[ \frac{m + 2}{m + 1}\, ha^{2} + \frac{m + 2}{m + 1}\, ha^{2} + (1 + \alpha)\, \frac{h^{3}}{3}, \] in which $\dfrac{m + 2}{m + 1}$ has the limit~$1$ when $m$~increases without limit, and $1 + \alpha$~has also the limit~$1$, since, in that case, $\alpha$~diminishes without limit. Therefore the limit of the last expression is \[ ha^{2} + ha^{2} + \frac{h^{3}}{3} \quad\text{or}\quad \frac{(a + h)^{3} - a^{3}}{3}. \] {\Loosen This result may be stated as follows: If the variable~$x$, setting out from a value~$a$, becomes successively $a + dx$, $a + 2\,dx$, etc., until the total increment is~$h$, the smaller $dx$ is taken, the more nearly will the sum of all the values of~$x^{2}\, dx$, or $a^{2}\, dx + (a + dx)^{2}\, dx + (a + 2\, dx)^{2}\, dx + \etc.$, be equal to} \[ \frac{(a + h)^{3} - a^{3}}{3}, \] and to this the aforesaid sum may be brought within any given degree of nearness, by taking $dx$ sufficiently small. This result is called the \emph{integral} of~$x^{2}\, dx$, between \index{Integral Calculus!notation of}% \index{Integrals!definition of|EtSeq}% \index{Notation!of the Integral Calculus}% the limits $a$~and~$a + h$, and is written $\int x^{2}\, dx$, when it is not necessary to specify the limits, $\int_{a}^{a+h} x^{2}\, dx$, or\footnote {This notation $\int x^{2}\, dx\Ibar_{a}^{a+h}$ appears to me to avoid the objections which may be raised against $\int_{a+h}^{a} x^{2}\, dx$ as contrary to analogy, which would require that $\int^{2} x^{2}\, dx^{2}$ should stand for the second integral of~$x^{2}\, dx$. It will be found convenient in such integrals as $\int z\, dx\Ibar_{b}^{a}\, dy\Ibar_{0}^{\phi x}$. There is as yet no general agreement on this point of notation.---\textit{De~Morgan}, 1832.} $\int x^{2}\, dx\Ibar_{a}^{a+h}$, or $\int x^{2}\, dx\Ibar_{x=a}^{x=a+h}$ in the contrary case. We \PageSep{120} now proceed to show the connexion of this process with the principles of the Differential Calculus. \Subsection{Connexion of the Integral with the Differential Calculus.} Let $x$ have the successive values $a$, $a + dx$, $a + 2\, dx$, etc.,~\dots\ up to $a + m\, dx$, or $a + h$, $h$~being a given quantity, and $dx$ the $m$\th~part of~$h$, so that as $m$~is increased without limit, $dx$~is diminished without limit. Develop the successive values $\phi x$, or $\phi a$, $\phi(a + dx)$\Add{,}~\dots\ (\PageRef{21}),\par {\footnotesize\begin{alignat*}{6} & \phi a &&= \phi a\Add{,} \\ &\phi(a + dx) &&= \phi a &&+ \phi' a\, dx &&+ \phi'' a\, \frac{(dx)^{2}}{2} &&+ \phi''' a\, \frac{(dx)^{3}}{2·3} &&+ \etc.\Add{,} \displaybreak[0] \\ &\phi(a + 2\, dx) &&= \phi a &&+ \phi' a\, 2\, dx &&+ \phi'' a\, \frac{(2\, dx)^{2}}{2} &&+ \phi''' a\, \frac{(2\, dx)^{3}}{2·3} &&+ \etc.\Add{,} \displaybreak[0] \\ &\phi(a + 3\, dx) &&= \phi a &&+ \phi' a\, 3\, dx &&+ \phi'' a\, \frac{(3\, dx)^{2}}{2} &&+ \phi''' a\, \frac{(3\, dx)^{3}}{2·3} &&+ \etc.\Add{,} \\ \DotRow{12} \\ &\phi(a + m\, dx) &&= \phi a &&+ \phi' a\, m\, dx &&+ \phi'' a\, \frac{(m\, dx)^{2}}{2} &&+ \phi''' a\, \frac{(m\, dx)^{3}}{2·3} &&+ \etc. \end{alignat*}}% If we multiply each development by~$dx$ and add the results, we have a series made up of the following terms, arising from the different columns, \begin{alignat*}{7} &\phi a &&×{} && && && && && \phantom{()}m\, dx\Add{,} \\ &\phi' a &&× (1 &&+ 2 &&+ 3 &&+ \dots &&+ m &&)\, (dx)^{2}\Add{,} \\ &\phi'' a &&× (1^{2} &&+ 2^{2} &&+ 3^{2} &&+ \dots &&+ m^{2} &&)\, \frac{(dx)^{3}}{2}\Add{,} \\ &\phi''' a &&× (1^{3} &&+ 2^{3} &&+ 3^{3} &&+ \dots &&+ m^{3} &&)\, \frac{(dx)^{4}}{2·3} \quad \etc.\Add{,} \end{alignat*} and, as in the last example, we may represent (\PageRef{73}), \begin{alignat*}{6} &1 &&+ 2 &&+ 3 &&+ \dots &&+ m &&\text{by}\quad \tfrac{1}{2}m^{2}(1 + \alpha)\Add{,} \displaybreak[0] \\ &1^{2} &&+ 2^{2} &&+ 3^{2} &&+ \dots &&+ m^{2} &&\text{by}\quad \tfrac{1}{3}m^{3}(1 + \beta)\Add{,} \displaybreak[0] \\ &1^{3} &&+ 2^{3} &&+ 3^{3} &&+ \dots &&+ m^{3}\quad &&\text{by}\quad \tfrac{1}{4}m^{4}(1 + \gamma) \quad \etc.\Add{,} \end{alignat*} \PageSep{121} where $\alpha$,~$\beta$,~$\gamma$, etc., diminish without limit, when $m$~is increased without limit. If we substitute these values, and also put $\dfrac{h}{m}$ instead of~$dx$, we have, for the sum of the terms, \begin{align*} \phi a\, h + \phi' a\, \frac{h^{2}}{2} (1 + \alpha) &+ \phi'' a\, \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} (1 + \beta) \\ &+ \phi''' a\, \frac{h^{4}}{2·3·4} (1 + \gamma) + \etc. \end{align*} which, when $m$~is increased without limit, in consequence of which $\alpha$,~$\beta$,~etc., diminish without limit, continually approaches to \[ \phi a\, h + \phi' a\, \frac{h^{2}}{2} + \phi'' a\, \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} + \phi''' a\, \frac{h^{4}}{2·3·4} + \etc.\Add{,} \] which is the limit arising from supposing $x$ to increase from~$a$ through $a + dx$, $a + 2\, dx$, etc., up to~$a + h$, multiplying every value of~$\phi x$ so obtained by~$dx$, summing the results, and decreasing~$dx$ without limit. This is the integral of $\phi x\, dx$ from $x = a$ to $x = a + h$. \index{Integrals!relations between differential coefficients and}% It is evident that this series bears a great resemblance to the development in \PageRef{21}, deprived of its first term. Let us suppose that $\psi a$~is the function of which $\phi a$~is the differential coefficient, that is, that $\psi' a = \phi a$. These two functions being the same, their differential coefficients will be the same, that is, $\psi'' a = \phi' a$. Similarly $\psi''' a = \phi'' a$, and so on. Substituting these, the above series becomes \[ \psi' a\, h + \psi'' a\, \frac{h^{2}}{2} + \psi''' a\, \frac{h^{3}}{2·3} + \psi^{\text{iv}} a\, \frac{h^{4}}{2·3·4} + \etc.\Add{,} \] {\Loosen which is (\PageRef{21}) the same as $\psi(a + h) - \psi a$. That is, the integral of $\phi x\, dx$ between the limits $a$~and~$a + h$, is $\psi(a + h) - \psi a$, where $\psi x$~is the function, which, \PageSep{122} when differentiated, gives~$\phi x$. For $a + h$ we may write~$b$, so that $\psi b - \psi a$ is the integral of~$\phi x\, dx$ from $x = a$ to $x = b$. Or we may make the second limit indefinite by writing~$x$ instead of~$b$, which gives $\psi x - \psi a$, which is said to be the integral of~$\phi x\, dx$, beginning when $x = a$, the summation being supposed to be continued from $x = a$ until $x$~has the value which it may be convenient to give it.} \Subsection{Nature of Integration.} Hence results a new branch of the inquiry, the reverse of the Differential Calculus, the object of which is, not to find the differential coefficient, having given the function, but to find the function, having given the differential coefficient. This is called the Integral Calculus. From the definition given, it is obvious that the value of an integral is not to be determined, unless we know the values of~$x$ corresponding to the beginning and end of the summation, whose limit furnishes the integral. We might, instead of defining the integral in the manner above stated, have made the word mean merely the converse of the differential coefficient; thus, if $\phi x$~be the differential coefficient of~$\psi x$, $\psi x$~might have been called the integral of~$\phi x\, dx$. We should then have had to show that the integral, thus defined, is equivalent to the limit of the summation already explained. We have preferred bringing the former method before the student first, as it is most analogous to the manner in which he will deduce integrals in questions of geometry or mechanics. \index{Integrals!indefinite}% With the last-mentioned definition, it is also obvious that every function has an unlimited number of integrals. For whatever differential coefficient~$\psi x$ \PageSep{123} gives, $C + \psi x$ will give the same, if $C$~be a constant, that is, not varying when $x$~varies. In this case, if $x$ become $x + h$, $C + \psi x$ becomes $C + \psi x + \psi' x\, h + \etc.$, from which the subtraction of the original form $C + \psi x$ gives $\psi' x\, h + \etc.$; whence, by the process in \PageRef{23}, $\psi' x$~is the differential coefficient of $C + \psi' x$ as well as of~$\psi x$. As many values, therefore, positive or negative, as can be given to~$C$, so many different integrals \index{Integrals!indefinite}% can be found for~$\psi' x$; and these answer to the various limits between which the summation in our original definition may be made. To make this problem definite, not only $\psi' x$ the function to be integrated, must be given, but also that value of~$x$ from which the summation is to begin. If this be~$a$, the integral of~$\psi' x$ is, as before determined, $\psi x - \psi a$, and $C = -\psi a$. We may afterwards end at any value of~$x$ which we please. If $x = a$, $\psi x - \psi a = 0$, as is evident also from the formation of the integral. We may thus, having given an integral in terms of~$x$, find the value at which it began, by equating the integral to zero, and finding the value of~$x$. Thus, since $x^{2}$, when differentiated, gives~$2x$, $x^{2}$~is the integral of~$2x$, beginning at $x = 0$; and $x^{2} - 4$~is the integral beginning at~$x = 2$. In the language of Leibnitz, an integral would be \index{Leibnitz}% the sum of an infinite number of infinitely small quantities, which are the differentials or infinitely small increments of a function. Thus, a circle being, according to him, a rectilinear polygon of an infinite number of infinitely small sides, the sum of these would be the circumference of the figure. As before (\PageRefs{13}{14}, \PageNo{38}~et~seq., \PageNo{48}~et~seq.) we proceed to interpret this inaccuracy of language. If, in a circle, we successively describe regular polygons of $3$,~$4$, $5$,~$6$,~etc., sides, we may, by this means, at last attain to a polygon \PageSep{124} whose side shall differ from the arc of which it is the chord, by as small a fraction, either of the chord or arc, as we please (\PageRefs{7}{11}). That is, $A$~being the arc, $C$~the chord, and $D$~their difference, there is no fraction so small that $D$~cannot be made a smaller part of~$C$. Hence, if $m$~be the number of sides of the polygon, $mC + mD$ or $mA$ is the real circumference; and since $mD$~is the same part of~$mC$, which $D$~is of~$C$, $mD$~may be made as small a part of~$mC$ as we please; so that $mC$, or the sum of all the sides of the polygon, can be made as nearly equal to the circumference as we please. As in other cases, the expressions of Leibnitz are \index{Leibnitz}% the most convenient and the shortest, for all who can immediately put a rational construction upon them; this, and the fact that, good or bad, they have been, and are, used in the works of Lagrange, Laplace, \index{Lagrange}% \index{Laplace}% Euler, and many others, which the student who really \index{Euler}% desires to know the present state of physical science, cannot dispense with, must be our excuse for continually bringing before him modes of speech, which, taken quite literally, are absurd. \Subsection{Determination of Curvilinear Areas. The Parabola.} We will now suppose such a part of a curve, each \index{Curvilinear areas, determination of|EtSeq}% \index{Parabola, the|EtSeq}% ordinate of which is a given function of the corresponding abscissa, as lies between two given ordinates; for example,~$MPP'M'$. Divide the line~$MM'$ into a number of equal parts, which we may suppose as great as we please, and construct \Fig[Figure]{10}. Let $O$~be the origin of co-ordinates, and let $OM$, the value of~$x$, at which we begin, be~$a$; and $OM'$, the value at which we end, be~$b$. Though we have only divided~$MM'$ \PageSep{125} into four equal parts in the figure, the reasoning to which we proceed would apply equally, had we divided it into four million of parts. The sum of the parallelograms $Mr$,~$mr$,~$m'r''$, and~$m''R$, is less than the area~$MPP'M'$, the value of which it is our object to investigate, by the sum of the curvilinear triangles $Prp$,~$pr'p'$,~$p'r''p''$, and~$p''RP'$. The sum of these triangles is less than the sum of the parallelograms $Qr$,~$qr'$,~$q'r''$, and~$q''R$; but these parallelograms are together \Figure{10} equal to the parallelogram~$q''w$, as appears by inspection of the figure, since the base of each of the above-mentioned parallelograms is equal to~$m''M$, or~$q''P'$, and the altitude~$P'w$ is equal to the sum of the altitudes of the same parallelograms. Hence the sum of the parallelograms $Mr$,~$mr'$,~$m'r''$, and~$m''R$, differs from the curvilinear area~$MPP'M'$ by less than the parallelogram~$q''w$. But this last parallelogram may be made as small as we please by sufficiently increasing the number of parts into which $MM'$~is divided; \PageSep{126} for since one side of it,~$P'w$, is always less than~$P'M'$, and the other side~$P'q''$, or~$m''M'$, is as small a part as we please of~$MM'$ the number of square units in~$q''w$, is the product of the number of linear units in $P'w$ and~$P'q''$, the first of which numbers being finite, and the second as small as we please, the product is as small as we please. Hence the curvilinear area~$MPP'M'$ is the limit towards which we continually approach, but which we never reach, by dividing $MM'$ into a greater and greater number of equal parts, and adding the parallelograms $Mr$,~$mr'$,~etc., so obtained. If each of the equal parts into which $MM'$ is divided be called~$dx$, we have $OM = a$, $Om = a + dx$, $Om' = a + 2\,dx$, etc. And $MP$,~$mp$, $m'p'$,~etc., are the values of the function which expresses the ordinates, corresponding to $a$,~$a + dx$, $a + 2\, dx$,~etc., and may therefore be represented by $\phi a$, $\phi(a + dx)$, $\phi(a + 2\, dx)$, etc. These are the altitudes of a set of parallelograms, the base of each of which is~$dx$; hence the sum of their area is \[ \phi a\, dx + \phi(a + dx)\, dx + \phi(a + 2\, dx)\, dx + \etc., \] and the limit of this, to which we approach by diminishing~$dx$, is the area required. This limit is what we have defined to be the integral of~$\phi x\, dx$ from $x = a$ to $x = b$; or if $\psi x$~be the function, which, when differentiated, gives $\phi x$, it is $\psi b - \psi a$. Hence, $y$~being the ordinate, the area included between the axis of~$x$, any two values of~$y$, and the portion of the curve they cut off, is $\int y\, dx$, beginning at the one ordinate and ending at the other. Suppose that the curve is a part of a parabola of which $O$~is the vertex, and whose equation\footnote {If the student has not any acquaintance with the conic sections, he must nevertheless be aware that there is some curve whose abscissa and ordinate are connected by the equation $y^{2} = px$. This, to him, must be the definition of \emph{parabola}: by which word he must understand, a curve whose equation is $y^{2} = px$.} is \PageSep{127} therefore $y^{2} = px$ where $p$~is the double ordinate which passes through the focus. Here $y = p^{\efrac{1}{2}} x^{\efrac{1}{2}}$, and we must find the integral of~$p^{\efrac{1}{2}} x^{\efrac{1}{2}}\, dx$, or the function whose differential coefficient is~$p^{\efrac{1}{2}} x^{\efrac{1}{2}}$, $p^{\efrac{1}{2}}$~being a constant. If we take the function~$cx^{n}$, $c$~being independent of~$x$, and substitute $x + h$ for~$x$, we have for the development $cx^{n} + cnx^{n-1}\, h + \etc$. Hence the differential coefficient of~$cx^{n}$ is~$cnx^{n-1}$; and as $c$~and~$n$ may be any numbers or fractions we please, we may take them such that $cn$~shall $= p^{\efrac{1}{2}}$ and $n - 1 = \frac{1}{2}$, in which case $n = \frac{3}{2}$ and $c = \frac{2}{3}p^{\efrac{1}{2}}$. Therefore the differential coefficient of~$\frac{2}{3} p^{\efrac{1}{2}} x^{\efrac{3}{2}}$ is~$p^{\efrac{1}{2}} x^{\efrac{1}{2}}$, and conversely, the integral of~$p^{\efrac{1}{2}} x^{\efrac{1}{2}}\, dx$ is~$\frac{2}{3} p^{\efrac{1}{2}} x^{\efrac{3}{2}}$. {\Loosen The area~$MPP'M'$ of the parabola is therefore \index{Parabola, the}% ~$\frac{2}{3} p^{\efrac{1}{2}} b^{\efrac{3}{2}} - \frac{2}{3} p^{\efrac{1}{2}} a^{\efrac{3}{2}}$. If we begin the integral at the vertex~$O$, in which case $a = 0$, we have for the area~$OM'P'$, $\frac{2}{3} p^{\efrac{1}{2}} b^{\efrac{3}{2}}$, where $b = OM'$. This is~$\frac{2}{3} p^{\efrac{1}{2}} b^{\efrac{1}{2}} × b$, which, since $p^{\efrac{1}{2}} b^{\efrac{1}{2}} = M'P'$ is $\frac{2}{3}P'M' × OM'$, or two-thirds of the rectangle\footnote {This proposition is famous as having been discovered by Archimedes \index{Archimedes}% at a time when such a step was one of no small magnitude.} contained by $OM'$~and~$M'P'$.} \Subsection{Method of Indivisibles.} We may mention, in illustration of the preceding \index{Indivisibles!method of|EtSeq}% problem, a method of establishing the principles of the Integral Calculus, which generally goes by the name of the \emph{Method of Indivisibles}. A line is considered as the sum of an infinite number of points, a surface of an infinite number of lines, and a solid of an infinite number of surfaces. One line twice as long as another would be said to contain twice as many \PageSep{128} points, though the number of points in each is unlimited. To this there are two objections. First, the word infinite, in this absolute sense, really has no \index{Infinite@\emph{Infinite}, the word}% meaning, since it will be admitted that the mind has no conception of a number greater than any number. The word infinite\footnote {See \Title{Study of Mathematics} (Chicago: The Open Court Publishing~Co\Add{.}), page~123 et~seq.} can only be justifiably used as an abbreviation of a distinct and intelligible proposition; for example, when we say that $a + \dfrac{1}{x}$ is equal to~$a$ when $x$~is infinite, we only mean that as $x$ is increased, $a + \dfrac{1}{x}$~becomes nearer to~$a$, and may be made as near to it as we please, if $x$~may be as great as we please. The second objection is, that the notion of a line being the sum of a number of points is not true, nor does it approach nearer the truth as we increase the number of points. If twenty points be taken on a straight line, the sum of the twenty-one lines which lie between point and point is equal to the whole line; which cannot be if the points by themselves constitute any part of the line, however small. Nor will the sum of the points be a part of the line, if twenty thousand be taken instead of twenty. There is then, in this method, neither the rigor of geometry, nor that approach to truth, which, in the method of Leibnitz, \index{Leibnitz}% may be carried to any extent we please, short of absolute correctness. We would therefore recommend to the student not to regard any proposition derived from this method as true on that account; for falsehoods, as well as truths, may be deduced from it. Indeed, the primary notion, that the number of points in a line is proportional to its length, is manifestly incorrect. Suppose (\Fig{6}, \PageRef{48}) that the point~$Q$ \PageSep{129} moves from $A$ to~$P$. It is evident that in whatever number of points $OQ$ cuts~$AP$, it cuts~$MP$ in the same number. But $PM$~and~$PA$ are not equal. A defender of the system of indivisibles, if there were such a person, \index{Indivisibles!notion of, in mechanics|EtSeq}% would say something equivalent to supposing that the points on the two lines are of \emph{different sizes}, which would, in fact, be an abandonment of the method, and an adoption of the idea of Leibnitz, using \index{Leibnitz}% the word \emph{point} to stand for the infinitely small \index{Point@\emph{Point}, the word}% line. This notion of indivisibles, or at least a way of speaking which looks like it, prevails in many works on mechanics. Though a point is not treated as a length, or as any part of space whatever, it is considered as having weight; and two points are spoken of as having different weights. The same is said of a line and a surface, neither of which can correctly be supposed to possess weight. If a solid be of the same density throughout, that is, if the weight of a cubic inch of it be the same from whatever part it is cut, it is plain that the weight may be found by finding the number of cubic inches in the whole, and multiplying this number by the weight of one cubic inch. But if the weight of every two cubic inches is different, we can only find the weight of the whole by the integral calculus. Let $AB$ (\Fig{11}) be a line possessing weight, or \index{Points, the number of, in a straight line}% a very thin parallelepiped of matter, which is such, that if we were to divide it into any number of equal parts, as in the figure, the weight of the several parts would be different. We suppose the weight to vary continuously, that is, if two contiguous parts of equal length be taken, as $pq$~and~$qr$, the ratio of the weights \PageSep{130} of these two parts may, by taking them sufficiently small, be as near to equality as we please. The \emph{density} of a body is a mathematical term, which \index{Density, continuously varying|EtSeq}% \index{Specific gravity, continuously varying|EtSeq}% may be explained as follows: A cubic inch of gold weighs more than a cubic inch of water; hence gold is \emph{denser} than water. If the first weighs $19$~times as much as the second, gold is said to be $19$~times more dense than water, or the density of gold is $19$~times that of water. Hence we might define the density by the weight of a cubic inch of the substance, but it is usual to take, not this weight, but the proportion which it bears to the same weight of water. Thus, when we say the \emph{density}, or \emph{specific gravity} (these terms are used indifferently), of cast iron is~$7.207$, we mean \index{Iron bar continually varying in density, weight of|EtSeq}% \index{Weight of an iron bar of which the density varies from point to point|EtSeq}% that if any vessel of pure water were emptied and filled with cast iron, the iron would weigh $7.207$~times as much as the water. If the density of a body were uniform throughout, we might easily determine it by dividing the weight of any bulk of the body, by the weight of an equal bulk of water. In the same manner (\PageRef[pages]{52} et~seq.)\ we could, from our definition of velocity, determine any uniform velocity by dividing the length described by the time. But if the density vary continuously, no such measure can be adopted. For if by the side of~$AB$ (which we will suppose to be of iron) we placed a similar body of water similarly divided, and if we divided the weight of the part~$pq$ of iron by the weight of the same part of water, we should get different densities, according as the part~$pq$ is longer or shorter. The water is supposed to be homogeneous, that is, any part of it~$pr$, being twice the length of~$pq$, is twice the weight of~$pq$, and so on. The iron, on the contrary, being supposed to vary in density, the doubling \PageSep{131} the length gives either more or less than twice the weight. But if we suppose $q$ to move towards~$p$, both on the iron and the water, the limit of the ratio~$pq$ of iron to $pq$~of water, may be chosen as a measure of the density of~$p$, on the same principle as in \PageRefs{54}{55}, the limit of the ratio of the length described to the time of describing it, was called the velocity. If we call $k$ this limit, and if the weight varies continuously, though no part~$pq$, however small, of iron, would be exactly $k$~times the same part of water in weight, we may nevertheless take $pq$ so small that these weights shall be as nearly as we please in the ratio of $k$~to~$1$. Let us now suppose that this density, expressed by the limiting ratio aforesaid, is always $x^{2}$ at any \Figure{11} point whose distance from~$A$ is $x$~feet; that is, the density at~$q$, $2$~feet distance from~$A$, is~$4$, and so on. Let the whole distance $AB = a$. If we divide~$a$ into $n$~equal parts, each of which is~$dx$, so that $n\, dx = a$, and if we call~$b$ the area of the section of the parallelepiped, ($b$~being a fraction of a square foot,) the solid content of each of the parts will be $b\, dx$ in cubic feet; and if $w$~be the weight of a cubic foot of water, the weight of the same bulk of water will be~$wb\, dx$. If the solid~$AB$ were homogeneous in the immediate neighborhood of the point~$p$, the density being then~$x^{2}$, would give $x^{2} × bw\, dx$ for the weight of the same part of the substance. This is not true, but can be brought as near to the truth as we please, by taking $dx$ sufficiently small, or dividing~$AB$ into a sufficient \PageSep{132} number of parts. Hence the real weight of~$pq$ may be represented by $bwx^{2}\, dx + \alpha$, where $\alpha$~may be made as small a part as we please of the term which precedes it. In the sum of any number of these terms, the sum arising from the term~$\alpha$ diminishes without limit as compared with the sum arising from the term~$bwx^{2}\, dx$; for if $\alpha$~be less than the thousandth part of~$p$, $\alpha'$~less than the thousandth part of~$p'$, etc., then $\alpha + \alpha' + \etc$.\ will be less than the thousandth part of~$p + p' + \etc.$: which is also true of any number of quantities, and of any fraction, however small, which each term of one set is of its corresponding term in the other. Hence the taking of the integral of~$bwx^{2}\, dx$ dispenses with the necessity of considering the term~$\alpha$; for in taking the integral, we find a limit which supposes $dx$ to have decreased without limit, and the \emph{integral} which would arise from~$\alpha$ has therefore diminished without limit. The integral of~$bwx^{2}\, dx$ is~$\frac{1}{3}bwx^{3}$, which taken from $x = 0$ to $x = a$ is~$\frac{1}{3}bwa^{3}$. This is therefore the weight in pounds of the bar whose length is $a$~feet, and whose section is $b$~square feet, when the density at any point distant by $x$~feet from the beginning is~$x^{2}$; $w$~being the weight in pounds of a cubic foot of water. \Subsection{Concluding Remarks on the Study of the Calculus.} We would recommend it to the student, in pursuing \index{Advice for studying the Calculus}% \index{Approximate solutions in the Integral Calculus}% \index{Rough methods of solution in the Integral Calculus}% any problem of the Integral Calculus, never for one moment to lose sight of the manner in which he would do it, if a rough solution for practical purposes only were required. Thus, if he has the area of a curve to find, instead of merely saying that~$y$, the ordinate, being a certain function of the abscissa~$x$, \PageSep{133} $\int y\, dx$ within the given limits would be the area required; and then proceeding to the mechanical solution of the question: let him remark that if an approximate solution only were required, it might be obtained by dividing the curvilinear area into a number of four-sided figures, as in \Fig[Figure]{10}, one side of which only is curvilinear, and embracing so small an arc that it may, without visible error, be considered as rectilinear. The mathematical method begins with the same principle, investigating upon this supposition, not the sum of these rectilinear areas, but the limit towards which this sum approaches, as the subdivision is rendered more minute. This limit is shown to be that of which we are in search, since it is proved that the error diminishes without limit, as the subdivision is indefinitely continued. We now leave our reader to any elementary work which may fall in his way, having done our best to place before him those considerations, something equivalent to which he must turn over in his mind before he can understand the subject. The method so generally followed in our elementary works, of leading the student at once into the mechanical processes of the science, postponing entirely all other considerations, is to many students a source of obscurity at least, if not an absolute impediment to their progress; since they cannot imagine what is the object of that which they are required to do. That they shall understand everything contained in these treatises, on the first or second reading, we cannot promise; but that the want of illustration and the preponderance of \emph{technical} reasoning are the great causes of the difficulties which students experience, is the opinion of many \index{Advice for studying the Calculus}% \index{Approximate solutions in the Integral Calculus}% \index{Rough methods of solution in the Integral Calculus}% who have had experience in teaching this subject. \PageSep{134} %[Blank page] \PageSep{135} \BackMatter \Section[Bibliography of Standard Text-books and Works of Reference on the Calculus] {Brief Bibliography.\protect\footnotemark} \footnotetext{The information given regarding the works mentioned in this list is designed to enable the reader to select the books which are best suited to his needs and his purse. Where the titles do not sufficiently indicate the character of the books, a note or extract from the Preface has been added. The American prices have been supplied by Messrs.\ Lemcke \&~Buechner, 812~Broadway, New~York, through whom the purchases, especially of the foreign books, may be conveniently made.---\Ed.} \BibSect{Standard Text-books and Treatises on the Calculus.} \BibSubsect{English.} \begin{Book} Perry, John: \Title{Calculus for Engineers.} Second edition, London and New York: Edward Arnold. 1897. Price, \Price{7s. 6d.} (\$2.50). \begin{Descrip} Extract from Author's Preface: ``This book describes what has for many years been the most important part of the regular course in the Calculus for Mechanical and Electrical Engineering students at the Finsbury Technical College. The students in October knew only the most elementary mathematics, many of them did not know the Binomial Theorem, or the definition of the sine of an angle. In July they had not only done the work of this book, but their knowledge was of a practical kind, ready for use in any such engineering problems as I give here.'' Especially good in the character and number of practical examples given. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Lamb, Horace: \Title{Infinitesimal Calculus.} New York: The Macmillan Co. 1898. Price,~\$3.00. \begin{Descrip} Extract from Author's Preface: ``This book attempts to teach those portions of the Calculus which are of primary importance in the application to such subjects as Physics and Engineering\dots. Stress is laid on fundamental principles\dots. Considerable attention has been paid to the logic of the subject.'' \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \PageSep{136} \begin{Book} Edwards, Joseph: \Title{An Elementary Treatise on the Differential Calculus.} Second edition, revised. 8vo,~cloth. New York and London: The Macmillan~Co. 1892. Price, \$3.50.---% \Title{Differential Calculus for Beginners.} 8vo,~cloth. 1893.\Chg{ }{---}\Title{The Integral Calculus for Beginners.} 8vo,~cloth. (Same Publishers.) Price, \$1.10~each. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Byerly, William E.: \Title{Elements of the Differential Calculus.} Boston: Ginn \&~Co. Price, \$2.15.---\Title{Elements of the Integral Calculus.} (Same Publishers.) Price,~\$2.15. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Rice, J.~M., and Johnson, W.~W.: \Title{An Elementary Treatise on the Differential Calculus Founded on the Method of Rates or Fluxions.} New~York: John Wiley \&~Sons. 8vo. 1884. Price, \$3.50. Abridged edition, 1889. Price,~\$1.50. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Johnson, W.~W.: \Title{Elementary Treatise on the Integral Calculus Founded on the Method of Rates or Fluxions.} 8vo,~cloth. New~York: John Wiley \&~Sons. 1885. Price,~\$1.50. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Greenhill, A.~G.: \Title{Differential and Integral Calculus.} With applications. 8vo,~cloth. Second edition. New~York and London: The Macmillan~Co. 1891. Price, \Price{9s.}~(\$2.60). \end{Book} \begin{Book} Price: \Title{Infinitesimal Calculus.} Four Vols. 1857--65. Out of print and very scarce. Obtainable for about~\$27.00. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Smith, William Benjamin: \Title{Infinitesimal Analysis.} Vol.~I., Elementary: Real Variables. New~York and London: The Macmillan~Co. 1898. Price,~\$3.25. \begin{Descrip} ``The aim has been, within a prescribed expense of time and energy to penetrate as far as possible, and in as many directions, into the subject in hand,---that the student should attain as wide knowledge of the matter, as full comprehension of the methods, and as clear consciousness of the spirit and power of analysis as the nature of the case would admit.''---From Author's Preface. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Todhunter, Isaac: \Title{A Treatise on the Differential Calculus.} London and New~York: The Macmillan~Co. Price, \Price{10s. 6d.} (\$2.60). \Title{A Treatise on the Integral Calculus.} (Same publishers.) Price, \Price{10s. 6d.} (\$2\Chg{ }{.}60). \begin{Descrip} Todhunter's text-books were, until recently, the most widely used in England. His works on the Calculus still retain their standard character, as general manuals. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \PageSep{137} \begin{Book} Williamson: \Title{Differential and Integral Calculus.} London and New~York: Longmans, Green, \&~Co. 1872--1874. Two~Vols. Price, \$3.50~each. \end{Book} \begin{Book} De~Morgan, Augustus: \Title{Differential and Integral Calculus.} London: Society for the Diffusion of Useful Knowledge. 1842. Out of print. About~\$6.40. \begin{Descrip} The most extensive and complete work in English. ``The object has been to contain within the prescribed limits, the whole of the students' course from the confines of elementary algebra and trigonometry, to the entrance of the highest works on mathematical physics'' (Author's Preface). Few examples. In typography, and general arrangement of material, inferior to the best recent works. Valuable for collateral study, and for its philosophical spirit. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \BibSubsect{French.} \begin{Book} Sturm: \Title{Cours d'analyse de l'École Polytechnique.} 10.~édition, revue et corrigé par E.~Prouhet, et augmentée de~la théorie élémentaire des fonctions elliptiques, par H.~Laurent. 2~volumes in---8. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1895. Bound, 16~fr.\ 50~c. \$4.95. \begin{Descrip} One of the most widely used of text-books. First published in 1857. The new tenth edition has been thoroughly revised and brought down to date. The exercises, while not numerous, are sufficient, those which accompany the additions and complementary chapters of M.~De~Saint Germain having been taken from the Collection of M.~Tisserand, mentioned below. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Duhamel: \Title{Éléments de calcul infinitésimal.} 4.~Edition, revue et annotée par J.~Bertrand. 2~volumes in---8; avec planches. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1886. 15~fr. \$4.50. \begin{Descrip} The first edition was published between 1840 and 1841. ``Cordially recommended to teachers and students'' by De~Morgan. Duhamel paid great attention to the philosophy and logic of the mathematical sciences, and the student may also be referred in this connexion to his \Title{Méthodes dans les sciences de raisonnement}. 5~volumes. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. Price, 25.50~francs. \$7.65. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Lacroix, S.-F.: \Title{Traité élémentaire de calcul différentiel et de calcul intégral.} 9.~Edition, revue et augmentée de notes par Hermite et Serret. 2~vols. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1881. 15~fr. \$4.50. \begin{Descrip} A very old work. The first edition was published in 1797. It was the standard treatise during the early part of the century, and has been kept revised by competent hands. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \PageSep{138} \begin{Book} Appell, P.; \Title{Éléments d'analyse mathématique.} À l'usage des ingénieurs et dés physiciens. Cours professé à l'École Centrale des Arts et Manufactures. 1~vol.\ in---8, 720~pages, avec figures, cartonné à l'anglaise. Paris: Georges Carré \&~C. Naud. 1899. Price, 24~francs.\ \$7.20. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Boussinesq, J.: \Title{Cours d'analyse infinitésimal.} À l'usage des personnes qui étudient cette science en vue de ses applications mécaniques et physiques, 2~vols., grand in\Chg{-}{---}8, avec figures. Tome~I\@. Calcul différentiel. Paris, 1887. 17~fr.\ (\$5.10). Tome~II\@. Calcul intégral. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1890. 23~fr.\ 50~c.\ (\$7.05). \end{Book} \begin{Book} Hermite, Ch.: \Title{Cours d'analyse de l'École Polytechnique.} 2~vols. Vol.~I\@. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1897. \begin{Descrip} A new edition of Vol.~I. is in preparation (1899). Vol.~II. has not yet appeared. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Jordan, Camille: \Title{Cours d'analyse de l'École Polytechnique.} 3~volumes. 2.~édition. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1893--1898. 51~fr.\ \$14.70. \begin{Descrip} Very comprehensive on the theoretical side. Enters deeply into the metaphysical aspects of the subject. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Laurent, H.: \Title{Traité d'analyse.} 7~vols in---8. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1885--1891. 73~fr.\ \$21.90. \begin{Descrip} The most extensive existing treatise on the Calculus. A general handbook and work of reference for the results contained in the more special works and memoirs. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Picard, Émile: \Title{Traité d'analyse.} 4~volumes grand in\Chg{-}{---}8. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1891. 15~fr.\ each. Vols.~I.--III., \$14.40. Vol.~IV. has not yet appeared. \begin{Descrip} An advanced treatise on the Integral Calculus and the theory of differential equations. Presupposes a knowledge of the Differential Calculus. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Serret, J.-A.: \Title{Cours de calcul différentiel et intégral.} 4.~edition, augmentée d'une note sur les fonctions elliptiques, par Ch.~Hermite. 2~forts volumes in---8. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1894. 25~fr.\ \$7.50. \begin{Descrip} A good German translation of this work by Axel Harnack has passed through its second edition (Leipsic: Teubner, 1885 and 1897). \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \PageSep{139} \begin{Book} Hoüel, J.: \Title{Cours de calcul infinitésimal.} 4~beaux volumes grand in---8, avec figures. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1878--1879--1880--1881. 50~fr.\ \$15.00. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Bertrand, J.: \Title{Traité de calcul différentiel et de calcul intégral.} (1)~Calcul différentiel. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et fils. 1864. Scarce. About \$48.00. (2)~Calcul intégral (Intégrales définies et indéfinies). Paris, 1870. Scarce. About \$24.00. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Boucharlat, J.-L.: \Title{Éléments de calcul différentiel et de calcul intégral.} 9.~édition, revue et annotée par H.~Laurent. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1891. 8~fr.\ \$2.40. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Moigno: \Title{Leçons de calcul différentiel et de calcul intégral\Typo{,}{.}} 2~vols., Paris, 1840--1844. Scarce. About \$9.60. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Navier: \Title{Leçons d'analyse de l'École Polytechnique.} Paris, 1840. 2nd~ed. 1856. Out of print. About \$3.60. \begin{Descrip} An able and practical work. Very popular in its day. The typical course of the \textit{École Polytechnique}, and the basis of several of the treatises that followed, including that of Sturm. Also much used in its German translation. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Cournot: \Title{Théorie des fonctions et du calcul infinitésimal.} 2~vols. Paris, 1841. 2nd~ed. 1856--1858. Out of print, and scarce. About \$3.00. \begin{Descrip} The first edition (1841) was ``cordially recommended to teachers and students'' by De~Morgan. Cournot was especially strong on the philosophical side. He examined the foundations of many sciences and developed original views on the theory of knowledge, which are little known but have been largely drawn from by other philosophers. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Cauchy, A.: \Title{\OE{}uvres complètes.} Tome~III: \Title{Cours d'analyse de l'École Polytechnique.} Tome~IV: \Title{Résumé des leçons données à l'École Polytechnique sur le calcul infinitésimal. Leçons sur le calcul différentiel.} Tome~V: \Title{Leçons sur les applications du calcul infinitésimal à la géométrie.} Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils, 1885--1897. 25~fr.\ each. \$9.50~each. \begin{Descrip} The works of Cauchy, as well as those of Lagrange, which follow, are mentioned for their high historical and educational importance. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Lagrange, J.~L.: \Title{\OE{}uvres complètes.} Tome~IX: \Title{Théorie des fonctions analytiques.} Tome~X.: \Title{Leçons sur le calcul des fonctions.} \PageSep{140} Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils, 1881--1884. 18~fr.\ per volume. \$5.40 per~volume. \begin{Descrip} ``The same power of abstraction and facility of treatment which signalise these works are nowhere to be met with in the prior or subsequent history of the subject. In addition, they are replete with the profoundest aperçus into the history of the development of analytical truths,---aperçus which could have come only from a man who combined superior creative endowment with exact and comprehensive knowledge of the facts. In the remarks woven into the body of the text will be found what is virtually a detailed history of the subject, and one which is not to be had elsewhere, least of all in diffuse histories of mathematics. The student, thus, not only learns in these works how to think, but also discovers how people actually have thought, and what are the ways which human instinct and reason have pursued in the different individuals who have participated in the elaboration of the science.''---(E.~Dühring.) \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Euler, L.: \begin{Descrip} The Latin treatises of Euler are also to be mentioned in this connexion, for the benefit of those who wish to pursue the history of the text-book making of this subject to its fountain-head. They are the \Title{Differential Calculus} (St.~Petersburg, 1755), the \Title{Integral Calculus} (3~vols., St.~Petersburg, 1768--1770), and the \Title{Introduction to the Infinitesimal Analysis} (2~vols., Lausanne, 1748). Of the last-mentioned work an old French translation by Labey exists (Paris: Gauthier-Villars), and a new German translation (of Vol.~I. only) by Maser (Berlin: Julius Springer, 1885). Of the first-mentioned treatises on the Calculus proper there exist two old German translations, which are not difficult to obtain. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \BibSubsect{German.} \begin{Book} Harnack, Dr.\ Axel: \Title{Elemente der Differential- und Integralrechnung.} Zur Einführung in das Studium dargestellt. Leipzig: Teubner, 1881. M.~7.60. Bound, \$2.80. (English translation. London: Williams \&~Norgate. 1891.) \end{Book} \begin{Book} Junker, Dr.\ Friedrich: \Title{Höhere Analysis.} I.~\Title{Differentialrechnung.} Mit 63~Figuren. II.~\Title{Integralrechnung.} Leipzig: G.~J. Göschen'sche Verlagshandlung. 1898--1899. 80~pf.\ each. 30~cents each. \begin{Descrip} These books are marvellously cheap, and very concise. They contain no examples. Pocket-size. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Autenheimer, F.: \Title{Elementarbuch der Differential- und Integralrechnung mit zahlreichen Anwendungen aus der Analysis, Geometrie, Mechanik, Physik etc.} Für höhere Lehranstalten \PageSep{141} und den Selbstunterricht. 4te~verbesserte Auflage. Weimar: Bernhard Friedrich Voigt. 1895. \begin{Descrip} As indicated by its title, this book is specially rich in practical applications. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Stegemann: \Title{Grundriss der Differential- und Integralrechnung}, 8te~Auflage, herausgegeben von Kiepert. Hannover: Helwing, 1897. Two volumes, 26~marks. Two volumes, bound, \$8.50. \begin{Descrip} This work was highly recommended by Prof.\ Felix Klein at the Evanston Colloquium in~1893. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Schlömilch: \Title{Compendium der höheren Analysis.} Fifth edition, 1881. Two volumes, \$6.80. \begin{Descrip} Schlömilch's text-books have been very successful. The present work was long the standard manual. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Stolz, Dr.\ Otto: \Title{Grundzüge der Differential- und Integralrechnung.} In 2~Theilen. I.~Theil. Reelle Veränderliche und Functionen. (460~S.) 1893. M.~8. II.~Complexe Veränderliche und Functionen. (338~S.) Leipzig: Teubner. 1896. M.~8. Two volumes, \$6.00. \begin{Descrip} A supplementary 3rd part entitled \Title{Die Lehre von den Doppelintegralen} has just been published (1899). Based on the works of J.~Tannery, Peano, and Dini. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Lipschitz, R.: \Title{Lehrbuch der Analysis.} 1877--1880. Two volumes, bound, \$12.30. \begin{Descrip} Specially good on the theoretical side. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \BibSubsect{Collections of Examples and Illustrations.} \begin{Book} Byerly, W.~E.: \Title{Problems in Differential Calculus.} Supplementary to a Treatise on Differential Calculus. Boston: Ginn \&~Co. 75~cents. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Gregory: \Title{Examples on the Differential and Integral Calculus.} 1841. Second edition. 1846. Out of print. About \$6.40. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Frenet: \Title{Recueil d'exercises sur le calcul infinitésimal.} 5.~édition, augmentée d'un appendice, par H.~Laurent. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. 1891. 8~fr.\ \$2.40. \end{Book} \PageSep{142} \begin{Book} Tisserand, F.: \Title{Recueil complémentaire d'exercises sur le calcul infinitésimal.} Second edition. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils 1896. \begin{Descrip} Complementary to Frenet. \end{Descrip} \end{Book} \begin{Book} Laisant, C.~A.: \Title{Recueil de problèmes de mathématiques.} Tome~VII\@. Calcul infinitésimal et calcul des fonctions. Mécanique. Astronomie. (Announced for publication.) Paris: Gauthier-Villars et~fils. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Schlömilch, Dr.\ Oscar: \Title{Uebungsbuch zum Studium der höheren Analysis.} I.~Theil. Aufgaben aus der Differentialrechnung. 4te~Auflage. (336~S.) 1887. M.~6. II.~Aufgaben aus der Integralrechnung. 3te~Auflage. (384~S.) Leipzig: Teubner, 1882. M.~7.60. Both volumes, bound, \$7.60. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Sohncke, L.~A.: \Title{Sammlung von Aufgaben aus der Differential- und Integralrechnung.} Herausgegeben von Heis. Two volumes, in---8. Bound, \$3.00. \end{Book} \begin{Book} Fuhrmann, Dr.\ Arwed: \Title{Anwendungen der Infinitesimalrechnung in den Naturwissenschaften, im Hochbau und in der Technik.} Lehrbuch und Aufgabensammlung. In sechs Theilen, von denen jeder ein selbstständiges Ganzes bildet. Theil~I. Naturwissenschaftliche Anwendungen der Differentialrechnung. Theil~II. Naturwissenschaftliche Anwendungen der Integralrechnung. Berlin: Verlag von Ernst \&~Korn. 1888--1890. Vol.~I., Cloth, \$1.35. Vol.~II., Cloth, \$2.20. \end{Book} \PageSep{143} \printindex \iffalse %INDEX. Accelerated motion 57, 60 Accelerating force 62 Advice for studying the Calculus 132, 133 Angle, unit employed in measuring an#Angle 51 Approximate solutions in the Integral Calculus 132, 133 Arc and its chord, a continuously decreasing|EtSeq#Arc 7, 39 % et seq. Archimedes 127 Astronomical ephemeris 76 Calculus, notation of 25 Calculus, notation of|EtSeq 79 % et seq. Circle, equation of|EtSeq 31 % et seq. Circle cut by straight line, investigated|EtSeq 31 % et seq. Coefficients, differential|EtSeq 22 % et seq. Coefficients, differential 38, 55, 82, 88, 96, 100, 112 Complete Differential Coefficients 96 Constants 14 Contiguous values 112 Continuous quantities|EtSeq 7 % et seq. Continuous quantities 53 Co-ordinates 30 Curve, magnified 40 Curvilinear areas, determination of|EtSeq 124 % et seq. Density, continuously varying|EtSeq 130 % et seq. Derivatives 19, 21, 22 Derived Functions|EtSeq 19 % et seq. Derived Functions 21 Differences arithmetical 4 of increments 26 calculus of 89 Differential coefficients|EtSeq 22 % et seq., Differential coefficients 38, 55, 82 as the index of the change of a function 112 of higher orders 88 Differentials partial|EtSeq 78 % et seq.; total|EtSeq 78 % et seq. Differentiation of the common functions 85, 86 successive|EtSeq 88 % et seq.; implicit|EtSeq 94 % et seq.; of complicated functions|EtSeq 100 % et seq. Direct function 97 Direction 36 Equality 4 Equations, solution of 77 Equidistant values 104 Euler 27, 124 Errors, in the valuation of quantities 75, 84 Explicit functions 107 Falling bodies 56 Finite differences|EtSeq 88 % et seq. Fluxions 11, 60, 112 Force 61-63 Functions definition of|EtSeq 14 % et seq.; derived|EtSeq 19 % et seq., derived 21 direct and indirect 97 implicit and explicit 107, 108 inverse|EtSeq 102 % et seq.; of several variables|EtSeq 78 % et seq.; recapitulation of results in the theory of 74 Generally@\emph{Generally}, the word 16 Implicit differentiation|EtSeq 94 % et seq.; function 107, 108 Impulse 60 Increase without limit|EtSeq 5, 65 % et seq. Increment 16, 113 \PageSep{144} Independent variables 106 Indirect function 97 Indivisibles method of|EtSeq 127 % et seq.; notion of, in mechanics|EtSeq 129 % et seq. Infinite@\emph{Infinite}, the word#Infinite 128 Infinitely small, the notion of#Infinitely 12, 49, 59, 83 Infinitely small, the notion of|EtSeq#Infinitely 38 % et seq., Infinity, orders of|EtSeq 42 % et seq. Integral Calculus 73 notation of 119 Integral Calculus|EtSeq 115 % et seq. Integrals definition of|EtSeq 119 % et seq.; relations between differential coefficients and 121 indefinite 122, 123 Intersections, limit of|EtSeq 46 % et seq. Inverse functions|EtSeq 102 % et seq. Iron bar continually varying in density, weight of|EtSeq#Iron 130 % et seq. Ladder against wall|EtSeq 45 % et seq. Lagrange 124 Laplace 124 Leibnitz 11, 13, 38, 42, 48, 59, 60, 83, 123, 124, 128, 129 Limit of intersections|EtSeq 46 % et seq. Limits|EtSeq 26 % et seq. Limiting ratios|EtSeq 65 % et seq. Limiting ratios 81 Logarithms 20, 38, 86, 87 Logarithms|EtSeq 112 % et seq. Magnified curve 40 Motion accelerated 60 simple harmonic 57 Newton 11, 60 Notation of the Differential Calculus 25 of the Differential Calculus|EtSeq 79 % et seq. of the Integral Calculus 119 Orders, differential coefficients of higher 88 Orders of infinity|EtSeq 42 % et seq. Parabola, the#Parabola 30, 127 Parabola, the|EtSeq#Parabola 124 % et seq. Partial differentials|EtSeq 78 % et seq.; differential coefficients 96 Point@\emph{Point}, the word#Point 129 Points, the number of, in a straight line 129 Polygon 38 Proportion|EtSeq 2 % et seq. Quantities, continuous|EtSeq 7 % et seq. Quantities, continuous 53 Ratio defined|EtSeq 2 % et seq.; of two increments 87 Ratios, limiting|EtSeq 65 % et seq. Ratios, limiting 81 Rough methods of solution in the Integral Calculus 132, 133 Series|EtSeq 15, 24 % et seq. Signs|EtSeq 31 % et seq. Simple harmonic motion 57 Sines 87 Singular values 16 Small, has no precise meaning 12 Specific gravity, continuously varying|EtSeq 130 % et seq. Successive differentiation|EtSeq 88 % et seq. Sun's longitude 76 Tangent 37, 38, 40 Taylor's Theorem|EtSeq 15, 19 % et seq. Time, idea of#Time 4 Time, idea of|EtSeq#Time 110 % et seq. Total differential coefficient 100 differentials|EtSeq 78 % et seq.; variations 95 Transit instrument 84 Uniformly accelerated 57, 60 Values contiguous 112 equidistant 104 Variables independent and dependent 14, 15, 106 functions of several|EtSeq 78 % et seq. Variations, total#Variations 95 Velocity linear|EtSeq 52 % et seq. linear 111 angular 59 Weight of an iron bar of which the density varies from point to point|EtSeq#Iron 130 % et seq. \fi \PageSep{145} \iffalse %[** TN: Catalog text has been (lightly) proofread, but not marked up in LaTeX] CATALOGUE OF PUBLICATIONS OF THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING CO. COPE, E. D. THE PRIMARY FACTORS OF ORGANIC EVOLUTION. 121 cuts. Pp. xvi, 547. Cloth, \$2.00 net (10s.). MULLER, F. MAX. THREE INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON THE SCIENCE OF THOUGHT. 128 pages. Cloth, 75c (3s. 6d.). THREE LECTURES ON THE SCIENCE OF LANGUAGE. 112 pages. 2nd Edition. Cloth, 75c (3s. 6d.). ROMANES, GEORGE JOHN. DARWIN AND AFTER DARWIN. An Exposition of the Darwinian Theory and a Discussion of Post-Darwinian Questions. Three Vols., \$4.00 net. Singly, as follows: 1. The Darwinian Theory. 460 pages. 125 illustrations. Cloth, \$2.00. 2. Post-Darwinian Questions. Heredity and Utility. Pp. 338. \$1.50. 3. Post-Darwinian Questions. Isolation and Physiological Selection. Pp. 181. \$1.00. AN EXAMINATION OF WEISMANNISM. 236 pages. Cloth, \$1.00 net. THOUGHTS ON RELIGION. Edited by Charles Gore, M. A., Canon of Westminster. Third Edition, Pages, 184. Cloth, gilt top, \$1.25 net. SHUTE. DR. D. KERFOOT. FIRST BOOK IN ORGANIC EVOLUTION. Colored plates, and numerous diagrams. (In Preparation.) MACH, ERNST. THE SCIENCE OF MECHANICS. A Critical and Historical Exposition of its Principles. Translated by T. J. McCormack. 250 cuts. 534 pages. 1/2 in., gilt top. \$2.50 (12s. 6d.). POPULAR SCIENTIFIC LECTURES. Third Edition. 415 pages. 59 cuts. Cloth, gilt top. Net, \$1.50 (7s. 6d.). THE ANALYSIS OF THE SENSATIONS. Pp. 208. 37 cuts. Cloth, \$1.25 net (6s. 6d.). LAGRANGE. J. L. LECTURES ON ELEMENTARY MATHEMATICS. With portrait of the author. Pp. 172. Price, \$1.00 net (5s.). DE MORGAN, AUGUSTUS. ON THE STUDY AND DIFFICULTIES OF MATHEMATICS. New Reprint edition with notes. Pp. viii+288. Cloth, \$1.25 net (5s.). ELEMENTARY ILLUSTRATIONS OF THE DIFFERENTIAL AND INTEGRAL CALCULUS. New reprint edition. Price, \$1.00 (5s.). SCHUBERT, HERMANN. MATHEMATICAL ESSAYS AND RECREATIONS. Pp. 149. Cuts, 37. Cloth, 75c net (3s. 6d.). HUC AND GABET, MM. TRAVELS IN TARTARY, THIBET AND CHINA. (1844--1846.) Translated from the French by W. Hazlitt. Illustrated with 100 engravings on wood. 2 vols. Pp. 28+660. Cl., \$2.00 (10s.). % --- Page CARUS, PAUL. THE ETHICAL PROBLEM. Second edition, revised and greatly enlarged. 351 pages. Cloth, \$1.25 (6s. 6d.). FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS. Second edition, enlarged and revised. 372 pp. Cl., \$1.50 (7s. 6d.). HOMILIES OF SCIENCE. 317 pages. Cloth, Gilt Top, \$1.50 (7s. 6d.). THE IDEA OF GOD. Fourth edition. 32 pages. Paper, 15c (9d.). THE SOUL OF MAN. With 152 cuts and diagrams. 458 pages. Cloth, \$3.00 (15s.). TRUTH IN FICTION. Twelve Tales with a Moral. White and gold binding, gilt edges. Pp. 111. \$1.00 (5s.). THE RELIGION OF SCIENCE. Second, extra edition. Pp. 103. Price, 50c net (2s. 6d.). PRIMER OF PHILOSOPHY. 240 pages. Second Edition. Cloth, \$1.00 (5s.). THE GOSPEL OF BUDDHA. According to Old Records. Fifth Edition. Pp. 275. Cloth, \$1.00 (5s.). In German, \$1.25 (6s. 6d.). BUDDHISM AND ITS CHRISTIAN CRITICS. Pages, 311. Cloth, \$1.25 (6s. 6d.). KARMA. A Story of Early Buddhism. Illustrated by Japanese artists. Crêpe paper, 75c (3s. 6d.). NIRVANA: A Story of Buddhist Psychology. Japanese edition, like Karma. \$1.00 (4s. 6d.). LAO-TZE'S TAO TEH-KING. Chinese-English. With introduction, transliteration. Notes, etc. Pp. 360. Cloth, \$3.00 (15s.). CORNILL, CARL HEINRICH. THE PROPHETS OF ISRAEL. Popular Sketches from Old Testament History. Pp., 200. Cloth, \$1.00 net (5s.). HISTORY OF THE PEOPLE OF ISRAEL. Pp. vi + 325. Cloth, \$1.50 (7s. 6d.). POWELL, J. W. TRUTH AND ERROR; or, the Science of Intellection. Pp. 423. Cloth, \$1.75 (7s. 6d.). RIBOT. TH. THE PSYCHOLOGY OF ATTENTION. THE DISEASES OF PERSONALITY. THE DISEASES OF THE WILL. Authorised translations. Cloth, 75 cents each (3s. 6d.). Full set, cloth, \$1.75 net (9s.). EVOLUTION OF GENERAL IDEAS. Pp. 231. Cloth, \$1.25 net (6s. 6d.). WAGNER, RICHARD. A PILGRIMAGE TO BEETHOVEN. A Story. With portrait of Beethoven. Pp. 40. Boards, 50c net (2s. 6d.) HUTCHINSON, WOODS. THE GOSPEL ACCORDING TO DARWIN. Pp. xii+241. Price, \$1.50 (6s.). FREYTAG, GUSTAV. THE LOST MANUSCRIPT. A Novel. 2 vols. 953 pages. Extra cloth, \$4.00 (21s). One vol., cl., \$1.00 (5s.). MARTIN LUTHER. Illustrated. Pp.130. Cloth, \$1.00 net (5s.). % --- Page TRUMBULL, M. M. THE FREE TRADE STRUGGLE IN ENGLAND. Second Edition. 296 pages. Cloth, 75c (3s. 6d.). WHEELBARROW: Articles and Discussions on the Labor Question With portrait of the author. 303 pages. Cloth, \$1.00 (5s.). GOETHE AND SCHILLER'S XENIONS. Translated by Paul Carus. Album form. Pp. 162. Cl., \$1.00 (5s.). OLDENBERG. H. ANCIENT INDIA: ITS LANGUAGE AND RELIGIONS. Pp. 100. Cloth, 50c net (2s. 6d.). CONWAY, DR. MONCURE DANIEL. SOLOMON, AND SOLOMONIC LITERATURE. Pp. 243. Cloth, \$1.50 net (6s. 6d.). GARBE, RICHARD. THE REDEMPTION OF THE BRAHMAN. A Tale of Hindu Life. Laid paper. Gilt top. 96 pages. Price, 75c (3s. 6d.). THE PHILOSOPHY OF ANCIENT INDIA. Pp. 89. Cloth, 50c net (2s. 6d.). HUEPPE. FERDINAND. THE PRINCIPLES OF BACTERIOLOGY. 28 Woodcuts. Pp. x+467. Price, \$1.75 net (9s.). LÉVY-BRUHL, PROF. L. HISTORY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY IN FRANCE. With 23 Photogravure and Half-Tone Portraits of the Chief French Philosophers. Handsomely bound. (In the press.) TOPINARD, DR. PAUL. SCIENCE AND FAITH, or Man as an Animal and Man as a Member of Society. Pp. 374. Cloth, \$1.50 net (7s. 6d.). BINET, ALFRED. THE PSYCHOLOGY OF REASONING. Pp. 193. Cloth, 75c (3s. 6d.). THE PSYCHIC LIFE OF MICRO-ORGANISMS. Pp. 135. Cloth, 75 cents. ON DOUBLE CONSCIOUSNESS. See No. 8, Religion of Science Library. THE OPEN COURT. A Monthly Magazine Devoted to the Science of Religion, the Religion of Science, and the Extension of the Religious Parliament Idea. Terms: \$1.00 a year; 5s. 6d. to foreign countries in the Postal Union. Single Copies, 10 cents (6d.). THE MONIST. A Quarterly Magazine of Philosophy and Science. Per copy, 50 cents; Yearly, \$2.00. In England and all countries in U.P.U. per copy, 2s. 6d.: Yearly, 9s. 6d. CHICAGO: THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING CO., Monon Building, 324 Dearborn St. LONDON: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner & Company. % --- Page The Religion of Science Library, A collection of bi-monthly publications, most of which are reprints of books published by The Open Court Publishing Company. Yearly, \$1.50. Separate copies according to prices quoted. The books are printed upon good paper, from large type. The Religion of Science Library, by its extraordinarily reasonable price, will place a large number of valuable books within the reach of all readers. The following have already appeared in the series: No. 1. The Religion of Science. By Paul Carus. 25c (1s. 6d). 2. Three Introductory Lectures on the Science of Thought. By F. Max Müller. 25c (1s. 6d.). 3. Three Lectures on the Science of Language. F. Max Müller. 25c (1s. 6d.) 4. The Diseases of Personality. By Th. Ribot. 25c (1s. 6d.). 5. The Psychology of Attention. By Th. Ribot. 25c (1s. 6d.). 6. The Psychic Life of Micro-Organisms. By Alfred Binet. 25c (1s. 6d.) 7. The Nature of the State. By Paul Carus. 15c (9d.). 8. On Double Consciousness. By Alfred Binet. 15c (9d.). 9. Fundamental Problems. By Paul Carus. 50c (2s. 6d.). 10. The Diseases of the Will. By Th. Ribot. 25c (1s. 6d.). 11. The Origin of Language. By Ludwig Noire. 15c (9d.). 12. The Free Trade Struggle in England. M. M. Trumbull. 25c (1s. 6d.). 13. Wheelbarrow on the Labor Question. By M. M. Trumbull. 35c (2s.). 14. The Gospel of Buddha By Paul Carus. 35c (2s.). 15. The Primer of Philosophy. By Paul Carus. 25c (1s. 6d.). 16. On Memory, and The Specific Energies of the Nervous System. By Prof. Ewald Hering. 15c (9d.). 17. The Redemption of the Brahman. A Tale of Hindu Life. By Richard Garbe. 25c (1s. 6d.). 18. An Examination of Weismannism. By G. J. Romanes. 35c (2s.). 19. On Germinal Selection. By August Weismann. 25c (1s. 6d.). 20. Lovers Three Thousand Years Ago. By T. A. Goodwin. (Out of print.) 21. Popular Scientific Lectures. By Ernst Mach. 50c (2s. 6d.). 22. Ancient India: Its Language and Religions. By H. Oldenberg. 25c (1s. 6d.). 23. The Prophets of Israel. By Prof. C. H. Cornill. 25c (1s. 6d.). 24. Homilies of Science. By Paul Carus. 35c (2s.). 25. Thoughts on Religion. By G. J. Romanes. 50c (2s. 6d.). 26. The Philosophy of Ancient India. By Prof. Richard Garbe. 25c (1s. 6d.). 27. Martin Luther. By Gustav Freytag. 25c (1s. 6d.). 28. English Secularism. By George Jacob Holyoake. 25c (1s. 6d.). 29. On Orthogenesis. By Th. Eimer. 25c (1s. 6d.). 30. Chinese Philosophy. By Paul Carus. 25c (1s. 6d.). 31. The Lost Manuscript. By Gustav Freytag. 60c (3s.). 32. A Mechanico-Physiological Theory of Organic Evolution. By Carl von Naegeli. 15c (9d.). 33. Chinese Fiction. By Dr. George T. Candlin. 15c (9d.). 34. Mathematical Essays and Recreations. By H. Schubert. 25c (1s. 6d.). 35. The Ethical Problem. By Paul Carus. 50c (2s. 6d.). 36. Buddhism and Its Christian Critics. By Paul Carus. 50c (2s. 6d.). 37. Psychology for Beginners. By Hiram M. Stanley. 20c (1s.). 38. Discourse on Method. By Descartes. 25c (1s. 6d.). THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING CO., CHICAGO: 324 Dearborn Street. LONDON: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner & Company. \fi %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% GUTENBERG LICENSE %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \PGLicense \begin{PGtext} End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of Elementary Illustrations of the Differential and Integral Calculus, by Augustus De Morgan *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK DIFFERENTIAL, INTEGRAL CALCULUS *** ***** This file should be named 39041-pdf.pdf or 39041-pdf.zip ***** This and all associated files of various formats will be found in: http://www.gutenberg.org/3/9/0/4/39041/ Produced by Andrew D. Hwang. Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions will be renamed. Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission. If you do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the rules is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research. They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks. Redistribution is subject to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution. *** START: FULL LICENSE *** THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project Gutenberg-tm License (available with this file or online at http://gutenberg.net/license). Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8. 1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below. 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation" or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an individual work is in the public domain in the United States and you are located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg-tm License when you share it without charge with others. 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United States. 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg: 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase "Project Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed: This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.net 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is derived from the public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase "Project Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9. 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works posted with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work. 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm. 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project Gutenberg-tm License. 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary, compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.net), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1. 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying, performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9. 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works provided that - You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation." - You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg-tm works. - You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of receipt of the work. - You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works. 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael Hart, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below. 1.F. 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread public domain works in creating the Project Gutenberg-tm collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain "Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment. 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE. 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the problem. 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS' WITH NO OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTIBILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE. 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions. 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause. Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from people in all walks of life. Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation web page at http://www.pglaf.org. Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification number is 64-6221541. Its 501(c)(3) letter is posted at http://pglaf.org/fundraising. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state's laws. The Foundation's principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr. S. Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered throughout numerous locations. Its business office is located at 809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887, email business@pglaf.org. Email contact links and up to date contact information can be found at the Foundation's web site and official page at http://pglaf.org For additional contact information: Dr. Gregory B. Newby Chief Executive and Director gbnewby@pglaf.org Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS. The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any particular state visit http://pglaf.org While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who approach us with offers to donate. International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff. Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other ways including including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To donate, please visit: http://pglaf.org/donate Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Professor Michael S. Hart is the originator of the Project Gutenberg-tm concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared with anyone. For thirty years, he produced and distributed Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support. Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition. Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility: http://www.gutenberg.net This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm, including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks. \end{PGtext} % %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % % % % End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of Elementary Illustrations of the % % Differential and Integral Calculus, by Augustus De Morgan % % % % *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK DIFFERENTIAL, INTEGRAL CALCULUS *** % % % ***** This file should be named 39041-t.tex or 39041-t.zip ***** % % This and all associated files of various formats will be found in: % % http://www.gutenberg.org/3/9/0/4/39041/ % % % % %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % \end{document} ### @ControlwordReplace = ( ['\\th', 'th'], ['\\ie', 'i.e.'], ['\\eg', 'e.g.'] ); @ControlwordArguments = ( ['\\Signature', 1, 1, '', ' ', 1, 1, '', ' '], ['\\Figure', 0, 0, '', '', 1, 0, '', ''], ['\\BookMark', 1, 0, '', '', 1, 0, '', ''], ['\\First', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Section', 0, 0, '', '', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\SubSectHead', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Subsection', 0, 0, '', '', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Fig', 1, 1, 'Fig. ', ''], ['\\Pagelabel', 1, 0, '', ''], ['\\Pageref', 1, 1, 'p. ', ''], ['\\Pagerefs', 1, 1, 'pp. ', ', ', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Eq', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Typo', 1, 0, '', '', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Add', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Chg', 1, 0, '', '', 1, 1, '', ''] ); $PageSeparator = qr/^\\PageSep/; $CustomClean = 'print "\\nCustom cleaning in progress..."; my $cline = 0; while ($cline <= $#file) { $file[$cline] =~ s/--------[^\n]*\n//; # strip page separators $cline++ } print "done\\n";'; ### This is pdfTeX, Version 3.1415926-1.40.10 (TeX Live 2009/Debian) (format=pdflatex 2011.9.6) 3 MAR 2012 15:22 entering extended mode %&-line parsing enabled. **39041-t.tex (./39041-t.tex LaTeX2e <2009/09/24> Babel and hyphenation patterns for english, usenglishmax, dumylang, noh yphenation, farsi, arabic, croatian, bulgarian, ukrainian, russian, czech, slov ak, danish, dutch, finnish, french, basque, ngerman, german, german-x-2009-06-1 9, ngerman-x-2009-06-19, ibycus, monogreek, greek, ancientgreek, hungarian, san skrit, italian, latin, latvian, lithuanian, mongolian2a, mongolian, bokmal, nyn orsk, romanian, irish, coptic, serbian, turkish, welsh, esperanto, uppersorbian , estonian, indonesian, interlingua, icelandic, kurmanji, slovenian, polish, po rtuguese, spanish, galician, catalan, swedish, ukenglish, pinyin, loaded. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/book.cls Document Class: book 2007/10/19 v1.4h Standard LaTeX document class (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/bk12.clo File: bk12.clo 2007/10/19 v1.4h Standard LaTeX file (size option) ) \c@part=\count79 \c@chapter=\count80 \c@section=\count81 \c@subsection=\count82 \c@subsubsection=\count83 \c@paragraph=\count84 \c@subparagraph=\count85 \c@figure=\count86 \c@table=\count87 \abovecaptionskip=\skip41 \belowcaptionskip=\skip42 \bibindent=\dimen102 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/inputenc.sty Package: inputenc 2008/03/30 v1.1d Input encoding file \inpenc@prehook=\toks14 \inpenc@posthook=\toks15 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/latin1.def File: latin1.def 2008/03/30 v1.1d Input encoding file )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/ifthen.sty Package: ifthen 2001/05/26 v1.1c Standard LaTeX ifthen package (DPC) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsmath.sty Package: amsmath 2000/07/18 v2.13 AMS math features \@mathmargin=\skip43 For additional information on amsmath, use the `?' option. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amstext.sty Package: amstext 2000/06/29 v2.01 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsgen.sty File: amsgen.sty 1999/11/30 v2.0 \@emptytoks=\toks16 \ex@=\dimen103 )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsbsy.sty Package: amsbsy 1999/11/29 v1.2d \pmbraise@=\dimen104 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsopn.sty Package: amsopn 1999/12/14 v2.01 operator names ) \inf@bad=\count88 LaTeX Info: Redefining \frac on input line 211. \uproot@=\count89 \leftroot@=\count90 LaTeX Info: Redefining \overline on input line 307. \classnum@=\count91 \DOTSCASE@=\count92 LaTeX Info: Redefining \ldots on input line 379. LaTeX Info: Redefining \dots on input line 382. LaTeX Info: Redefining \cdots on input line 467. \Mathstrutbox@=\box26 \strutbox@=\box27 \big@size=\dimen105 LaTeX Font Info: Redeclaring font encoding OML on input line 567. LaTeX Font Info: Redeclaring font encoding OMS on input line 568. \macc@depth=\count93 \c@MaxMatrixCols=\count94 \dotsspace@=\muskip10 \c@parentequation=\count95 \dspbrk@lvl=\count96 \tag@help=\toks17 \row@=\count97 \column@=\count98 \maxfields@=\count99 \andhelp@=\toks18 \eqnshift@=\dimen106 \alignsep@=\dimen107 \tagshift@=\dimen108 \tagwidth@=\dimen109 \totwidth@=\dimen110 \lineht@=\dimen111 \@envbody=\toks19 \multlinegap=\skip44 \multlinetaggap=\skip45 \mathdisplay@stack=\toks20 LaTeX Info: Redefining \[ on input line 2666. LaTeX Info: Redefining \] on input line 2667. ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/amssymb.sty Package: amssymb 2009/06/22 v3.00 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/amsfonts.sty Package: amsfonts 2009/06/22 v3.00 Basic AMSFonts support \symAMSa=\mathgroup4 \symAMSb=\mathgroup5 LaTeX Font Info: Overwriting math alphabet `\mathfrak' in version `bold' (Font) U/euf/m/n --> U/euf/b/n on input line 96. )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/alltt.sty Package: alltt 1997/06/16 v2.0g defines alltt environment ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/tools/indentfirst.sty Package: indentfirst 1995/11/23 v1.03 Indent first paragraph (DPC) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/yfonts/yfonts.sty Package: yfonts 2003/01/08 v1.3 (WaS) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/footmisc/footmisc.sty Package: footmisc 2009/09/15 v5.5a a miscellany of footnote facilities \FN@temptoken=\toks21 \footnotemargin=\dimen112 \c@pp@next@reset=\count100 \c@@fnserial=\count101 Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style bringhurst on input line 855. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style chicago on input line 863. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style wiley on input line 872. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style lamport-robust on input line 883. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style lamport* on input line 903. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style lamport*-robust on input line 924 . ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/was/icomma.sty Package: icomma 2002/03/10 v2.0 (WaS) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/tools/multicol.sty Package: multicol 2008/12/05 v1.6h multicolumn formatting (FMi) \c@tracingmulticols=\count102 \mult@box=\box28 \multicol@leftmargin=\dimen113 \c@unbalance=\count103 \c@collectmore=\count104 \doublecol@number=\count105 \multicoltolerance=\count106 \multicolpretolerance=\count107 \full@width=\dimen114 \page@free=\dimen115 \premulticols=\dimen116 \postmulticols=\dimen117 \multicolsep=\skip46 \multicolbaselineskip=\skip47 \partial@page=\box29 \last@line=\box30 \mult@rightbox=\box31 \mult@grightbox=\box32 \mult@gfirstbox=\box33 \mult@firstbox=\box34 \@tempa=\box35 \@tempa=\box36 \@tempa=\box37 \@tempa=\box38 \@tempa=\box39 \@tempa=\box40 \@tempa=\box41 \@tempa=\box42 \@tempa=\box43 \@tempa=\box44 \@tempa=\box45 \@tempa=\box46 \@tempa=\box47 \@tempa=\box48 \@tempa=\box49 \@tempa=\box50 \@tempa=\box51 \c@columnbadness=\count108 \c@finalcolumnbadness=\count109 \last@try=\dimen118 \multicolovershoot=\dimen119 \multicolundershoot=\dimen120 \mult@nat@firstbox=\box52 \colbreak@box=\box53 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/makeidx.sty Package: makeidx 2000/03/29 v1.0m Standard LaTeX package ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/tools/array.sty Package: array 2008/09/09 v2.4c Tabular extension package (FMi) \col@sep=\dimen121 \extrarowheight=\dimen122 \NC@list=\toks22 \extratabsurround=\skip48 \backup@length=\skip49 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/graphicx.sty Package: graphicx 1999/02/16 v1.0f Enhanced LaTeX Graphics (DPC,SPQR) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/keyval.sty Package: keyval 1999/03/16 v1.13 key=value parser (DPC) \KV@toks@=\toks23 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/graphics.sty Package: graphics 2009/02/05 v1.0o Standard LaTeX Graphics (DPC,SPQR) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/trig.sty Package: trig 1999/03/16 v1.09 sin cos tan (DPC) ) (/etc/texmf/tex/latex/config/graphics.cfg File: graphics.cfg 2009/08/28 v1.8 graphics configuration of TeX Live ) Package graphics Info: Driver file: pdftex.def on input line 91. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/pdftex-def/pdftex.def File: pdftex.def 2009/08/25 v0.04m Graphics/color for pdfTeX \Gread@gobject=\count110 )) \Gin@req@height=\dimen123 \Gin@req@width=\dimen124 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/tools/calc.sty Package: calc 2007/08/22 v4.3 Infix arithmetic (KKT,FJ) \calc@Acount=\count111 \calc@Bcount=\count112 \calc@Adimen=\dimen125 \calc@Bdimen=\dimen126 \calc@Askip=\skip50 \calc@Bskip=\skip51 LaTeX Info: Redefining \setlength on input line 76. LaTeX Info: Redefining \addtolength on input line 77. \calc@Ccount=\count113 \calc@Cskip=\skip52 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/fancyhdr/fancyhdr.sty \fancy@headwidth=\skip53 \f@ncyO@elh=\skip54 \f@ncyO@erh=\skip55 \f@ncyO@olh=\skip56 \f@ncyO@orh=\skip57 \f@ncyO@elf=\skip58 \f@ncyO@erf=\skip59 \f@ncyO@olf=\skip60 \f@ncyO@orf=\skip61 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/geometry/geometry.sty Package: geometry 2008/12/21 v4.2 Page Geometry (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/ifpdf.sty Package: ifpdf 2009/04/10 v2.0 Provides the ifpdf switch (HO) Package ifpdf Info: pdfTeX in pdf mode detected. ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/ifvtex.sty Package: ifvtex 2008/11/04 v1.4 Switches for detecting VTeX and its modes (HO) Package ifvtex Info: VTeX not detected. ) \Gm@cnth=\count114 \Gm@cntv=\count115 \c@Gm@tempcnt=\count116 \Gm@bindingoffset=\dimen127 \Gm@wd@mp=\dimen128 \Gm@odd@mp=\dimen129 \Gm@even@mp=\dimen130 \Gm@dimlist=\toks24 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/xelatex/xetexconfig/geometry.cfg)) (/usr/share/te xmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/hyperref.sty Package: hyperref 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hypertext links for LaTeX (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/ifxetex/ifxetex.sty Package: ifxetex 2009/01/23 v0.5 Provides ifxetex conditional ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/oberdiek/hycolor.sty Package: hycolor 2009/10/02 v1.5 Code for color options of hyperref/bookmark (H O) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/oberdiek/xcolor-patch.sty Package: xcolor-patch 2009/10/02 xcolor patch )) \@linkdim=\dimen131 \Hy@linkcounter=\count117 \Hy@pagecounter=\count118 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/pd1enc.def File: pd1enc.def 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hyperref: PDFDocEncoding definition (HO) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/etexcmds.sty Package: etexcmds 2007/12/12 v1.2 Prefix for e-TeX command names (HO) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/infwarerr.sty Package: infwarerr 2007/09/09 v1.2 Providing info/warning/message (HO) ) Package etexcmds Info: Could not find \expanded. (etexcmds) That can mean that you are not using pdfTeX 1.50 or (etexcmds) that some package has redefined \expanded. (etexcmds) In the latter case, load this package earlier. ) (/etc/texmf/tex/latex/config/hyperref.cfg File: hyperref.cfg 2002/06/06 v1.2 hyperref configuration of TeXLive ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/oberdiek/kvoptions.sty Package: kvoptions 2009/08/13 v3.4 Keyval support for LaTeX options (HO) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/kvsetkeys.sty Package: kvsetkeys 2009/07/30 v1.5 Key value parser with default handler suppor t (HO) )) Package hyperref Info: Option `hyperfootnotes' set `false' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Option `bookmarks' set `true' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Option `linktocpage' set `false' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Option `pdfdisplaydoctitle' set `true' on input line 286 4. Package hyperref Info: Option `pdfpagelabels' set `true' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Option `bookmarksopen' set `true' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Option `colorlinks' set `true' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Hyper figures OFF on input line 2975. Package hyperref Info: Link nesting OFF on input line 2980. Package hyperref Info: Hyper index ON on input line 2983. Package hyperref Info: Plain pages OFF on input line 2990. Package hyperref Info: Backreferencing OFF on input line 2995. Implicit mode ON; LaTeX internals redefined Package hyperref Info: Bookmarks ON on input line 3191. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/ltxmisc/url.sty \Urlmuskip=\muskip11 Package: url 2006/04/12 ver 3.3 Verb mode for urls, etc. ) LaTeX Info: Redefining \url on input line 3428. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/bitset.sty Package: bitset 2007/09/28 v1.0 Data type bit set (HO) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/intcalc.sty Package: intcalc 2007/09/27 v1.1 Expandable integer calculations (HO) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/bigintcalc.sty Package: bigintcalc 2007/11/11 v1.1 Expandable big integer calculations (HO) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/pdftexcmds.sty Package: pdftexcmds 2009/09/23 v0.6 LuaTeX support for pdfTeX utility functions (HO) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/ifluatex.sty Package: ifluatex 2009/04/17 v1.2 Provides the ifluatex switch (HO) Package ifluatex Info: LuaTeX not detected. ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/ltxcmds.sty Package: ltxcmds 2009/08/05 v1.0 Some LaTeX kernel commands for general use (HO ) ) Package pdftexcmds Info: LuaTeX not detected. Package pdftexcmds Info: \pdf@primitive is available. Package pdftexcmds Info: \pdf@ifprimitive is available. ))) \Fld@menulength=\count119 \Field@Width=\dimen132 \Fld@charsize=\dimen133 \Field@toks=\toks25 Package hyperref Info: Hyper figures OFF on input line 4377. Package hyperref Info: Link nesting OFF on input line 4382. Package hyperref Info: Hyper index ON on input line 4385. Package hyperref Info: backreferencing OFF on input line 4392. Package hyperref Info: Link coloring ON on input line 4395. Package hyperref Info: Link coloring with OCG OFF on input line 4402. Package hyperref Info: PDF/A mode OFF on input line 4407. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/atbegshi.sty Package: atbegshi 2008/07/31 v1.9 At begin shipout hook (HO) ) \Hy@abspage=\count120 \c@Item=\count121 ) *hyperref using driver hpdftex* (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/hpdftex.def File: hpdftex.def 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hyperref driver for pdfTeX \Fld@listcount=\count122 ) \TmpLen=\skip62 \c@SecNo=\count123 \@indexfile=\write3 \openout3 = `39041-t.idx'. Writing index file 39041-t.idx \ParIndent=\skip63 (./39041-t.aux) \openout1 = `39041-t.aux'. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OML/cmm/m/it on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for T1/cmr/m/n on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OT1/cmr/m/n on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OMS/cmsy/m/n on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OMX/cmex/m/n on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for U/cmr/m/n on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for LY/yfrak/m/n on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for LYG/ygoth/m/n on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for PD1/pdf/m/n on input line 605. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 605. (/usr/share/texmf/tex/context/base/supp-pdf.mkii [Loading MPS to PDF converter (version 2006.09.02).] \scratchcounter=\count124 \scratchdimen=\dimen134 \scratchbox=\box54 \nofMPsegments=\count125 \nofMParguments=\count126 \everyMPshowfont=\toks26 \MPscratchCnt=\count127 \MPscratchDim=\dimen135 \MPnumerator=\count128 \everyMPtoPDFconversion=\toks27 ) *geometry auto-detecting driver* *geometry detected driver: pdftex* -------------------- Geometry parameters paper: class default landscape: -- twocolumn: -- twoside: true asymmetric: -- h-parts: 9.03375pt, 307.14749pt, 9.03375pt v-parts: 1.26749pt, 466.58623pt, 1.90128pt hmarginratio: 1:1 vmarginratio: 2:3 lines: -- heightrounded: -- bindingoffset: 0.0pt truedimen: -- includehead: true includefoot: true includemp: -- driver: pdftex -------------------- Page layout dimensions and switches \paperwidth 325.215pt \paperheight 469.75499pt \textwidth 307.14749pt \textheight 404.71243pt \oddsidemargin -63.23624pt \evensidemargin -63.23624pt \topmargin -71.0025pt \headheight 12.0pt \headsep 19.8738pt \footskip 30.0pt \marginparwidth 98.0pt \marginparsep 7.0pt \columnsep 10.0pt \skip\footins 10.8pt plus 4.0pt minus 2.0pt \hoffset 0.0pt \voffset 0.0pt \mag 1000 \@twosidetrue \@mparswitchtrue (1in=72.27pt, 1cm=28.45pt) ----------------------- (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/color.sty Package: color 2005/11/14 v1.0j Standard LaTeX Color (DPC) (/etc/texmf/tex/latex/config/color.cfg File: color.cfg 2007/01/18 v1.5 color configuration of teTeX/TeXLive ) Package color Info: Driver file: pdftex.def on input line 130. ) Package hyperref Info: Link coloring ON on input line 605. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/nameref.sty Package: nameref 2007/05/29 v2.31 Cross-referencing by name of section (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/oberdiek/refcount.sty Package: refcount 2008/08/11 v3.1 Data extraction from references (HO) ) \c@section@level=\count129 ) LaTeX Info: Redefining \ref on input line 605. LaTeX Info: Redefining \pageref on input line 605. (./39041-t.out) (./39041-t.out) \@outlinefile=\write4 \openout4 = `39041-t.out'. \AtBeginShipoutBox=\box55 Overfull \hbox (3.10696pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 621--621 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 Title: Elementary Illustrations of the Differential and Integ ral Calculus[] [] Overfull \hbox (20.10721pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 631--631 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK DIFFERENTIAL, INTEG RAL CALCULUS ***[] [] LaTeX Font Info: Try loading font information for U+msa on input line 633. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/umsa.fd File: umsa.fd 2009/06/22 v3.00 AMS symbols A ) LaTeX Font Info: Try loading font information for U+msb on input line 633. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/umsb.fd File: umsb.fd 2009/06/22 v3.00 AMS symbols B ) [1 {/var/lib/texmf/fonts/map/pdftex/updmap/pdftex.map}] [2] Underfull \hbox (badness 1127) in paragraph at lines 669--675 \OT1/cmr/m/n/12 LECTURES ON EL-E-MEN-TARY MATH-E-MAT-ICS. By [] [1 ] [2] [3 ] [4] [5] [6] (./39041-t.toc) \tf@toc=\write5 \openout5 = `39041-t.toc'. [7 ] [8] [9] [1 ] [2] [3] LaTeX Font Info: Try loading font information for OMS+cmr on input line 999. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/omscmr.fd File: omscmr.fd 1999/05/25 v2.5h Standard LaTeX font definitions ) LaTeX Font Info: Font shape `OMS/cmr/m/n' in size <8> not available (Font) Font shape `OMS/cmsy/m/n' tried instead on input line 999. LaTeX Font Info: Font shape `OMS/cmr/m/n' in size <7> not available (Font) Font shape `OMS/cmsy/m/n' tried instead on input line 1001. [4] [5] [6] [7] <./images/fig1.png, id=244, 239.2137pt x 128.6406pt> File: ./images/fig1.png Graphic file (type png) [8] [9 <./images/fig1.png (PNG copy)>] [10] File: ./images/fig1.png Graphic file (type png) [11] [12] [13] [14] [15] [16] [17] [18] [19] [20] [21] [22] [23] [24] [25] [26] [27] [28] [29] [30] [31] [32] <./images/fig2.png, id=3 95, 234.8775pt x 121.4136pt> File: ./images/fig2.png Graphic file (type png) [33] [34] [35 <./images/fig2.png>] <./images/fig3.png, id=417, 235.6002pt x 199.2243pt> File: ./images/fig3.png Graphic file (type png) [36] [37 <./images/fig3.png>] [38] [39] [40] File: ./images/fig2.png Graphic file (type png) [41] [42] [43] [44] <./images/fig4.png, id=471, 235.600 2pt x 94.4328pt> File: ./images/fig4.png Graphic file (type png) [45] [46 <./images/fig4.png>] [47] [48] [49] [50] [51] <./images/fig5.png, id=545, 241.3818pt x 97.5645pt> File: ./images/fig5.png Graphic file (type png) File: ./images/fig5.png Graphic file (type png) [52 <./images/fig5.png (PNG copy)>] [53] [54] <./images /fig6.png, id=582, 237.7683pt x 118.5228pt> File: ./images/fig6.png Graphic file (type png) <./images/fig7.png, id=583, 239.9364pt x 138.7584pt> File: ./images/fig7.png Graphic file (type png) [55] [56 <./images/fig6.png (PNG copy)>] [57 <./images/ fig7.png (PNG copy)>] [58] File: ./images/fig7.png Graphic file (type png) [59] [60] [61] [62] [63] [64] [65] [66] <./images/fig8. png, id=654, 238.491pt x 121.4136pt> File: ./images/fig8.png Graphic file (type png) [67] [68 <./images/fig8.png (PNG copy)>] [69] [70] [71] Overfull \hbox (0.70534pt too wide) detected at line 3196 \OT1/cmr/m/n/12 [1 + 2 + 3 + [] + (\OML/cmm/m/it/12 n \OMS/cmsy/m/n/12 ^^@ \OT1 /cmr/m/n/12 1) + \OML/cmm/m/it/12 n\OT1/cmr/m/n/12 ]\OML/cmm/m/it/12 v[]t[] \OT 1/cmr/m/n/12 = \OML/cmm/m/it/12 n \OMS/cmsy/m/n/12 ^^A [] \OML/cmm/m/it/12 v[]t [] \OT1/cmr/m/n/12 = []\OML/cmm/m/it/12 : [] [72] <./images/fig9.png, id=697, 241.3818pt x 49.8663pt> File: ./images/fig9.png Graphic file (type png) [73] [74 <./images/fig9.png (PNG copy)>] [75] [76] [77] [78] [79] [80] [81] [82] [83] [84] [85] [86] [87] [88] Overfull \hbox (0.92978pt too wide) detected at line 3767 [] [] [89] [90] [91] [92] [93] [94] [95] [96] [97] [98] [99] [100] [101] [102] [103] [104] [105] [106] [107] [108] [109] [110] [111] [112] [113] [114] [115] Overfull \hbox (5.08812pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 4726--4726 [] [] [116] [117] [118] [119] [120] [121] [122] [123] [124] [125] [126] [127] [128] [ 129] [130] [131] [132] [133] [134] [135] [136] [137] [138] [139] [140] [141] [1 42] [143] [144] [145] <./images/fig10.png, id=1178, 239.2137pt x 172.7253pt> File: ./images/fig10.png Graphic file (type png) [146] [147 <./images/fig10.png (PNG copy)>] [148] [149 ] [150] [151] [152] <./images/fig11.png, id=1226, 240.6591pt x 44.8074pt> File: ./images/fig11.png Graphic file (type png) [153] [154 <./images/fig11.png (PNG copy)>] [155] [156 ] LaTeX Font Info: Font shape `OMS/cmr/m/n' in size <10> not available (Font) Font shape `OMS/cmsy/m/n' tried instead on input line 6101. [157 ] [158] [159] Overfull \hbox (1.97104pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 6243--6249 \OT1/cmr/m/n/12 Sturm: \OT1/cmr/m/it/12 Cours d'analyse de l'[]Ecole Poly-tech- nique. \OT1/cmr/m/n/12 10. ^^Sedition, [] [160] [161] [162] [163] Underfull \hbox (badness 1931) in paragraph at lines 6413--6420 \OT1/cmr/m/it/12 de l'[]Ecole Poly-tech-nique. \OT1/cmr/m/n/12 Tome IV: \OT1/cm r/m/it/12 R^^Sesum^^Se des [] [164] [165] [166] Underfull \hbox (badness 1881) in paragraph at lines 6565--6569 \OT1/cmr/m/n/12 Frenet: \OT1/cmr/m/it/12 Re-cueil d'exercises sur le cal-cul in -finit^^Sesimal. [] [167] Overfull \hbox (1.74687pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 6597--6601 \OT1/cmr/m/n/12 Sohncke, L. A.: \OT1/cmr/m/it/12 Samm-lung von Auf-gaben aus de r Differential- [] [168] (./39041-t.ind [169] [170 ] [171] [172] [173]) Overfull \hbox (11.60709pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 7277--7277 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK DIFFERENTIAL, INTEGRA L CALCULUS ***[] [] [1 ] Overfull \hbox (3.10696pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 7344--7344 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation"[] [] Overfull \hbox (3.10696pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 7349--7349 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prev ent you from[] [] Overfull \hbox (3.10696pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 7354--7354 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of[] [] [2] [3] Overfull \hbox (3.10696pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 7417--7417 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gut enberg.net),[] [] [4] [5] [6] [7] [8] [9] [10] (./39041-t.aux) *File List* book.cls 2007/10/19 v1.4h Standard LaTeX document class bk12.clo 2007/10/19 v1.4h Standard LaTeX file (size option) inputenc.sty 2008/03/30 v1.1d Input encoding file latin1.def 2008/03/30 v1.1d Input encoding file ifthen.sty 2001/05/26 v1.1c Standard LaTeX ifthen package (DPC) amsmath.sty 2000/07/18 v2.13 AMS math features amstext.sty 2000/06/29 v2.01 amsgen.sty 1999/11/30 v2.0 amsbsy.sty 1999/11/29 v1.2d amsopn.sty 1999/12/14 v2.01 operator names amssymb.sty 2009/06/22 v3.00 amsfonts.sty 2009/06/22 v3.00 Basic AMSFonts support alltt.sty 1997/06/16 v2.0g defines alltt environment indentfirst.sty 1995/11/23 v1.03 Indent first paragraph (DPC) yfonts.sty 2003/01/08 v1.3 (WaS) footmisc.sty 2009/09/15 v5.5a a miscellany of footnote facilities icomma.sty 2002/03/10 v2.0 (WaS) multicol.sty 2008/12/05 v1.6h multicolumn formatting (FMi) makeidx.sty 2000/03/29 v1.0m Standard LaTeX package array.sty 2008/09/09 v2.4c Tabular extension package (FMi) graphicx.sty 1999/02/16 v1.0f Enhanced LaTeX Graphics (DPC,SPQR) keyval.sty 1999/03/16 v1.13 key=value parser (DPC) graphics.sty 2009/02/05 v1.0o Standard LaTeX Graphics (DPC,SPQR) trig.sty 1999/03/16 v1.09 sin cos tan (DPC) graphics.cfg 2009/08/28 v1.8 graphics configuration of TeX Live pdftex.def 2009/08/25 v0.04m Graphics/color for pdfTeX calc.sty 2007/08/22 v4.3 Infix arithmetic (KKT,FJ) fancyhdr.sty geometry.sty 2008/12/21 v4.2 Page Geometry ifpdf.sty 2009/04/10 v2.0 Provides the ifpdf switch (HO) ifvtex.sty 2008/11/04 v1.4 Switches for detecting VTeX and its modes (HO) geometry.cfg hyperref.sty 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hypertext links for LaTeX ifxetex.sty 2009/01/23 v0.5 Provides ifxetex conditional hycolor.sty 2009/10/02 v1.5 Code for color options of hyperref/bookmark (HO ) xcolor-patch.sty 2009/10/02 xcolor patch pd1enc.def 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hyperref: PDFDocEncoding definition (HO) etexcmds.sty 2007/12/12 v1.2 Prefix for e-TeX command names (HO) infwarerr.sty 2007/09/09 v1.2 Providing info/warning/message (HO) hyperref.cfg 2002/06/06 v1.2 hyperref configuration of TeXLive kvoptions.sty 2009/08/13 v3.4 Keyval support for LaTeX options (HO) kvsetkeys.sty 2009/07/30 v1.5 Key value parser with default handler support (HO) url.sty 2006/04/12 ver 3.3 Verb mode for urls, etc. bitset.sty 2007/09/28 v1.0 Data type bit set (HO) intcalc.sty 2007/09/27 v1.1 Expandable integer calculations (HO) bigintcalc.sty 2007/11/11 v1.1 Expandable big integer calculations (HO) pdftexcmds.sty 2009/09/23 v0.6 LuaTeX support for pdfTeX utility functions ( HO) ifluatex.sty 2009/04/17 v1.2 Provides the ifluatex switch (HO) ltxcmds.sty 2009/08/05 v1.0 Some LaTeX kernel commands for general use (HO) atbegshi.sty 2008/07/31 v1.9 At begin shipout hook (HO) hpdftex.def 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hyperref driver for pdfTeX supp-pdf.mkii color.sty 2005/11/14 v1.0j Standard LaTeX Color (DPC) color.cfg 2007/01/18 v1.5 color configuration of teTeX/TeXLive nameref.sty 2007/05/29 v2.31 Cross-referencing by name of section refcount.sty 2008/08/11 v3.1 Data extraction from references (HO) 39041-t.out 39041-t.out umsa.fd 2009/06/22 v3.00 AMS symbols A umsb.fd 2009/06/22 v3.00 AMS symbols B omscmr.fd 1999/05/25 v2.5h Standard LaTeX font definitions ./images/fig1.png ./images/fig1.png ./images/fig2.png ./images/fig3.png ./images/fig2.png ./images/fig4.png ./images/fig5.png ./images/fig5.png ./images/fig6.png ./images/fig7.png ./images/fig7.png ./images/fig8.png ./images/fig9.png ./images/fig10.png ./images/fig11.png 39041-t.ind *********** ) Here is how much of TeX's memory you used: 7120 strings out of 493848 95599 string characters out of 1152824 205472 words of memory out of 3000000 9724 multiletter control sequences out of 15000+50000 18054 words of font info for 69 fonts, out of 3000000 for 9000 714 hyphenation exceptions out of 8191 37i,18n,43p,298b,640s stack positions out of 5000i,500n,10000p,200000b,50000s Output written on 39041-t.pdf (194 pages, 919386 bytes). PDF statistics: 1752 PDF objects out of 2073 (max. 8388607) 523 named destinations out of 1000 (max. 500000) 120 words of extra memory for PDF output out of 10000 (max. 10000000)