% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % % % % Project Gutenberg's An Introduction to Mathematics, by Alfred North Whitehead % % % This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with % % almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or % % re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included % % with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org % % % % % % Title: An Introduction to Mathematics % % % % Author: Alfred North Whitehead % % % % Release Date: December 6, 2012 [EBook #41568] % % Most recently updated: June 11, 2021 % % % % Language: English % % % % Character set encoding: UTF-8 % % % % *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK AN INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS *** % % % %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % \def\ebook{41568} %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% %% %% %% Packages and substitutions: %% %% %% %% book: Required. %% %% inputenc: Latin-1 text encoding. Required. %% %% %% %% ifthen: Logical conditionals. Required. %% %% %% %% amsmath: AMS mathematics enhancements. Required. %% %% amssymb: Additional mathematical symbols. Required. %% %% %% %% alltt: Fixed-width font environment. Required. %% %% %% %% indentfirst: Indent first paragraph of each section. Optional. %% %% %% %% footmisc: Start footnote numbering on each page. Required. %% %% %% %% multicol: Multicolumn environment for index. Required. %% %% makeidx: Index. Required. %% %% %% %% graphicx: Standard interface for graphics inclusion. Required. %% %% caption: Caption customization. Required. %% %% %% %% calc: Length calculations. Required. %% %% %% %% fancyhdr: Enhanced running headers and footers. Required. %% %% %% %% geometry: Enhanced page layout package. Required. %% %% hyperref: Hypertext embellishments for pdf output. Required. %% %% %% %% %% %% Producer's Comments: %% %% %% %% OCR text for this ebook was obtained on Nov. 24, 2012, from %% %% http://archive.org/details/introductiontoma00whitiala. %% %% %% %% Minor changes to the original are noted in this file in three %% %% ways: %% %% 1. \Typo{}{} for typographical corrections, showing original %% %% and replacement text side-by-side. %% %% 2. \Chg{}{} and \Add{}, for inconsistent/missing punctuation,%% %% italicization, and capitalization. %% %% 3. [** TN: Note]s for lengthier or stylistic comments. %% %% %% %% %% %% Compilation Flags: %% %% %% %% The following behavior may be controlled by boolean flags. %% %% %% %% ForPrinting (false by default): %% %% If false, compile a screen optimized file (one-sided layout, %% %% blue hyperlinks). If true, print-optimized PDF file: Larger %% %% text block, two-sided layout, black hyperlinks. %% %% %% %% %% %% PDF pages: 228 (if ForPrinting set to false) %% %% PDF page size: 4.5 x 6.5" (non-standard) %% %% %% %% Summary of log file: %% %% * One overfull hbox (0.86pt), one slightly underfull hbox. %% %% %% %% Compile History: %% %% %% %% December, 2012: (Andrew D. Hwang) %% %% texlive2011, GNU/Linux %% %% %% %% Command block: %% %% %% %% pdflatex x2 %% %% makeindex %% %% pdflatex x2 %% %% %% %% %% %% December 2012: pglatex. %% %% Compile this project with: %% %% pdflatex 41568-t.tex ..... TWO times %% %% makeindex 41568-t.idx %% %% pdflatex 41568-t.tex ..... TWO times %% %% %% %% pdfTeX, Version 3.1415926-1.40.10 (TeX Live 2009/Debian) %% %% %% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \listfiles \documentclass[12pt,leqno]{book}[2005/09/16] %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% PACKAGES %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \usepackage[utf8]{inputenc}[2006/05/05] \usepackage{ifthen}[2001/05/26] %% Logical conditionals \usepackage{amsmath}[2000/07/18] %% Displayed equations \usepackage{amssymb}[2002/01/22] %% and additional symbols \usepackage{alltt}[1997/06/16] %% boilerplate, credits, license \IfFileExists{indentfirst.sty}{% \usepackage{indentfirst}[1995/11/23] }{} \usepackage[perpage,symbol]{footmisc}[2005/03/17] \usepackage{multicol}[2006/05/18] \usepackage{makeidx}[2000/03/29] \usepackage{graphicx}[1999/02/16]%% For diagrams \usepackage[labelformat=empty,textfont=small]{caption}[2007/01/07] \usepackage{calc}[2005/08/06] \usepackage{fancyhdr} %% For running heads %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% %%%% Interlude: Set up PRINTING (default) or SCREEN VIEWING %%%% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % ForPrinting=true false (default) % Asymmetric margins Symmetric margins % 1 : 1.6 text block aspect ratio 3 : 4 text block aspect ratio % Black hyperlinks Blue hyperlinks % Start major marker pages recto No blank verso pages % \newboolean{ForPrinting} %% UNCOMMENT the next line for a PRINT-OPTIMIZED VERSION of the text %% %\setboolean{ForPrinting}{true} %% Initialize values to ForPrinting=false \newcommand{\Margins}{hmarginratio=1:1} % Symmetric margins \newcommand{\HLinkColor}{blue} % Hyperlink color \newcommand{\PDFPageLayout}{SinglePage} \newcommand{\TransNote}{Transcriber's Note} \newcommand{\TransNoteCommon}{% The camera-quality files for this public-domain ebook may be downloaded \textit{gratis} at \begin{center} \texttt{www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/\ebook}. \end{center} This ebook was produced using scanned images and OCR text generously provided by the University of California, Santa Barbara, through the Internet Archive. \bigskip Minor typographical corrections and presentational changes have been made without comment. \bigskip } \newcommand{\TransNoteText}{% \TransNoteCommon This PDF file is optimized for screen viewing, but may be recompiled for printing. Please consult the preamble of the \LaTeX\ source file for instructions and other particulars. } %% Re-set if ForPrinting=true \ifthenelse{\boolean{ForPrinting}}{% \renewcommand{\Margins}{hmarginratio=2:3} % Asymmetric margins \renewcommand{\HLinkColor}{black} % Hyperlink color \renewcommand{\PDFPageLayout}{TwoPageRight} \renewcommand{\TransNote}{Transcriber's Note} \renewcommand{\TransNoteText}{% \TransNoteCommon This PDF file is optimized for printing, but may be recompiled for screen viewing. Please consult the preamble of the \LaTeX\ source file for instructions and other particulars. } }{% If ForPrinting=false, don't skip to recto \renewcommand{\cleardoublepage}{\clearpage} } %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% %%%% End of PRINTING/SCREEN VIEWING code; back to packages %%%% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \ifthenelse{\boolean{ForPrinting}}{% \setlength{\paperwidth}{8.5in}% \setlength{\paperheight}{11in}% % 1:1.6 \usepackage[body={5in,8in},\Margins]{geometry}[2002/07/08] }{% \setlength{\paperwidth}{4.5in}% \setlength{\paperheight}{6.5in}% \raggedbottom % 3:4 \usepackage[body={4.25in,5.6in},\Margins,includeheadfoot]{geometry}[2002/07/08] } \providecommand{\ebook}{00000} % Overridden during white-washing \usepackage[pdftex, hyperfootnotes=false, pdftitle={The Project Gutenberg eBook \#\ebook: An Introduction to Mathematics.}, pdfauthor={Alfred North Whitehead}, pdfkeywords={University of California, Santa Barbara, The Internet Archive, Andrew D. Hwang}, pdfstartview=Fit, % default value pdfstartpage=1, % default value pdfpagemode=UseNone, % default value bookmarks=true, % default value linktocpage=false, % default value pdfpagelayout=\PDFPageLayout, pdfdisplaydoctitle, pdfpagelabels=true, bookmarksopen=true, bookmarksopenlevel=0, colorlinks=true, linkcolor=\HLinkColor]{hyperref}[2007/02/07] %% Fixed-width environment to format PG boilerplate %% \newenvironment{PGtext}{% \begin{alltt} \fontsize{8.1}{10}\ttfamily\selectfont}% {\end{alltt}} % Errors found during digitization \newcommand{\Typo}[2]{#2} % Changes made for consistency; use \newcommand{\Chg}[2]{#1} to match original \newcommand{\Chg}[2]{#2} \newcommand{\Add}[1]{\Chg{}{#1}} %% Miscellaneous global parameters %% % No hrule in page header \renewcommand{\headrulewidth}{0pt} % Loosen spacing \setlength{\emergencystretch}{1em} \newcommand{\Loosen}{\spaceskip 0.375em plus 0.75em minus 0.25em} % Scratch pad for length calculations \newlength{\TmpLen} %% Running heads %% \newcommand{\FlushRunningHeads}{\clearpage\fancyhf{}} \newcommand{\InitRunningHeads}{% \setlength{\headheight}{15pt} \pagestyle{fancy} \thispagestyle{empty} \ifthenelse{\boolean{ForPrinting}} {\fancyhead[RO,LE]{\thepage}} {\fancyhead[R]{\thepage}} } % Uniform style for running heads \newcommand{\RHeads}[1]{\small\textsc{\MakeUppercase{#1}}} \newcommand{\SetRunningHeads}[1]{% \fancyhead[CO]{\RHeads{Introduction to Mathematics}}% \fancyhead[CE]{\RHeads{#1}}% } \newcommand{\BookMark}[2]{\phantomsection\pdfbookmark[#1]{#2}{#2}} %% Major document divisions %% \newcommand{\PGBoilerPlate}{% \pagenumbering{Alph} \pagestyle{empty} \BookMark{0}{PG Boilerplate.} } \newcommand{\FrontMatter}{% \cleardoublepage \frontmatter \BookMark{-1}{Front Matter.} } \newcommand{\MainMatter}{% \FlushRunningHeads \InitRunningHeads \mainmatter \BookMark{-1}{Main Matter.} } \newcommand{\BackMatter}{% \FlushRunningHeads \InitRunningHeads \backmatter \BookMark{-1}{Back Matter.} } \newcommand{\PGLicense}{% \FlushRunningHeads \pagenumbering{Roman} \InitRunningHeads \BookMark{-1}{PG License.} \fancyhead[C]{\RHeads{License}} } %% ToC formatting %% \newcommand{\TableofContents}{% \FlushRunningHeads \InitRunningHeads \SetRunningHeads{Contents} \BookMark{0}{Contents.} \SectTitle{Contents} } % Set the section number in a fixed-width box \newcommand{\ToCBox}[1]{\settowidth{\TmpLen}{XVII.}% \makebox[\TmpLen][r]{#1}\hspace*{1em}% } % For internal use, to determine if we need the Sect./Page line \newcommand{\ToCAnchor}{} % \ToCLine{Chapter}{Title}{page number} \newcommand{\ToCLine}[3]{% \ifthenelse{\not\equal{#1}{}}{% \label{toc:#1}% \ifthenelse{\not\equal{\pageref{toc:#1}}{\ToCAnchor}}{% \renewcommand{\ToCAnchor}{\pageref{toc:#1}}% \noindent\makebox[\textwidth][r]{\scriptsize CHAP.\hfill PAGE}\\[8pt]% }{}% \settowidth{\TmpLen}{999}% \noindent\strut\parbox[b]{\textwidth-\TmpLen}{\small% \ToCBox{#1}\hangindent4em\MakeUppercase{#2}\dotfill}% \makebox[\TmpLen][r]{\pageref{chapter:#1}}% }{% else #1 = {} \label{toc:#2}% \ifthenelse{\not\equal{\pageref{toc:#2}}{\ToCAnchor}}{% \renewcommand{\ToCAnchor}{\pageref{toc:#2}}% \noindent\makebox[\textwidth][r]{\scriptsize CHAP.\hfill PAGE}\\[8pt]% }{}% \settowidth{\TmpLen}{999}% \noindent\strut\parbox[b]{\textwidth-\TmpLen}{\small% \ToCBox{}\hangindent4em\MakeUppercase{#2}\dotfill}% \makebox[\TmpLen][r]{\pageref{appendix:#2}}% }% \smallskip } %% Sectional units %% % Typographical abstraction \newcommand{\ChapHead}[2]{% \SectTitle{#1} \SubsectTitle{#2} } \newcommand{\SectTitle}[1]{% \section*{\centering\large\normalfont\MakeUppercase{#1}} } \newcommand{\SubsectTitle}[1]{% \subsection*{\centering\normalsize\normalfont\MakeUppercase{#1}} } % \Chapter[running head]{Number}{Title} \newcommand{\Chapter}[3][]{% \FlushRunningHeads \InitRunningHeads \ifthenelse{\equal{#1}{}}{% \BookMark{0}{#2: #3.}% \SetRunningHeads{#3}% }{% \ifthenelse{\equal{#2}{VIII}}{ \BookMark{0}{#2: #1 (Continued).}% }{% \BookMark{0}{#2: #1.}% } \SetRunningHeads{#1}% } \Pagelabel[chapter]{#2} \ifthenelse{\equal{#2}{I}}{% \section*{\normalfont\centering\Large AN INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS} }{} \ChapHead{Chapter #2}{#3} } \newcommand{\Appendix}[2][]{% \FlushRunningHeads \InitRunningHeads \BookMark{0}{#2.} \fancyhead[C]{\RHeads{#2}} \Pagelabel[appendix]{#2}% \SectTitle{#2}% \ifthenelse{\not\equal{#1}{}}{% \SubsectTitle{#1}% }{} } %% Diagrams %% \newcommand{\Graphic}[2]{% \phantomsection\label{fig:#2}% \includegraphics[width=#1]{./images/#2.pdf}% } % \Figure[width]{figure number} \newcommand{\DefWidth}{4in}% Default figure width \newcommand{\Figure}[2][\DefWidth]{% \begin{figure}[hbt!] \centering \phantomsection\label{fig:#2} \Graphic{#1}{fig#2} \caption{Fig.~#2.} \end{figure}\ignorespaces% } \newcommand{\Diagram}[1]{% \begin{figure}[hbt!] \centering \Graphic{\DefWidth}{#1} \end{figure}\ignorespaces% } % Figure labels \newcommand{\FigNum}[1]{\hyperref[fig:#1]{#1}} \newcommand{\Fig}[2][Fig.]{\hyperref[fig:#2]{#1~#2}} \newcommand{\ChapNum}[1]{\hyperref[chapter:#1]{#1}} \newcommand{\ChapRef}[2][Chapter]{\hyperref[chapter:#2]{\Chg{#1}{Chapter}~#2}} \newcommand{\Note}[1]{#1\Pagelabel{note#1}} \newcommand{\Pagelabel}[2][page]{\phantomsection\label{#1:#2}} \newcommand{\Pageref}[2][p.]{\hyperref[page:#2]{#1~\pageref*{page:#2}}} % Page separators \newcommand{\PageSep}[1]{\ignorespaces} %% Index formatting \makeindex \makeatletter \renewcommand{\@idxitem}{\par\hangindent 30\p@\global\let\idxbrk\nobreak} \renewcommand\subitem{\idxbrk\@idxitem \hspace*{12\p@}\let\idxbrk\relax} \renewcommand{\indexspace}{\par\penalty-3000 \vskip 10pt plus5pt minus3pt\relax} \renewenvironment{theindex}{% \setlength\columnseprule{0.5pt}\setlength\columnsep{18pt}% \begin{multicols}{2}[{\FlushRunningHeads% \InitRunningHeads% \BookMark{0}{Index.}% \fancyhead[C]{\RHeads{Index}}% \Pagelabel[appendix]{Index}% \SectTitle{Index}\small}]% \setlength\parindent{0pt}\setlength\parskip{0pt plus 0.3pt}% \let\item\@idxitem\raggedright% }{% \end{multicols}\normalsize\FlushRunningHeads } \makeatother \newcommand{\EtSeq}[1]{\hyperpage{#1}\,\textit{et~seqq.}} % Miscellaneous textual conveniences (N.B. \emph, not \textit) \newcommand{\Cf}{\emph{Cf.}} \newcommand{\cf}{\emph{cf.}} \newcommand{\eg}{\emph{e.g.}} \newcommand{\ie}{\emph{i.e.}} \newcommand{\viz}{\emph{viz.}} \newcommand{\First}[1]{\textsc{#1}} \newcommand{\Title}[1]{\textit{#1}} \newcommand{\Foreign}[1]{\textit{#1}} % Small-caps A.D. and B.C. \newcommand{\SCAbbrev}[3]{% \ifthenelse{\equal{#3}{.}}% {\textsc{\MakeLowercase{#1.#2}.}}% {\textsc{\MakeLowercase{#1.#2}.}\@#3}% } \newcommand{\AD}[1]{\SCAbbrev{A}{D}{#1}} \newcommand{\BC}[1]{\SCAbbrev{B}{C}{#1}} %% Miscellaneous mathematical formatting %% \DeclareInputMath{176}{{}^{\circ}} \DeclareInputMath{183}{\cdot} \newcommand{\Strut}[1][12pt]{\rule{0pt}{#1}} % Cross-ref-able equation tags \newcommand{\Tag}[1]{\tag*{\quad\ensuremath{#1}}} \newcommand{\Eq}[1]{\ensuremath{#1}} %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% START OF DOCUMENT %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \begin{document} %% PG BOILERPLATE %% \PGBoilerPlate \begin{center} \begin{minipage}{\textwidth} \small \begin{PGtext} Project Gutenberg's An Introduction to Mathematics, by Alfred North Whitehead This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org Title: An Introduction to Mathematics Author: Alfred North Whitehead Release Date: December 6, 2012 [EBook #41568] Most recently updated: June 11, 2021 Language: English Character set encoding: UTF-8 *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK AN INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS *** \end{PGtext} \end{minipage} \end{center} \newpage %% Credits and transcriber's note %% \begin{center} \begin{minipage}{\textwidth} \begin{PGtext} Produced by Andrew D. Hwang. (This ebook was produced using OCR text generously provided by the University of California, Santa Barbara, through the Internet Archive.) \end{PGtext} \end{minipage} \vfill \end{center} \begin{minipage}{0.85\textwidth} \small \BookMark{0}{Transcriber's Note.} \subsection*{\centering\normalfont\scshape% \normalsize\MakeLowercase{\TransNote}}% \raggedright \TransNoteText \end{minipage} %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% FRONT MATTER %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \PageSep{i} \FrontMatter %[** TN: Publisher's front matter] \noindent\footnotesize HOME UNIVERSITY LIBRARY \\ OF MODERN KNOWLEDGE \vfill \begin{center} \Large AN INTRODUCTION TO \\ MATHEMATICS \medskip \normalsize \textsc{By A. N. WHITEHEAD, Sc.D., F.R.S.} \vfill \footnotesize \scshape London \\ {\normalsize WILLIAMS \& NORGATE} \\[6pt] \rule{0.5in}{0.5pt} \\[6pt] HENRY HOLT \& Co., New York \\ Canada: WM. BRIGGS, Toronto \\ India: R. \& T. WASHBOURNE, Ltd. \end{center} \normalsize \PageSep{ii} \iffalse HOME UNIVERSITY LIBRARY OF MODERN KNOWLEDGE Editors: HERBERT FISHER, M.A.. F.B.A. PROF. GILBERT MURRAY, D.LlTT., LL.D., F.B.A. PROF. J. ARTHUR THOMSON, M.A. PROF. WILLIAM T. BREWSTER, M.A. \Add{(}COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY, U.S.A.) NEW YORK HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY \PageSep{iii} AN INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS BY A. N. WHITEHEAD, Sc.D., F.R.S., AUTHOR OF ``UNIVERSAL ALGEBRA,'' JOINT AUTHOR OF ``PRINCIPIA MATHEMATICA'' NEW AND REVISED EDITION LONDON WILLIAMS AND NORGATE \PageSep{iv} PRINTED BY HALELL, WATSON AND VINEY, LD., LONDON AND AYLESBURY. \fi \PageSep{v} \TableofContents %CHAP. PAGE \ToCLine{I}{The Abstract Nature of Mathematics}{7} \ToCLine{II}{Variables}{15} \ToCLine{III}{Methods of Application}{25} \ToCLine{IV}{Dynamics}{42} \ToCLine{V}{The Symbolism of Mathematics}{58} \ToCLine{VI}{Generalizations of Number}{71} \ToCLine{VII}{Imaginary Numbers}{87} \ToCLine{VIII}{Imaginary Numbers (Continued)}{101} \ToCLine{IX}{Coordinate Geometry}{112} \ToCLine{X}{Conic Sections}{128} \ToCLine{XI}{Functions}{145} \ToCLine{XII}{Periodicity in Nature}{164} \PageSep{vi} %CHAP. PAGE \ToCLine{XIII}{Trigonometry}{173} \ToCLine{XIV}{Series}{194} \ToCLine{XV}{The Differential Calculus}{217} \ToCLine{XVI}{Geometry}{236} \ToCLine{XVII}{Quantity}{245} \ToCLine{}{Notes}{250} \ToCLine{}{Bibliography}{251} \ToCLine{}{Index}{253} \PageSep{7} \MainMatter % [** TN: Text printed by \Chapter macro] % AN INTRODUCTION TO % MATHEMATICS \Chapter[Nature of Mathematics]{I}{The Abstract Nature of Mathematics} \First{The} study of mathematics is apt to commence in disappointment. The important applications of the science, the theoretical interest of its ideas, and the logical rigour of its methods, all generate the expectation of a speedy introduction to processes of interest. We are told that by its aid the stars are weighed and the billions of molecules in a drop of water are counted. Yet, like the ghost of Hamlet's father, this great science eludes the efforts of our mental weapons to grasp it---``\,'Tis here, 'tis there, 'tis gone''---and what we do see does not suggest the same excuse for illusiveness as sufficed for the ghost, that it is too noble for our gross methods. ``A show of violence,'' if ever excusable, may surely be ``offered'' to the trivial results which occupy the \PageSep{8} pages of some elementary mathematical treatises. The reason for this failure of the science to live up to its reputation is that its fundamental ideas are not explained to the student disentangled from the technical procedure which has been invented to facilitate their exact presentation in particular instances. Accordingly, the unfortunate learner finds himself struggling to acquire a knowledge of a mass of details which are not illuminated by any general conception. Without a doubt, technical facility is a first requisite for valuable mental activity: we shall fail to appreciate the rhythm of Milton, or the passion of Shelley, so long as we find it necessary to spell the words and are not quite certain of the forms of the individual letters. In this sense there is no royal road to learning. But it is equally an error to confine attention to technical processes, excluding consideration of general ideas. Here lies the road to pedantry. The object of the following Chapters is not to teach mathematics, but to enable students from the very beginning of their course to know what the science is about, and why it is necessarily the foundation of exact thought as applied to natural phenomena. All allusion in what follows to detailed deductions in any part of the science will be inserted \PageSep{9} merely for the purpose of example, and care will be taken to make the general argument comprehensible, even if here and there some technical process or symbol which the reader does not understand is cited for the purpose of illustration. The first acquaintance which most people \index{Abstractness (\emph{defined})}% have with mathematics is through arithmetic. That two and two make four is usually taken as the type of a simple mathematical proposition which everyone will have heard of. Arithmetic, therefore, will be a good subject to consider in order to discover, if possible, the most obvious characteristic of the science. Now, the first noticeable fact about arithmetic is that it applies to everything, to tastes and to sounds, to apples and to angels, to the ideas of the mind and to the bones of the body. The nature of the things is perfectly indifferent, of all things it is true that two and two make four. Thus we write down as the leading characteristic of mathematics that it deals with properties and ideas which are applicable to things just because they are things, and apart from any particular feelings, or emotions, or sensations, in any way connected with them. This is what is meant by calling mathematics an abstract science. The result which we have reached deserves attention. It is natural to think that an \PageSep{10} abstract science cannot be of much importance in the affairs of human life, because it has omitted from its consideration everything of real interest. It will be remembered that Swift, in his description of Gulliver's \index{Swift}% voyage to Laputa, is of two minds on this \index{Laputa}% point. He describes the mathematicians of that country as silly and useless dreamers, whose attention has to be awakened by flappers. Also, the mathematical tailor measures his height by a quadrant, and deduces his other dimensions by a rule and compasses, producing a suit of very ill-fitting clothes. On the other hand, the mathematicians of Laputa, by their marvellous invention of the magnetic island floating in the air, ruled the country and maintained their ascendency over their subjects. Swift, indeed, lived at a time peculiarly unsuited for gibes at contemporary mathematicians. Newton's \Title{Principia} \index{Newton}% had just been written, one of the great forces which have transformed the modern world. Swift might just as well have laughed at an earthquake. But a mere list of the achievements of mathematics is an unsatisfactory way of arriving at an idea of its importance. It is worth while to spend a little thought in getting at the root reason why mathematics, because of its very abstractness, must always remain one of the most important topics \PageSep{11} for thought. Let us try to make clear to ourselves why explanations of the order of events necessarily tend to become mathematical. Consider how all events are interconnected. When we see the lightning, we listen for the thunder; when we hear the wind, we look for the waves on the sea; in the chill autumn, the leaves fall. Everywhere order reigns, so that when some circumstances have been noted we can foresee that others will also be present. The progress of science consists in observing these interconnections and in showing with a patient ingenuity that the events of this evershifting world are but examples of a few general connections or relations called laws. To see what is general in what is particular and what is permanent in what is transitory is the aim of scientific thought. In the eye of science, the fall of an apple, the motion of a planet round a sun, and the clinging of the atmosphere to the earth are all seen as examples of the law of gravity. This possibility of disentangling the most complex evanescent circumstances into various examples of permanent laws is the controlling idea of modern thought. Now let us think of the sort of laws which we want in order completely to realize this scientific ideal. Our knowledge of the particular facts of the world around us is gained \PageSep{12} from our sensations. We see, and hear, and taste, and smell, and feel hot and cold, and push, and rub, and ache, and tingle. These are just our own personal sensations: my toothache cannot be your toothache, and my sight cannot be your sight. But we ascribe the origin of these sensations to relations between the things which form the external world. Thus the dentist extracts not the toothache but the tooth. And not only so, we also endeavour to imagine the world as one connected set of things which underlies all the perceptions of all people. There is not one world of things for my sensations and another for yours, but one world in which we both exist. It is the same tooth both for dentist and patient. Also we hear and we touch the same world as we see. It is easy, therefore, to understand that we want to describe the connections between these external things in some way which does not depend on any particular sensations, nor even on all the sensations of any particular person. The laws satisfied by the course of events in the world of external things are to be described, if possible, in a neutral universal fashion, the same for blind men as for deaf men, and the same for beings with faculties beyond our ken as for normal human beings. But when we have put aside our immediate \PageSep{13} \index{Abstractness (\emph{defined})}% \index{Dynamical Explanation}% sensations, the most serviceable part---from its clearness, definiteness, and universality---of what is left is composed of our general ideas of the abstract formal properties of things; in fact, the abstract mathematical ideas mentioned above. Thus it comes about that, step by step, and not realizing the full meaning of the process, mankind has been led to search for a mathematical description of the properties of the universe, because in this way only can a general idea of the course of events be formed, freed from reference to particular persons or to particular types of sensation. For example, it might be asked at dinner: ``What was it which underlay my sensation of sight, yours of touch, and his of taste and smell?''\ the answer being ``an apple.'' But in its final analysis, science seeks to describe an apple in terms of the positions and motions of molecules, a description which ignores me and you and him, and also ignores sight and touch and taste and smell. Thus mathematical ideas, because they are abstract, supply just what is wanted for a scientific description of the course of events. This point has usually been misunderstood, %[** TN: Entry listed on p. 18 in the original] \index{Pythagoras}% from being thought of in too narrow a way. Pythagoras had a glimpse of it when he proclaimed that number was the source of all things. In modern times the belief that the \PageSep{14} ultimate explanation of all things was to be found in Newtonian mechanics was an adumbration of the truth that all science as it grows towards perfection becomes mathematical \index{Dynamical Explanation}% in its ideas. \PageSep{15} \Chapter{II}{Variables} \First{Mathematics} as a science commenced when first someone, probably a Greek, proved propositions about \emph{any} things or about \emph{some} things, without specification of definite particular things. These propositions were first enunciated by the Greeks for geometry; and, accordingly, geometry was the great Greek mathematical science. After the rise of geometry centuries passed away before algebra made a really effective start, despite some faint anticipations by the later Greek mathematicians. The ideas of \emph{any} and of \emph{some} are introduced into algebra by the use of letters, instead of the definite numbers of arithmetic. Thus, instead of saying that $2 + 3 = 3 + 2$, in algebra we generalize and say that, if $x$ and~$y$ stand for \emph{any} two numbers, then $x + y = y + x$. Again, in the place of saying that $3 > 2$, we generalize and say that if $x$~be \emph{any} number there exists \emph{some} number (or numbers)~$y$ such that $y > x$. We may remark in passing that this latter assumption---for when put in its strict ultimate form it is an assumption---is \PageSep{16} of vital importance, both to philosophy and to mathematics; for by it the notion of infinity is introduced. Perhaps it required the introduction of the arabic numerals, by which the use of letters as standing for definite numbers has been completely discarded in mathematics, in order to suggest to mathematicians the technical convenience of the use of letters for the ideas of \emph{any} number and \emph{some} number. The Romans would have stated the number of the year in which this is written in the form MDCCCCX., whereas we write it~1910, thus leaving the letters for the other usage. But this is merely a speculation. After the rise of algebra the differential calculus was invented by Newton and \index{Newton}% Leibniz, and then a pause in the progress \index{Leibniz}% of the philosophy of mathematical thought occurred so far as these notions are concerned; and it was not till within the last few years that it has been realized how fundamental \emph{any} and \emph{some} are to the very nature of mathematics, with the result of opening out still further subjects for mathematical exploration. Let us now make some simple algebraic statements, with the object of understanding exactly how these fundamental ideas occur. \Eq{(1)} For \emph{any} number~$x$, $x + 2 = 2 + x$; \Eq{(2)} For \emph{some} number~$x$, $x + 2 = 3$; \Eq{(3)} For \emph{some} number~$x$, $x + 2 > 3$. \PageSep{17} The first point to notice is the possibilities contained in the meaning of \emph{some}, as here used. Since $x + 2 = 2 + x$ for any number~$x$, it is true for \emph{some} number~$x$. Thus, as here used, \emph{any} implies \emph{some} and \emph{some} does not exclude \emph{any}. Again, in the second example, there is, in fact, only one number~$x$, such that $x + 2 = 3$, namely only the number~$1$. Thus the \emph{some} may be one number only. But in the third\Typo{,}{} example, any number~$x$ which is greater than~$1$ gives $x + 2 > 3$. Hence there are an infinite number of numbers which answer to the \emph{some} number in this case. Thus \emph{some} may be anything between \emph{any} and \emph{one only}, including both these limiting cases. It is natural to supersede the statements \Eq{(2)} and \Eq{(3)} by the questions: \Eq{(2')} For what number~$x$ is $x + 2 = 3$; \Eq{(3')} For what numbers~$x$ is $x + 2 > 3$. %[** TN: No indent in the original] Considering~\Eq{(2')}, $x + 2 = 3$ is an equation, and \index{Unknown, The}% it is easy to see that its solution is $x = 3 - 2 = 1$. When we have asked the question implied in the statement of the equation $x + 2 = 3$, $x$~is called the unknown. The object of the solution of the equation is the determination of the unknown. Equations are of great importance in mathematics, and it seems as %[** TN: thoroughgoing hyphenated in the original; only instance] though \Eq{(2')}~exemplified a much more thoroughgoing and fundamental idea than the original statement~\Eq{(2)}. This, however, is a complete mistake. The idea of the undetermined \PageSep{18} ``variable'' as occurring in the use of ``some'' or ``any'' is the really important one in mathematics; that of the ``unknown'' in an equation, which is to be solved as quickly as possible, is only of subordinate use, though of course it is very important. One of the causes of the apparent triviality of much of elementary algebra is the preoccupation of the text-books with the solution of equations. The same remark applies to the solution of the inequality~\Eq{(3')} as compared to the original statement~\Eq{(3)}. But the majority of interesting formulæ, \index{Relations between Variables|EtSeq}% \index{Variable, The}% especially when the idea of \emph{some} is present, involve more than one variable. For example, the consideration of the pairs of numbers $x$ and~$y$ (fractional or integral) which satisfy $x + y = 1$ involves the idea of two correlated variables, $x$~and~$y$. When two variables are present the same two main types of statement occur. For example, \Eq{(1)}~for \emph{any} pair of numbers, $x$~and~$y$, $x + y = y + x$, and \Eq{(2)}~for \emph{some} pairs of numbers, $x$~and~$y$, $x + y = 1$. The second type of statement invites consideration of the aggregate of pairs of numbers which are bound together by some fixed relation---in the case given, by the relation $x + y = 1$. One use of formulæ of the first type, true for \emph{any} pair of numbers, is that by them formulæ of the second type can be \PageSep{19} thrown into an indefinite number of equivalent forms. For example, the relation $x + y = 1$ is equivalent to the relations \[ y + x = 1,\quad (x - y) + 2y = 1,\quad 6x + 6y = 6, \] and so on. Thus a skilful mathematician uses that equivalent form of the relation under consideration which is most convenient for his immediate purpose. It is not in general true that, when a pair of terms satisfy some fixed relation, if one of the terms is given the other is also definitely determined. For example, when $x$ and~$y$ satisfy $y^{2} = x$, if $x = 4$, $y$~can be~$±2$, thus, for any positive value of~$x$ there are alternative values for~$y$. Also in the relation $x + y > 1$, when either $x$ or~$y$ is given, an indefinite number of values remain open for the other. Again there is another important point to be noticed. If we restrict ourselves to positive numbers, integral or fractional, in considering the relation $x + y = 1$, then, if either $x$ or~$y$ be greater than~$1$, there is no positive number which the other can assume so as to satisfy the relation. Thus the ``field'' of the relation for~$x$ is restricted to numbers less than~$1$, and similarly for the ``field'' open to~$y$. Again, consider integral numbers only, positive or negative, and take the relation \PageSep{20} $y^{2} = x$, satisfied by pairs of such numbers. Then whatever integral value is given to~$y$, $x$~can assume one corresponding integral value. So the ``field'' for~$y$ is unrestricted among these positive or negative integers. But the ``field'' for~$x$ is restricted in two ways. In the first place $x$~must be positive, and in the second place, since $y$~is to be integral, $x$~must be a perfect square. Accordingly, the ``field'' of~$x$ is restricted to the set of integers $1^{2}$, $2^{2}$, $3^{2}$, $4^{2}$, and so on, \ie, to $1$, $4$, $9$, $16$, and so on. The study of the general properties of a relation between pairs of numbers is much facilitated by the use of a diagram constructed as follows: \Figure[3.5in]{1} Draw two lines $OX$ and $OY$ at right angles; let any number~$x$ be represented by $x$~units \PageSep{21} (in any scale) of length along~$OX$, any number~$y$ by $y$~units (in any scale) of length along~$OY$. Thus if $OM$, along~$OX$, be $x$~units in length, and $ON$, along~$OY$, be $y$~units in length, by completing the parallelogram $OMPN$ we find a point~$P$ which corresponds to the pair of numbers $x$~and~$y$. To each point there corresponds one pair of numbers, and to each pair of numbers there corresponds one point. The pair of numbers are called the coordinates of the point. Then the points whose coordinates satisfy some fixed relation can be indicated in a convenient way, by drawing a line, if they all lie on a line, or by shading an area if they are all points in the area. If the relation can be represented by an equation such as $x + y = 1$, or $y^{2} = x$, then the points lie on a line, which is straight in the former case and curved in the latter. For example, considering only positive numbers, the points whose coordinates satisfy $x + y = 1$ lie on the straight line~$AB$ in \Fig{1}, where $0A = 1$ and $OB = 1$. Thus this segment of the straight line~$AB$ gives a pictorial representation of the properties of the relation under the restriction to positive numbers. Another example of a relation between two variables is afforded by considering the variations in the pressure and volume of a given mass of some gaseous substance---such as air \PageSep{22} or coal-gas or steam---at a constant temperature. Let $v$~be the number of cubic feet in its volume and $p$~its pressure in lb.\ weight per square inch. Then the law, known as Boyle's law, expressing the relation between $p$ and~$v$ as both vary, is that the product~$pv$ is constant, always supposing that the temperature does not alter. Let us suppose, for example, that the quantity of the gas and its other circumstances are such that we can put $pv = 1$ (the exact number on the right-hand side of the equation makes no essential difference). \Figure{2} Then in \Fig{2} we take two lines, $OV$ and~$OP$, at right angles and draw~$OM$ along~$OV$ to represent $v$~units of volume, and $ON$ along~$OP$ \PageSep{23} to represent $p$~units of pressure. Then the point~$Q$, which is found by completing the parallelogram $OMQN$, represents the state of the gas when its volume is $v$~cubic feet and its pressure is $p$~lb.\ weight per square inch. If the circumstances of the portion of gas considered are such that $pv = 1$, then all these points~$Q$ which correspond to any possible state of this portion of gas must lie on the curved line $ABC$, which includes all points for which $p$~and $v$ are positive, and $pv = 1$. Thus this curved line gives a pictorial representation of the relation holding between the volume and the pressure. When the pressure is very big the corresponding point~$Q$ must be near~$C$, or even beyond~$C$ on the undrawn part of the curve; then the volume will be very small. When the volume is big $Q$~will be near to~$A$, or beyond~$A$; and then the pressure will be small. Notice that an engineer or a physicist may want to know the particular pressure corresponding to some definitely assigned volume. Then we have the case of determining the \emph{unknown}~$p$ when \index{Unknown, The}% $v$~is a known number. But this is only in particular cases. In considering generally the properties of the gas and how it will behave, he has to have in his mind the general form of the whole curve $ABC$ and its general properties. In other words the really fundamental idea is that of the pair of \emph{variables} \PageSep{24} satisfying the relation $pv = 1$. This example illustrates how the idea of \emph{variables} is fundamental, \index{Variable, The}% both in the applications as well as in the theory of mathematics. \PageSep{25} \Chapter{III}{Methods of Application} \First{The} way in which the idea of variables satisfying a relation occurs in the applications of mathematics is worth thought, and by devoting some time to it we shall clear up our thoughts on the whole subject. Let us start with the simplest of examples:---Suppose that building costs $1$\textit{s.}\ per cubic foot and that $20$\textit{s.}\ make~£$1$. Then in all the complex circumstances which attend the building of a new house, amid all the various sensations and emotions of the owner, the architect, the builder, the workmen, and the onlookers as the house has grown to completion, this fixed correlation is by the law assumed to hold between the cubic content and the cost to the owner, namely that if $x$~be the number of cubic feet, and £$y$~the cost, then $20y = x$. This correlation of $x$~and $y$ is assumed to be true for the building of any house by any owner. Also, the volume of the house and the cost are not supposed to have been perceived or apprehended by any particular sensation or faculty, or by any \PageSep{26} particular man. They are stated in an abstract general way, with complete indifference to the owner's state of mind when he has to pay the bill. Now think a bit further as to what all this means. The building of a house is a complicated set of circumstances. It is impossible to begin to apply the law, or to test it, unless amid the general course of events it is possible to recognize a definite set of occurrences as forming a particular instance of the building of a house. In short, we must know a house when we see it, and must recognize the events which belong to its building. Then amidst these events, thus isolated in idea from the rest of nature, the two elements of the cost and cubic content must be determinable; and when they are both determined, if the law be true, they satisfy the general formula \[ 20y = x. \] But is the law true? Anyone who has had much to do with building will know that we have here put the cost rather high. It is only for an expensive type of house that it will work out at this price. This brings out another point which must be made clear. While we are making mathematical calculations connected with the formula $20y = x$, it is indifferent to us whether the law be true or \PageSep{27} false. In fact, the very meanings assigned to $x$~and~$y$, as being a number of cubic feet and a number of pounds sterling, are indifferent. During the mathematical investigation we are, in fact, merely considering the properties of this correlation between a pair of variable numbers $x$ and~$y$. Our results will apply equally well, if we interpret $y$ to mean a number of fishermen and $x$~the number of fish caught, so that the assumed law is that on the average each fisherman catches twenty fish. The mathematical certainty of the investigation only attaches to the results considered as giving properties of the correlation $20y = x$ between the variable pair of numbers $x$ and~$y$. There is no mathematical certainty whatever about the cost of the actual building of any house. The law is not quite true and the result it gives will not be quite accurate. In fact, it may well be hopelessly wrong. Now all this no doubt seems very obvious. But in truth with more complicated instances there is no more common error than to assume that, because prolonged and accurate mathematical calculations have been made, the application of the result to some fact of nature is absolutely certain. The conclusion of no argument can be more certain than the assumptions from which it starts. All mathematical calculations about the course of \PageSep{28} nature must start from some assumed law of nature, such, for instance, as the assumed law of the cost of building stated above. Accordingly, however accurately we have calculated that some event must occur, the doubt always remains---Is the law true? If the law states a precise result, almost certainly it is not precisely accurate; and thus even at the best the result, precisely as calculated, is not likely to occur. But then we have no faculty capable of observation with ideal precision, so, after all, our inaccurate laws may be good enough. We will now turn to an actual case, that of Newton and the Law of Gravity. This law states that any two bodies attract one another with a force proportional to the product of their masses, and inversely proportional to the square of the distance between them. Thus if $m$~and~$M$ are the masses of the two bodies, reckoned in lbs.\ say, and $d$~miles is the distance between them, the force on either body, due to the attraction of the other and directed towards it, is proportional to~$\dfrac{mM}{d^{2}}$; thus this force can be written as equal to $\dfrac{kmM}{d^{2}}$, where $k$~is a definite number depending on the absolute magnitude of this attraction and also on the scale by which we choose to measure forces. It is easy to see that, if we \PageSep{29} wish to reckon in terms of forces such as the weight of a mass of $1$~lb., the number which $k$~represents must be extremely small; for when $m$~and $M$ and~$d$ are each put equal to~$1$, $\dfrac{kmM}{d^{2}}$~becomes the gravitational attraction of two equal masses of $1$~lb.\ at the distance of one mile, and this is quite inappreciable. However, we have now got our formula for the force of attraction. If we call this force~$F$, it is $F = k\dfrac{mM}{d^{2}}$, giving the correlation between the variables $F$,~$m$,~$M$, and~$d$. We all know the story of how it was found out. Newton, it states, was sitting in an orchard and watched the fall of an apple, and then the law of universal gravitation burst upon \index{Gravitation}% his mind. It may be that the final formulation of the law occurred to him in an orchard, as well as elsewhere---and he must have been somewhere. But for our purposes it is more instructive to dwell upon the vast amount of preparatory thought, the product of many minds and many centuries, which was necessary before this exact law could be formulated. In the first place, the mathematical habit of mind and the mathematical procedure explained in the previous two chapters had to be generated; otherwise Newton could never have thought of a formula representing the force between \emph{any} two masses \PageSep{30} at \emph{any} distance. Again, what are the meanings \index{Distance}% of the terms employed, Force, Mass, Distance? \index{Force}% \index{Mass}% Take the easiest of these terms, Distance. It seems very obvious to us to conceive all material things as forming a definite geometrical whole, such that the distances of the various parts are measurable in terms of some unit length, such as a mile or a yard. This is almost the first aspect of a material structure which occurs to us. It is the gradual outcome of the study of geometry and of the theory of measurement. Even now, in certain cases, other modes of thought are convenient. In a mountainous country distances are often reckoned in hours. But leaving distance, the other terms, Force and Mass, are much more obscure. The exact comprehension of the ideas which Newton \index{Newton}% meant to convey by these words was of slow growth, and, indeed, Newton himself was the first man who had thoroughly mastered the true general principles of Dynamics. \index{Dynamics}% Throughout the middle ages, under the influence of Aristotle, the science was entirely \index{Aristotle}% misconceived. Newton had the advantage of coming after a series of great men, notably Galileo, in Italy, who in the previous two \index{Galileo}% centuries had reconstructed the science and had invented the right way of thinking about it. He completed their work. Then, finally, having the ideas of force, mass, and distance, \PageSep{31} clear and distinct in his mind, and realising their importance and their relevance to the fall of an apple and the motions of the planets, he hit upon the law of gravitation and proved it to be the formula always satisfied in these various motions. The vital point in the application of mathematical formulæ is to have clear ideas and a correct estimate of their relevance to the phenomena under observation. No less than ourselves, our remote ancestors were impressed with the importance of natural phenomena and with the desirability of taking energetic measures to regulate the sequence of events. Under the influence of irrelevant ideas they executed elaborate religious ceremonies to aid the birth of the new moon, and performed sacrifices to save the sun during the crisis of an eclipse. There is no reason to believe that they were more stupid than we are. But at that epoch there had not been opportunity for the slow accumulation of clear and relevant ideas. The sort of way in which physical sciences \index{Electromagnetism|EtSeq}% grow into a form capable of treatment by mathematical methods is illustrated by the history of the gradual growth of the science of electromagnetism. Thunderstorms are events on a grand scale, arousing terror in men and even animals. From the earliest times they must have been objects of wild \PageSep{32} \index{Electricity|EtSeq}% and fantastic hypotheses, though it may be doubted whether our modern scientific discoveries in connection with electricity are not more astonishing than any of the magical explanations of savages. The Greeks knew that amber (Greek, electron) when rubbed would attract light and dry bodies. In 1600~\AD, Dr.~Gilbert, of Colchester, published \index{Gilbert, Dr.}% the first work on the subject in which any scientific method is followed. He made a list of substances possessing properties similar to those of amber; he must also have the credit of connecting, however vaguely, electric and magnetic phenomena. At the end of the seventeenth and throughout the eighteenth century knowledge advanced. Electrical machines were made, sparks were obtained from them; and the Leyden Jar was invented, by which these effects could be intensified. Some organised knowledge was being obtained; but still no relevant mathematical ideas had been found out. Franklin, \index{Franklin}% in the year 1752, sent a kite into the clouds and proved that thunderstorms were electrical. Meanwhile from the earliest epoch (2634~\BC) the Chinese had utilized the characteristic property of the compass needle, but do not seem to have connected it with any theoretical ideas. The really profound changes in human life all have their ultimate origin in knowledge \PageSep{33} pursued for its own sake. The use of the compass was not introduced into Europe till the end of the twelfth century~\AD, more than $3000$~years after its first use in China. The importance which the science of electromagnetism has since assumed in every department of human life is not due to the superior practical bias of Europeans, but to the fact that in the West electrical and magnetic phenomena were studied by men who were dominated by abstract theoretic interests. The discovery of the electric current is due \index{Electric Current}% to two Italians, Galvani in~1780, and Volta \index{Galvani}% \index{Volta}% in~1792. This great invention opened a new series of phenomena for investigation. The scientific world had now three separate, though allied, groups of occurrences on hand---the effects of ``statical'' electricity arising from frictional electrical machines, the magnetic phenomena, and the effects due to electric currents. From the end of the eighteenth century onwards, these three lines of investigation were quickly \Chg{inter-connected}{interconnected} and the modern science of electromagnetism was constructed, which now threatens to transform human life. Mathematical ideas now appear. During the decade 1780 to~1789, Coulomb, a Frenchman, \index{Coulomb}% proved that magnetic poles attract or repel each other, in proportion to the inverse square of their distances, and also that the \PageSep{34} same law holds for electric charges---laws curiously analogous to that of gravitation. In~1820, Öersted, a Dane, discovered that \index{Oersted@Öersted}% electric currents exert a force on magnets, and almost immediately afterwards the mathematical law of the force was correctly formulated by Ampère, a Frenchman, who \index{Ampere@Ampère}% also proved that two electric currents exerted forces on each other. ``The experimental investigation by which Ampère established the law of the mechanical action between electric currents is one of the most brilliant achievements in science. The whole, theory and experiment, seems as if it had leaped, full-grown and full armed, from the brain of the `Newton of Electricity.' It is perfect \index{Newton}% in form, and unassailable in accuracy, and it is summed up in a formula from which all the phenomena may be deduced, and which must always remain the cardinal formula of electro-dynamics.''\footnote {\Title{Electricity and Magnetism}, Clerk Maxwell, Vol.~II., \index{Clerk Maxwell}% ch.~iii.} The momentous laws of induction between currents and between currents and magnets were discovered by Michael Faraday in 1831--82. \index{Faraday}% Faraday was asked: ``What is the use of this discovery?'' He answered: ``What is the use of a child---it grows to be a man.'' Faraday's child has grown to be a man and is now the basis of all the modern applications \PageSep{35} of electricity. Faraday also reorganized the whole theoretical conception of the science. His ideas, which had not been fully understood by the scientific world, were extended and put into a directly mathematical form by Clerk Maxwell in~1873. As a result of his \index{Clerk Maxwell}% mathematical investigations, Maxwell recognized that, under certain conditions, electrical vibrations ought to be propagated. He at once suggested that the vibrations which form light are electrical. This suggestion has \index{Light}% since been verified, so that now the whole theory of light is nothing but a branch of the % [** TN: Herz [sic]] great science of electricity. Also Herz, a \index{Herz}% German, in~1888, following on Maxwell's ideas, succeeded in producing electric vibrations by direct electrical methods\Add{.} His experiments are the basis of our wireless telegraphy. In more recent years even more fundamental discoveries have been made, and the science continues to grow in theoretic importance and in practical interest. This rapid sketch of its progress illustrates how, by the gradual introduction of the relevant theoretic ideas, suggested by experiment and themselves suggesting fresh experiments, a whole mass of isolated and even trivial phenomena are welded together into one coherent science, in which the results of abstract mathematical deductions, starting from a few simple assumed \PageSep{36} laws, supply the explanation to the complex tangle of the course of events. Finally, passing beyond the particular sciences of electromagnetism and light, we can generalize our point of view still further, and direct our attention to the growth of mathematical physics considered as one great chapter of scientific thought. In the first place, what in the barest outlines is the story of its growth? It did not begin as one science, or as the product of one band of men. The Chaldean shepherds watched the skies, the agents of Government in Mesopotamia and Egypt measured the land, priests and philosophers brooded on the general nature of all things. The vast mass of the operations of nature appeared due to mysterious unfathomable forces. ``The wind bloweth where it listeth'' expresses accurately the blank ignorance then existing of any stable rules followed in detail by the succession of phenomena. In broad outline, then as now, a regularity of events was patent. But no minute tracing of their interconnection was possible, and there was no knowledge how even to set about to construct such a science. Detached speculations, a few happy or unhappy shots at the nature of things, formed the utmost which could be produced. Meanwhile land-surveys had produced geometry, \index{Geometry}% \PageSep{37} and the observations of the heavens disclosed the exact regularity of the solar system. Some of the later Greeks, such as Archimedes, had just views on the elementary \index{Archimedes|EtSeq}% phenomena of hydrostatics and optics. Indeed, Archimedes, who combined a genius for mathematics with a physical insight, must rank with Newton, who lived nearly two \index{Newton}% thousand years later, as one of the founders of mathematical physics. He lived at Syracuse, the great Greek city of Sicily. When the Romans besieged the town (in 212~to 210~\BC), he is said to have burned their ships by concentrating on them, by means of mirrors, the sun's rays. The story is highly improbable, but is good evidence of the reputation which he had gained among his contemporaries for his knowledge of optics. At the end of this siege he was killed. According to one account given by Plutarch, in his life of \index{Plutarch}% Marcellus, he was found by a Roman soldier \index{Marcellus}% absorbed in the study of a geometrical diagram which he had traced on the sandy floor of his room. He did not immediately obey the orders of his captor, and so was killed. For the credit of the Roman generals it must be said that the soldiers had orders to spare him. The internal evidence for the other famous story of him is very strong; for the discovery attributed to him is one eminently worthy of his genius for mathematical and physical research. \PageSep{38} Luckily, it is simple enough to be explained here in detail. It is one of the best easy examples of the method of application of mathematical ideas to physics. Hiero, King of Syracuse, had sent a quantity \index{Hiero}% of gold to some goldsmith to form the material of a crown. He suspected that the craftsmen had abstracted some of the gold and had supplied its place by alloying the remainder with some baser metal. Hiero sent the crown to Archimedes and asked him to test it. In these days an indefinite number of chemical tests would be available. But then Archimedes had to think out the matter afresh. The solution flashed upon him as he lay in his bath. He jumped up and ran through the streets to the palace, shouting \Foreign{Eureka! Eureka!} (I have found it, I have found it). This day, if we knew which it was, ought to be celebrated as the birthday of mathematical physics; the science came of age when Newton sat in his \index{Newton}% orchard. Archimedes had in truth made a great discovery. He saw that a body when immersed in water is pressed upwards by the surrounding water with a resultant force equal to the weight of the water it displaces. This law can be proved theoretically from the mathematical principles of hydrostatics and can also be verified experimentally. Hence, if $W$~lb.\ be the weight of the crown, as weighed \PageSep{39} in air, and $w$~lb.\ be the weight of the water which it displaces when completely immersed, $W - w$ would be the extra upward force necessary to sustain the crown as it hung in water. Now, this upward force can easily be ascertained by weighing the body as it hangs in water, as shown in the annexed figure. If \Figure{3} the weights in the right-hand scale come to $F$~lb., then the apparent weight of the crown in water is $F$~lb.; and we thus have \[ F = W - w \] and thus \[ w = W - F, \] and \[ \frac{W}{w} = \frac{W}{W - F} \Tag{(A)} \] where $W$ and $F$ are determined by the easy, and fairly precise, operation of weighing. \PageSep{40} Hence, by equation~\Eq{(A)}, $\dfrac{W}{w}$~is known. But $\dfrac{W}{w}$~is the ratio of the weight of the crown to the weight of an equal volume of water. This ratio is the same for any lump of metal of the same material: it is now called the specific gravity of the material, and depends only on the intrinsic nature of the substance and not on its shape or quantity. Thus to test if the crown were of gold, Archimedes had only to take a lump of indisputably pure gold and find its specific gravity by the same process. If the two specific gravities agreed, the crown was pure; if they disagreed, it was debased. This argument has been given at length, because not only is it the first precise example of the application of mathematical ideas to physics, but also because it is a perfect and simple example of what must be the method and spirit of the science for all time. The death of Archimedes by the hands of a Roman soldier is symbolical of a world-change of the first magnitude: the theoretical Greeks, with their love of abstract science, were superseded in the leadership of the European world by the practical Romans. Lord Beaconsfield, \index{Beaconsfield, Lord}% in one of his novels, has defined a practical man as a man who practises the errors of his forefathers. The Romans were a great race, but they were cursed with the sterility \PageSep{41} \index{Specific Gravity}% which waits upon practicality. They did not improve upon the knowledge of their forefathers, and all their advances were confined to the minor technical details of engineering. They were not dreamers enough to arrive at new points of view, which could give a more fundamental control over the forces of nature. No Roman lost his life because he was absorbed in the contemplation of a mathematical diagram. \PageSep{42} \Chapter{IV}{Dynamics} \First{The} world had to wait for eighteen hundred years till the Greek mathematical physicists found successors. In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries of our era great Italians, in particular Leonardo da~Vinci, the artist \index{Aristotle}% \index{Galileo|EtSeq}% \index{Leonardo da Vinci}% (born 1452, died 1519), and Galileo (born 1564, died 1642), rediscovered the secret, known to Archimedes, of relating abstract mathematical ideas with the experimental investigation of natural phenomena. Meanwhile the slow advance of mathematics and the accumulation of accurate astronomical knowledge had placed natural philosophers in a much more advantageous position for research. Also the very egoistic self-assertion of that age, its greediness for personal experience, led its thinkers to want to see for themselves what happened; and the secret of the relation of mathematical theory and experiment in inductive reasoning was practically discovered. It was an act eminently characteristic of the age that Galileo, a philosopher, should have \PageSep{43} dropped the weights from the leaning tower of Pisa. There are always men of thought and men of action; mathematical physics is the product of an age which combined in the same men impulses to thought with impulses to action. This matter of the dropping of weights from \index{Dynamics|EtSeq}% the tower marks picturesquely an essential step in knowledge, no less a step than the first attainment of correct ideas on the science of dynamics, the basal science of the whole subject. The particular point in dispute was as to whether bodies of different weights would fall from the same height in the same time. According to a dictum of Aristotle, universally followed up to that epoch, the heavier weight would fall the quicker. Galileo affirmed that they would fall in the same time, and proved his point by dropping weights from the top of the leaning tower. The apparent exceptions to the rule all arise when, for some reason, such as extreme lightness or great speed, the air resistance is important. But neglecting the air the law is exact. Galileo's successful experiment was not the \index{Motion, First Law of}% result of a mere lucky guess. It arose from his correct ideas in connection with inertia and mass. The first law of motion, as following Newton we now enunciate it, is---Every \index{Newton}% body continues in its state of rest or of uniform \PageSep{44} motion in a straight line, except so far as it is compelled by impressed force to change that state. This law is more than a dry formula: it is also a pæan of triumph over defeated heretics. The point at issue can be understood by deleting from the law the phrase ``or of uniform motion in a straight line.'' We there obtain what might be taken as the Aristotelian opposition formula: ``Every body continues in its state of rest except so far as it is compelled by impressed force to change that state.'' In this last false formula it is asserted that, apart from force, a body continues in a state of rest; and accordingly that, if a body is moving, a force is required to sustain the motion; so that when the force ceases, the motion ceases. The true Newtonian law takes diametrically the opposite point of view. The state of a body unacted on by force is that of uniform motion in a straight line, and no external force or influence is to be looked for as the cause, or, if you like to put it so, as the invariable accompaniment of this uniform rectilinear motion. Rest is merely a particular case of such motion, merely when the velocity is and remains zero. Thus, when a body is moving, we do not seek for any external influence except to explain changes in the rate of the velocity or changes in its direction. So long as the body is moving at the \PageSep{45} same rate and in the same direction there is no need to invoke the aid of any forces. The difference between the two points of view is well seen by reference to the theory of the motion of the planets. Copernicus, a \index{Copernicus}% Pole, born at Thorn in West Prussia (born 1473, died 1543), showed how much simpler it was to conceive the planets, including the \Figure[2.25in]{4} earth as revolving round the sun in orbits which are nearly circular; and later, Kepler, \index{Kepler}% a German mathematician, in the year 1609 proved that, in fact, the orbits are practically ellipses, that is, a special sort of oval curves \index{Ellipse}% which we will consider later in more detail. Immediately the question arose as to what are the forces which preserve the planets in this motion. According to the old false view, \PageSep{46} held by Kepler, the actual velocity itself required \index{Kepler}% preservation by force. Thus he looked for tangential forces as in the accompanying figure~(\FigNum{4}). But according to the Newtonian law, apart from some force the planet would move for ever with its existing velocity in a straight line, and thus depart entirely from the sun. Newton, therefore, had to search \index{Newton}% for a force which would bend the motion \Figure[2.25in]{5} round into its elliptical orbit. This he showed must be a force directed towards the sun as in the next figure~(\FigNum{5}). In fact, the force is the gravitational attraction of the sun acting according to the law of the inverse square of the distance, which has been stated above. The science of mechanics rose among the \index{Mechanics}% Greeks from a consideration of the theory of the mechanical advantage obtained by the use \PageSep{47} \index{Dynamical Explanation|EtSeq}% of a lever, and also from a consideration of various problems connected with the weights of bodies. It was finally put on its true basis at the end of the sixteenth and during the seventeenth centuries, as the preceding account shows, partly with the view of explaining the theory of falling bodies, but chiefly in order to give a scientific theory of planetary motions. But since those days dynamics has taken upon itself a more ambitious task, and now claims to be the ultimate science of which the others are but branches. The claim amounts to this: namely, that the various qualities of things perceptible to the senses are merely our peculiar mode of appreciating changes in position on the part of things existing in space. For example, suppose we look at Westminster Abbey. It has been standing there, grey and immovable, for centuries past. But, according to modern scientific theory, that greyness, which so heightens our sense of the immobility of the building, is itself nothing but our way of appreciating the rapid motions of the ultimate molecules, which form the outer surface of the building and communicate vibrations to a substance called the ether. Again we lay our hands on its stones and note their cool, even temperature, so symbolic of the quiet repose of the building. But this feeling of temperature simply marks our sense of the transfer of heat from the \PageSep{48} hand to the stone, or from the stone to the hand; and, according to modern science, heat is nothing but the agitation of the molecules of a body. Finally, the organ begins playing, and again sound is nothing but the result of motions of the air striking on the drum of the ear. Thus the endeavour to give a dynamical explanation of phenomena is the attempt to explain them by statements of the general form, that such and such a substance or body was in this place and is now in that place. Thus we arrive at the great basal idea of modern science, that all our sensations are the result of comparisons of the changed configurations of things in space at various times. It follows therefore, that the laws of motion, that is, the laws of the changes of configurations of things, are the ultimate laws of physical science. In the application of mathematics to the investigation of natural philosophy, science does systematically what ordinary thought does casually. When we talk of a chair, we usually mean something which we have been seeing or feeling in some way; though most of our language will presuppose that there is something which exists independently of our sight or feeling. Now in mathematical physics the opposite course is taken. The chair is conceived without any reference to \PageSep{49} \index{Variable, The}% anyone in particular, or to any special modes of perception. The result is that the chair becomes in thought a set of molecules in space, or a group of electrons, a portion of the ether in motion, or however the current scientific ideas describe it. But the point is that science reduces the chair to things moving in space and influencing each other's motions. Then the various elements or factors which enter into a set of circumstances, as thus conceived, are merely the things, like lengths of lines, sizes of angles, areas, and volumes, by which the positions of bodies in space can be settled. Of course, in addition to these geometrical elements the fact of motion and change necessitates the introduction of the rates of changes of such elements, that is to say, velocities, angular velocities, accelerations, and suchlike things. Accordingly, mathematical physics deals with correlations between variable numbers which are supposed to represent the correlations which exist in nature between the measures of these geometrical elements and of their rates of change. But always the mathematical laws deal with variables, and it is only in the occasional testing of the laws by reference to experiments, or in the use of the laws for special predictions that definite numbers are substituted. The interesting point about the world as \PageSep{50} thus conceived in this abstract way throughout the study of mathematical physics, where only the positions and shapes of things are considered together with their changes, is that the events of such an abstract world are sufficient to ``explain'' our sensations. When we hear a sound, the molecules of the air have been agitated in a certain way: given the agitation, or air-waves as they are called, all normal people hear sound; and if there are no air-waves, there is no sound. And, similarly, a physical cause or origin, or parallel event (according as different people might like to phrase it) underlies our other sensations. Our very thoughts appear to correspond to conformations and motions of the brain; injure the brain and you injure the thoughts. Meanwhile the events of this physical universe succeed each other according to the mathematical laws which ignore all special sensations and thoughts and emotions. Now, undoubtedly, this is the general aspect of the relation of the world of mathematical physics to our emotions, sensations, and thoughts; and a great deal of controversy has been occasioned by it and much ink spilled. We need only make one remark. The whole situation has arisen, as we have seen, from the endeavour to describe an external world ``explanatory'' of our various individual sensations and emotions, but a world \PageSep{51} also, not essentially dependent upon any particular sensations or upon any particular individual. Is such a world merely but one huge fairy tale? But fairy tales are fantastic and arbitrary: if in truth there be such a world, it ought to submit itself to an exact description, which determines accurately its various parts and their mutual relations. Now, to a large degree, this scientific world does submit itself to this test and allow its events to be explored and predicted by the apparatus of abstract mathematical ideas. It certainly seems that here we have an inductive verification of our initial assumption. It must be admitted that no inductive proof is conclusive; but if the whole idea of a world which has existence independently of our particular perceptions of it be erroneous, it requires careful explanation why the attempt to characterise it, in terms of that mathematical remnant of our ideas which would apply to it, should issue in such a remarkable success. It would take us too far afield to enter into \index{Parallelogram Law|EtSeq}% \index{Vectors|EtSeq}% a detailed explanation of the other laws of motion. The remainder of this chapter must be devoted to the explanation of remarkable ideas which are fundamental, both to mathematical physics and to pure mathematics: these are the ideas of vector quantities and the parallelogram law for vector addition. We \PageSep{52} have seen that the essence of motion is that a body was at~$A$ and is now at~$C$. This transference from $A$ to~$C$ requires two distinct elements to be settled before it is completely determined, namely its magnitude (\ie\ the length~$AC$) and its direction. Now anything, like this transference, which is completely given by the determination of a magnitude \Figure[2in]{6} and a direction is called a vector. For example, a velocity requires for its definition the assignment of a magnitude and of a direction. It must be of so many miles per hour in such and such a direction. The existence and the independence of these two elements in the determination of a velocity are well illustrated by the action of the captain of a ship, who communicates with different subordinates respecting them: he tells the chief engineer the number of knots at which he is to steam, and the helmsman the compass \PageSep{53} bearing of the course which he is to keep. Again the rate of change of velocity, that is velocity added per unit time, is also a vector quantity: it is called the acceleration. Similarly a force in the dynamical sense is another vector quantity. Indeed, the vector nature of forces follows at once according to dynamical principles from that of velocities and accelerations; but this is a point which we need not go into. It is sufficient here to say that a force acts on a body with a certain magnitude in a certain direction. Now all vectors can be graphically represented by straight lines. All that has to be done is to arrange: (i)~a scale according to which units of length correspond to units of magnitude of the vector---for example, one inch to a velocity of $10$~miles per~hour in the case of velocities, and one inch to a force of $10$~tons weight in the case of forces---and (ii)~a direction of the line on the diagram corresponding to the direction of the vector. Then a line drawn with the proper number of inches of length in the proper direction represents the required vector on the arbitrarily assigned scale of magnitude. This diagrammatic representation of vectors is of the first importance. By its aid we can enunciate the famous ``parallelogram law'' for the addition of vectors of the same kind but in different directions. Consider the vector~$AC$ in \Fig[figure]{6} as representative \PageSep{54} \index{Transportation, Vector of|EtSeq}% of the changed position of a body from $A$ to~$C$: we will call this the vector of transportation. It will be noted that, if the reduction of physical phenomena to mere changes in positions, as explained above, is correct, all other types of physical vectors are really reducible in some way or other to this single type. Now the final transportation from $A$ to~$C$ is equally well effected by a transportation from $A$ to~$B$ and a transportation from $B$ to~$C$, or, completing the parallelogram $ABCD$, by a transportation from $A$ to~$D$ and a transportation from $D$ to~$C$. These transportations as thus successively applied are said to be added together. This is simply a definition of what we mean by the addition of transportations. Note further that, considering parallel lines as being lines drawn in the same direction, the transportations $B$~to~$C$ and $A$~to~$D$ may be conceived as the same transportation applied to bodies in the two initial positions $B$ and~$A$. With this conception we may talk of the transportation $A$~to~$D$ as applied to a body in any position, for example at~$B$. Thus we may say that the transportation $A$~to~$C$ can be conceived as the sum of the two transportations $A$~to~$B$ and $A$~to~$D$ applied in any order. Here we have the parallelogram law for the addition of transportations: namely, if the transportations are $A$~to~$B$ and $A$~to~$D$, \PageSep{55} complete the parallelogram $ABCD$, and then the sum of the two is the diagonal~$AC$. All this at first sight may seem to be very artificial. But it must be observed that nature itself presents us with the idea. For example, a steamer is moving in the direction~$AD$ (\Chg{cf.}{\cf}\ \Fig[fig.]{6}) and a man walks across its deck. If the steamer were still, in one minute he would arrive at~$B$; but during that minute his starting point~$A$ on the deck has moved to~$D$, and his path on the deck has moved from $AB$ to~$DC$. So that, in fact, his transportation has been from $A$ to~$C$ over the surface of the sea. It is, however, presented to us analysed into the sum of two transportations, namely, one from $A$ to~$B$ relatively to the steamer, and one from $A$ to~$D$ which is the transportation of the steamer. By taking into account the element of time, namely one minute, this diagram of the man's transportation~$AC$ represents his velocity. For if $AC$~represented so many feet of transportation, it now represents a transportation of so many feet per minute, that is to say, it represents the velocity of the man. Then $AB$ and $AD$ represent two velocities, namely, his velocity relatively to the steamer, and the velocity of the steamer, whose ``sum'' makes up his complete velocity. It is evident that diagrams and definitions concerning transportations \PageSep{56} are turned into diagrams and definitions concerning velocities by conceiving the diagrams as representing transportations per unit time. Again, diagrams and definitions concerning velocities are turned into diagrams and definitions concerning accelerations \Figure[3in]{7} by conceiving the diagrams as representing velocities added per unit time. Thus by the addition of vector velocities and of vector accelerations, we mean the addition according to the parallelogram law. Also, according to the laws of motion a force is fully represented by the vector acceleration it produces in a body of given mass. Accordingly, forces will be said to be added when their joint effect is to be reckoned according to the parallelogram law. Hence for the fundamental vectors of \PageSep{57} science, namely transportations, velocities, and forces, the addition of any two of the same kind is the production of a ``resultant'' vector according to the rule of the parallelogram law. By far the simplest type of parallelogram is a rectangle, and in pure mathematics it is \index{Rectangle}% the relation of the single vector~$AC$ to the two component vectors, $AB$~and~$AD$, at right angles (\Chg{cf.}{\cf}\ \Fig[fig.]{7}), which is continually recurring. Let $x$,~$y$, and $r$~units represent the lengths of $AB$,~$AD$, and~$AC$, and let $m$~units of angle represent the magnitude of the angle $BAC$. Then the relations between $x$,~$y$,~$r$, and~$m$, in all their many aspects are the continually recurring topic of pure mathematics; and the results are of the type required for application to the fundamental vectors of mathematical physics. This diagram is the chief bridge over which the results of pure mathematics pass in order to obtain application to the facts of nature. \PageSep{58} \Chapter{V}{The Symbolism of Mathematics} \First{We} now return to pure mathematics, and consider more closely the apparatus of ideas out of which the science is built. Our first concern is with the symbolism of the science, and we start with the simplest and universally known symbols, namely those of arithmetic. Let us assume for the present that we have \index{Arabic Notation|EtSeq}% sufficiently clear ideas about the integral numbers, represented in the Arabic notation by $0$,~$1$, $2$,~\dots, $9$, $10$, $11$,~\dots\Add{,} $100$, $101$,~\dots\ and so on. This notation was introduced into Europe through the Arabs, but they apparently obtained it from Hindoo sources. The first known work\footnote {For the detailed historical facts relating to pure mathematics, I am chiefly indebted to \Title{A Short History \index{Ball, W. W. R.}% of Mathematics}, by W.~W.~R. Ball.} % [** TN: http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/31246] in which it is systematically explained is a work by an Indian mathematician, Bhaskara (born 1114~\AD). But \index{Bhaskara}% the actual numerals can be traced back to the seventh century of our era, and perhaps were originally invented in Tibet. For our present \PageSep{59} purposes, however, the history of the notation is a detail. The interesting point to notice is the admirable illustration which this numeral system affords of the enormous importance of a good notation. By relieving the brain of all unnecessary work, a good notation sets it free to concentrate on more advanced problems, and in effect increases the mental power of the race. Before the introduction of the Arabic notation, multiplication was difficult, and the division even of integers called into play the highest mathematical faculties. Probably nothing in the modern world would have more astonished a Greek mathematician than to learn that, under the influence of compulsory education, a large proportion of the population of Western Europe could perform the operation of division for the largest numbers. This fact would have seemed to him a sheer impossibility. The consequential extension of the notation to decimal fractions was not accomplished till the seventeenth century. Our modern power of easy reckoning with decimal fractions is the almost miraculous result of the gradual discovery of a perfect notation. Mathematics is often considered a difficult and mysterious science, because of the numerous symbols which it employs. Of course, nothing is more incomprehensible than \PageSep{60} a symbolism which we do not understand. Also a symbolism, which we only partially understand and are unaccustomed to use, is difficult to follow. In exactly the same way the technical terms of any profession or trade are incomprehensible to those who have never been trained to use them. But this is not because they are difficult in themselves. On the contrary they have invariably been introduced to make things easy. So in mathematics, granted that we are giving any serious attention to mathematical ideas, the symbolism is invariably an immense simplification. It is not only of practical use, but is of great interest. For it represents an analysis of the ideas of the subject and an almost pictorial representation of their relations to each other. If anyone doubts the utility of symbols, let him write out in full, without any symbol whatever, the whole meaning of the following equations which represent some of \index{Algebra, Fundamental Laws of}% the fundamental laws of algebra\footnotemark:--- \footnotetext{\Chg{Cf.}{\Cf}\ Note~A, \Pageref{noteA}.\Pagelabel{60}} %[** TN: left-aligned in the original] \begin{gather*} x + y = y + x\Add{,} \Tag{(1)} \\ (x + y) + z = x + (y + z)\Add{,} \Tag{(2)} \\ x × y = y × x\Add{,} \Tag{(3)} \\ (x × y) × z = x × (y × z)\Add{,} \Tag{(4)} \\ x × (y + z) = (x × y) + (x × z)\Add{.} \Tag{(5)} \end{gather*} Here \Eq{(1)}~and \Eq{(2)} are called the commutative and associative laws for addition, \Eq{(3)}~and \Eq{(4)} \PageSep{61} are the commutative and associative laws for multiplication, and \Eq{(5)}~is the distributive law relating addition and multiplication. For example, without symbols, \Eq{(1)}~becomes: If a second number be added to any given number the result is the same as if the first given number had been added to the second number. This example shows that, by the aid of symbolism, we can make transitions in reasoning almost mechanically by the eye, which otherwise would call into play the higher faculties of the brain. It is a profoundly erroneous truism, repeated by all copy-books and by eminent people when they are making speeches, that we should cultivate the habit of thinking of what we are doing. The precise opposite is the case. Civilization advances by extending the number of important operations which we can perform without thinking about them. Operations of thought are like cavalry charges in a battle---they are strictly limited in number, they require fresh horses, and must only be made at decisive moments. One very important property for symbolism to possess is that it should be concise, so as to be visible at one glance of the eye and to be rapidly written. Now we cannot place symbols more concisely together than by placing them in immediate juxtaposition. In a good symbolism therefore, the juxtaposition of important \PageSep{62} symbols should have an important meaning. This is one of the merits of the Arabic notation for numbers; by means of ten symbols, $0$,~$1$, $2$, $3$, $4$, $5$, $6$, $7$, $8$,~$9$, and by simple juxtaposition it symbolizes any number whatever. Again in algebra, when we have two variable numbers $x$ and~$y$, we have to make a choice as to what shall be denoted by their juxtaposition~$xy$. Now the two most important ideas on hand are those of addition and multiplication. Mathematicians have chosen to make their symbolism more concise by defining $xy$ to stand for $x × y$. Thus the laws \Eq{(3)},~\Eq{(4)}, and~\Eq{(5)} above are in general written, \[ xy = yx,\quad (xy)z = x(yz),\quad x(y + z) = xy + xz, \] thus securing a great gain in conciseness. The same rule of symbolism is applied to the juxtaposition of a definite number and a variable: we write~$3x$ for $3 × x$, and $30x$ for $30 × x$. It is evident that in substituting definite numbers for the variables some care must be taken to restore the~$×$, so as not to conflict with the Arabic notation. Thus when we substitute $2$~for~$x$ and $3$~for~$y$ in~$xy$, we must write $2 × 3$ for~$xy$, and not~$23$ which means $20 + 3$. It is interesting to note how important for the development of science a modest-looking symbol may be. It may stand for the emphatic presentation of an idea, often a very \PageSep{63} subtle idea, and by its existence make it easy to exhibit the relation of this idea to all the complex trains of ideas in which it occurs. For example, take the most modest of all symbols, namely,~$0$, which stands for the \emph{number} \index{Zero|EtSeq}% zero. The Roman notation for numbers had no symbol for zero, and probably most mathematicians of the ancient world would have been horribly puzzled by the idea of the number zero. For, after all, it is a very subtle idea, not at all obvious. A great deal of discussion on the meaning of the zero of quantity will be found in philosophic works. Zero is not, in real truth, more difficult or subtle in idea than the other cardinal numbers. What do we mean by~$1$ or by~$2$, or by~$3$? But we are familiar with the use of these ideas, though we should most of us be puzzled to give a clear analysis of the simpler ideas which go to form them. The point about zero is that we do not need to use it in the operations of daily life. No one goes out to buy zero fish. It is in a way the most civilized of all the cardinals, and its use is only forced on us by the needs of cultivated modes of thought. Many important services are rendered by the symbol~$0$, which stands for the number zero. The symbol developed in connection with the Arabic notation for numbers of which it is an essential part. For in that notation the \PageSep{64} value of a digit depends on the position in which it occurs. Consider, for example, the digit~$5$, as occurring in the numbers $25$, $51$, $3512$, $5213$. In the first number~$5$ stands for five, in the second number $5$~stands for fifty, in the third number for five hundred, and in the fourth number for five thousand. Now, when we write the number fifty-one in the symbolic form~$51$, the digit~$1$ pushes the digit~$5$ along to the second place (reckoning from right to left) and thus gives it the value fifty. But when we want to symbolize fifty by itself, we can have no digit~$1$ to perform this service; we want a digit in the units place to add nothing to the total and yet to push the~$5$ along to the second place. This service is performed by~$0$, the symbol for zero. It is extremely probable that the men who introduced for this purpose had no definite conception in their minds of the number zero. They simply wanted a mark to symbolize the fact that nothing was contributed by the digit's place in which it occurs. The idea of zero probably took shape gradually from a desire to assimilate the meaning of this mark to that of the marks, $1$, $2$,~\dots\Add{,}~$9$, which do represent cardinal numbers. This would not represent the only case in which a subtle idea has been introduced into mathematics by a symbolism which in its origin was dictated by practical convenience. \PageSep{65} Thus the first use of~$0$ was to make the arable notation possible---no slight service. We can imagine that when it had been introduced for this purpose, practical men, of the sort who dislike fanciful ideas, deprecated the silly habit of identifying it with a number zero. But they were wrong, as such men always are when they desert their proper function of masticating food which others have prepared. For the next service performed by the symbol~$0$ essentially depends upon assigning to it the function of representing the number zero. This second symbolic use is at first sight so absurdly simple that it is difficult to make a beginner realize its importance. Let us start with a simple example. In \ChapRef{II}.\ we mentioned the correlation between two variable numbers $x$ and $y$ represented by the equation $x + y = 1$. This can be represented in an indefinite number of ways; for example, $x = 1 - y$, $y = 1 - x$, $2x + 3y - 1 = x + 2y$, and so on. But the important way of stating it is \[ x + y - 1 = 0. \] Similarly the important way of writing the equation $x = 1$ is $x - 1 = 0$, and of representing the equation $3x - 2 = 2x^{2}$ is $2x^{2} - 3x + 2 = 0$. The point is that all the symbols which represent variables, \eg\ $x$~and~$y$, and the symbols \PageSep{66} representing some definite number other than zero, such as $1$ or $2$ in the examples above, are written on the left-hand side, so that the whole left-hand side is equated to the number zero. The first man to do this is said to have been Thomas Harriot, born at Oxford \index{Harriot, Thomas}% in 1560 and died in~1621. But what is the importance of this simple symbolic procedure? It made possible the growth of the \index{Form, Algebraic|EtSeq}% modern conception of \emph{algebraic form}. This is an idea to which we shall have continually to recur; it is not going too far to say that no part of modern mathematics can be properly understood without constant recurrence to it. The conception of form is so general that it is difficult to characterize it in abstract terms. At this stage we shall do better merely to consider examples. Thus the equations $2x - 3 = 0$, $x - 1 = 0$, $5x - 6 = 0$, are all equations of the same form, namely, equations involving one unknown~$x$, which is not multiplied by itself, so that $x^{2}$, $x^{3}$,~etc., do not appear. Again $3x^{2} - 2x + 1 = 0$, $x^{2} - 3x + 2 = 0$, $x^{2} - 4 = 0$, are all equations of the same form, namely, equations involving one unknown~$x$ in which $x × x$, that is~$x^{2}$, appears. These equations are called quadratic equations. Similarly cubic equations, in which $x^{3}$~appears, yield another form, and so on. Among the three quadratic equations given above there is a minor difference between the last equation, \PageSep{67} $x^{2} - 4 = 0$, and the preceding two equations, due to the fact that~$x$ (as distinct from~$x^{2}$) does not appear in the last and does in the other two. This distinction is very unimportant in comparison with the great fact that they are all three quadratic equations. Then further there are the forms of equation stating correlations between two variables; for example, $x + y - 1 = 0$, $2x + 3y - 8 = 0$, and so on. These are examples of what is called the \emph{linear} form of equation. The reason for this name of ``linear'' is that the graphic method of representation, which is explained at the end of \ChapRef{II}\Add{.}, always represents such equations by a straight line. Then there are other forms for two variables---for example, the quadratic form, the cubic form, and so on. But the point which we here insist upon is that this study of form is facilitated, and, indeed, made possible, by the standard method of writing equations with the symbol~$0$ on the right-hand side. There is yet another function performed by~$0$ in relation to the study of form. Whatever number $x$ may be, $0 × x = 0$, and $x + 0 = x$. By means of these properties minor differences of form can be assimilated. Thus the difference mentioned above between the quadratic equations $x^{2} - 3x + 2 = 0$, and $x^{2} - 4 = 0$, can be obliterated by writing the latter \PageSep{68} equation in the form $x^{2} + (0 × x) - 4 = 0$. For, by the laws stated above, $x^{2} + (0 × x) - 4 = x^{2} + 0 - 4 = x^{2} - 4$. Hence the equation $x^{2} - 4 = 0$\Typo{,}{} is merely representative of a particular class of quadratic equations and belongs to the same general form as does $x^{2} - 3x + 2 = 0$. For these three reasons the symbol~$0$, representing the number zero, is essential to modern mathematics. It has rendered possible types of investigation which would have been impossible without it. The symbolism of mathematics is in truth the outcome of the general ideas which dominate the science. We have now two such general ideas before us, that of the variable and that of algebraic form. The junction of these concepts has imposed on mathematics another type of symbolism almost quaint in its character, but none the less effective. We have seen that an equation involving two variables, $x$~and~$y$, represents a particular correlation between the pair of variables. Thus $x + y - 1 = 0$ represents one definite correlation, and $3x + 2y - 5 = 0$ represents another definite correlation between the variables $x$ and~$y$; and both correlations have the form of what we have called linear correlations. But now, how can we represent \emph{any} linear correlation between the variable numbers $x$ and~$y$? Here we want to symbolize \emph{any} linear correlation; just as $x$~symbolizes \emph{any} \PageSep{69} number. This is done by turning the numbers which occur in the definite correlation $3x + 2y - 5 = 0$ into letters. We obtain $ax + by - c = 0$. Here $a$,~$b$,~$c$, stand for variable numbers just as do $x$ and~$y$: but there is a difference in the use of the two sets of variables. We study the general properties of the relationship between $x$ and $y$ while $a$,~$b$, and~$c$ have unchanged values. We do not determine what the values of $a$,~$b$, and~$c$ are; but whatever they are, they remain fixed while we study the relation between the variables $x$ and $y$ for the whole group of possible values of $x$ and~$y$. But when we have obtained the properties of this correlation, we note that, because $a$,~$b$, and~$c$ have not in fact been determined, we have proved properties which must belong to \emph{any} such relation. Thus, by now varying $a$,~$b$, and~$c$, we arrive at the idea that $ax + by - c = 0$ represents a variable linear correlation between $x$ and~$y$. In comparison with $x$ and~$y$, the three variables $a$,~$b$, and~$c$ are called constants. Variables used in this \index{Constants}% way are sometimes also called parameters. \index{Parameters}% Now, mathematicians habitually save the trouble of explaining which of their variables are to be treated as ``constants,'' and which as variables, considered as correlated in their equations, by using letters at the end of the alphabet for the ``variable'' variables, and letters at the beginning of the alphabet for \PageSep{70} the ``constant'' variables, or parameters. The two systems meet naturally about the middle of the alphabet. Sometimes a word or two of explanation is necessary; but as a matter of fact custom and common sense are usually sufficient, and surprisingly little confusion is caused by a procedure which seems so lax. The result of this continual elimination of definite numbers by successive layers of parameters is that the amount of arithmetic performed by mathematicians is extremely small. Many mathematicians dislike all numerical computation and are not particularly expert at it. The territory of arithmetic ends where the two ideas of ``variables'' and of ``algebraic form'' commence their sway. \PageSep{71} \Chapter{VI}{Generalizations of Number} \First{One} great peculiarity of mathematics is the \index{Fractions|EtSeq}% set of allied ideas which have been invented in connection with the integral numbers from which we started. These ideas may be called extensions or generalizations of number. In the first place there is the idea of fractions. The earliest treatise on arithmetic which we possess was written by an Egyptian priest, named Ahmes, between 1700~\BC\ and 1100~\BC, \index{Ahmes}% and it is probably a copy of a much older work. It deals largely with the properties of fractions. It appears, therefore, that this concept was developed very early in the history of mathematics. Indeed the subject is a very obvious one. To divide a field into three equal parts, and to take two of the parts, must be a type of operation which had often occurred. Accordingly, we need not be surprised that the men of remote civilizations were familiar with the idea of two-thirds, and \PageSep{72} with allied notions. Thus as the first generalization of number we place the concept of fractions. The Greeks thought of this subject rather in the form of ratio, so that a Greek would naturally say that a line of two feet in length bears to a line of three feet in length the ratio of $2$~to~$3$. Under the influence of our algebraic notation we would more often say that one line was two-thirds of the other in length, and would think of two-thirds as a numerical multiplier. In connection with the theory of ratio, or \index{Incommensurable Ratios|EtSeq}% \index{Ratio|EtSeq}% fractions, the Greeks made a great discovery, which has been the occasion of a large amount of philosophical as well as mathematical thought. They found out the existence of ``incommensurable'' ratios. They proved, in fact, during the course of their geometrical investigations that, starting with a line of any length, other lines must exist whose lengths do not bear to the original length the ratio of any pair of integers---or, in other words, that lengths exist which are not any exact fraction of the original length. For example, the diagonal of a square cannot be expressed as any fraction of the side of the same square; in our modern notation the length of the diagonal is $\sqrt{2}$~times the length of the side. But there is no fraction which exactly represents~$\sqrt{2}$. We can approximate \PageSep{73} to~$\sqrt{2}$ as closely as we like, but we never exactly reach its value. For example, $\dfrac{49}{25}$~is just less than~$2$, and $\dfrac{9}{4}$~is greater than~$2$, so that $\sqrt{2}$~lies between $\dfrac{7}{5}$ and~$\dfrac{3}{2}$. But the best systematic way of approximating to~$\sqrt{2}$ in obtaining a series of decimal fractions, each bigger than the last, is by the ordinary method of extracting the square root; thus the series is $1$, $\dfrac{14}{10}$, $\dfrac{141}{100}$, $\dfrac{1414}{1000}$, and so on. Ratios of this sort are called by the Greeks incommensurable. They have excited from the time of the Greeks onwards a great deal of philosophic discussion, and the difficulties connected with them have only recently been cleared up. We will put the incommensurable ratios \index{Real Numbers|EtSeq}% with the fractions, and consider the whole set of integral numbers, fractional numbers, and incommensurable numbers as forming one class of numbers which we will call ``real numbers.'' We always think of the real numbers as arranged in order of magnitude, starting from zero and going upwards, and becoming indefinitely larger and larger as we proceed. The real numbers are conveniently \PageSep{74} represented by points on a line. Let $OX$ be \Diagram{pg76} any line bounded at~$O$ and stretching away indefinitely in the direction~$OX$. Take any convenient point,~$A$, on it, so that $OA$~represents the unit length; and divide off lengths $AB$, $BC$, $CD$, and so on, each equal to~$OA$. Then the point~$O$ represents the number~$0$, $A$~the number~$1$, $B$~the number~$2$, and so on. In fact the number represented by any point is the measure of its distance from~$O$, in terms of the unit length~$OA$. The points between $O$ and~$A$ represent the proper fractions and the incommensurable numbers less than~$1$; the middle point of~$OA$ represents~$\dfrac{1}{2}$, that of~$AB$ represents~$\dfrac{3}{2}$, that of~$BC$ represents~$\dfrac{5}{2}$, and so on. In this way every point on~$OX$ represents some one real number, and every real number is represented by some one point on~$OX$. The series (or row) of points along~$OX$, \index{Series|EtSeq}% starting from~$O$ and moving regularly in the direction from $O$ to~$X$, represents the real numbers as arranged in an ascending order \PageSep{75} of size, starting from zero and continually increasing as we go on. All this seems simple enough, but even at \index{Order, Type of|EtSeq}% this stage there are some interesting ideas to be got at by dwelling on these obvious facts. Consider the series of points which represent the integral numbers only, namely, the points, $O$,~$A$, $B$, $C$, $D$,~etc. Here there is a first point~$O$, a definite next point,~$A$, and each point, such as $A$ or~$B$, has one definite immediate predecessor and one definite immediate successor, with the exception of~$O$, which has no predecessor; also the series goes on indefinitely without end. This sort of order is called the type of order of the integers; its essence is the possession of next-door neighbours on either side with the exception of No.~1 in the row. Again consider the integers and fractions together, omitting the points which correspond to the incommensurable ratios. The sort of serial order which we now obtain is quite different. There is a first term~$O$; but no term has any immediate predecessor or immediate successor. This is easily seen to be the case, for between any two fractions we can always find another fraction intermediate in value. One very simple way of doing this is to add the fractions together and to halve the result. For example, %[** textstyle fractions start here] between $\frac{2}{3}$ and~$\frac{3}{4}$, the fraction $\frac{1}{2}(\frac{2}{3} + \frac{3}{4})$, that is~$\frac{17}{24}$, lies; and between $\frac{2}{3}$ and $\frac{17}{24}$ the \PageSep{76} \index{Compact Series}% fraction $\frac{1}{2}(\frac{2}{3} + \frac{17}{24})$, that is~$\frac{33}{48}$, lies; and so on indefinitely. Because of this property the series is said to be ``compact.'' There is no end point to the series, which increases indefinitely without limit as we go along the line~$OX$. It would seem at first sight as though the type of series got in this way from the fractions, always including the integers, would be the same as that got from all the real numbers, integers, fractions, and incommensurables taken together, that is, from all the points on the line~$OX$. All that we have hitherto said about the series of fractions applies equally well to the series of all real numbers. But there are important differences which we now proceed to develop. The absence of the incommensurables from the series of fractions leaves an absence of endpoints to certain classes. Thus, consider the incommensurable~$\sqrt{2}$. In the series of real numbers this stands between all the numbers whose squares are less than~$2$, and all the numbers whose squares are greater than~$2$. But keeping to the series of fractions alone and not thinking of the incommensurables, so that we cannot bring in~$\sqrt{2}$, there is no fraction which has the property of dividing off the series into two parts in this way, \ie\ so that all the members on one side have their squares less than~$2$, and on the other side greater than~$2$. Hence in the series of fractions \PageSep{77} there is a quasi-gap where $\sqrt{2}$~ought to come. This presence of quasi-gaps in the series of fractions may seem a small matter; but any mathematician, who happens to read this, knows that the possible absence of limits \index{Limits}% or maxima to a class of numbers, which yet does not spread over the whole series of numbers, is no small evil. It is to avoid this difficulty that recourse is had to the incommensurables, so as to obtain a complete series with no gaps. There is another even more fundamental difference between the two series. We can rearrange the fractions in a series like that of the integers, that is, with a first term, and such that each term has an immediate successor and (except the first term) an immediate predecessor. We can show how this can be done. Let every term in the series of fractions and integers be written in the fractional form by writing $\frac{1}{1}$ for~$1$, $\frac{2}{1}$ for~$2$, and so on for all the integers, excluding~$0$. Also for the moment we will reckon fractions which are equal in value but not reduced to their lowest terms as distinct; so that, for example, until further notice $\frac{2}{3}$, $\frac{4}{6}$, $\frac{6}{9}$, $\frac{8}{12}$, etc., are all reckoned as distinct. Now group the fractions into classes by adding together the numerator and denominator of each term. For the sake of brevity call this sum of the numerator and denominator of a fraction its index. Thus $7$~is \PageSep{78} the index of~$\frac{4}{3}$, and also of~$\frac{3}{4}$, and of~$\frac{2}{5}$. Let the fractions in each class be all fractions which have some specified index, which may therefore also be called the class index. Now arrange these classes in the order of magnitude of their indices. The first class has the index~$2$, and its only member is~$\frac{1}{1}$; the second class has the index~$3$, and its members are $\frac{1}{2}$ and~$\frac{2}{1}$; the third class has the index~$4$, and its members are $\frac{1}{3}$, $\frac{2}{2}$,~$\frac{3}{1}$; the fourth class has the index~$5$, and its members are $\frac{1}{4}$, $\frac{2}{3}$, $\frac{3}{2}$,~$\frac{4}{1}$; and so on. It is easy to see that the number of members (still including fractions not in their lowest terms) belonging to any class is one less than its index. Also the members of any one class can be arranged in order by taking the first member to be the fraction with numerator~$1$, the second member to have the numerator~$2$, and so on, up to~$(n - 1)$ where $n$~is the index. Thus for the class of index~$n$, the members appear in the order\Typo{.}{} %[** TN: Reformatted slightly from the original] \[ \frac{1}{n - 1},\quad \frac{2}{n - 2},\quad \frac{3}{n - 3},\ \dots,\quad \frac{n - 1}{1}. \] The members of the first four classes have in fact been mentioned in this order. Thus the whole set of fractions have now been arranged in an order like that of the integers. It runs thus \begin{gather*} \frac{1}{1},\ \frac{1}{2},\ \frac{2}{1},\ \frac{1}{3},\ \left[\frac{2}{2}\right],\ \frac{3}{1},\ \frac{1}{4},\ \frac{2}{3},\ \frac{3}{2},\ \frac{4}{1},\ \dots, \\ %\PageSep{79} \frac{n - 1}{1},\ \frac{1}{n - 1},\ \frac{2}{n - 2},\ \frac{3}{n - 3},\ \dots,\ \frac{n - 1}{1},\ \frac{1}{n}, \end{gather*} and so on. Now we can get rid of all repetitions of fractions of the same value by simply striking them out whenever they appear after their first occurrence. In the few initial terms written down above, $\frac{2}{2}$~which is enclosed above in square brackets is the only fraction not in its lowest terms. It has occurred before as~$\frac{1}{1}$. Thus this must be struck out. But the series is still left with the same properties, namely, (\textit{a})~there is a first term, (\textit{b})~each term has next-door neighbours, (\textit{c})~the series goes on without end. It can be proved that it is not possible to \index{Cantor, Georg}% arrange the whole series of real numbers in this way. This curious fact was discovered by Georg Cantor, a German mathematician still living; it is of the utmost importance in the philosophy of mathematical ideas. We are here in fact touching on the fringe of the great problems of the meaning of continuity and of infinity. Another extension of number comes from \index{Steps|EtSeq}% the introduction of the idea of what has been variously named an operation or a step, names which are respectively appropriate from slightly different points of view. We will start with a particular case. Consider \PageSep{80} the statement $2 + 3 = 5$. We add $3$ to~$2$ and obtain~$5$. Think of the operation of adding~$3$: let this be denoted by~$+3$. Again $4 - 3 = 1$. Think of the operation of subtracting~$3$: let this be denoted by~$-3$. Thus instead of considering the real numbers in themselves, we consider the \emph{operations} of adding or subtracting them: instead of~$\sqrt{2}$, we consider $+\sqrt{2}$ and~$-\sqrt{2}$, namely the operations of adding~$\sqrt{2}$ and of subtracting~$\sqrt{2}$. Then we can add these operations, of course in a different sense of addition to that in which we add numbers. The sum of two operations is the single operation which has the same effect as the two operations applied successively. In what order are the two operations to be applied? The answer is that it is indifferent, since for example \[ 2 + 3 + 1 = 2 + 1 + 3; \] so that the addition of the steps $+3$ and $+1$ is commutative. Mathematicians have a habit, which is puzzling to those engaged in tracing out meanings, but is very convenient in practice, of using the same symbol in different though allied senses. The one essential requisite for a symbol in their eyes is that, whatever its possible varieties of meaning, the formal laws for its use shall always be the same. In \PageSep{81} accordance with this habit the addition of operations is denoted by~$+$ as well as the addition of numbers. Accordingly we can write \[ (+3) + (+1) = +4; \] where the middle~$+$ on the left-hand side denotes the addition of the operations $+3$ and~$+1$. But, furthermore, we need not be so very pedantic in our symbolism, except in the rare instances when we are directly tracing meanings; thus we always drop the first~$+$ of a line and the brackets, and never write two $+$~signs running. So the above equation becomes \[ 3 + 1 = 4, \] which we interpret as simple numerical addition, or as the more elaborate addition of operations which is fully expressed in the previous way of writing the equation, or lastly as expressing the result of applying the operation~$+1$ to the number~$3$ and obtaining the number~$4$. Any interpretation which is possible is always correct. But the only interpretation which is always possible, under certain conditions, is that of operations. The other interpretations often give nonsensical results. This leads us at once to a question, which must have been rising insistently in the \PageSep{82} reader's mind: What is the use of all this elaboration? At this point our friend, the practical man, will surely step in and insist on sweeping away all these silly cobwebs of the brain. The answer is that what the mathematician is seeking is Generality. This is an \index{Generality in Mathematics}% idea worthy to be placed beside the notions of the Variable and of Form so far as concerns \index{Form, Algebraic}% \index{Variable, The}% its importance in governing mathematical procedure. Any limitation whatsoever upon the generality of theorems, or of proofs, or of interpretation is abhorrent to the mathematical instinct. These three notions, of the variable, of form, and of generality, compose a sort of mathematical trinity which preside over the whole subject. They all really spring from the same root, namely from the abstract nature of the science. Let us see how generality is gained by the introduction of this idea of operations. Take the equation $x + 1 = 3$; the solution is $x = 2$. Here we can interpret our symbols as mere numbers, and the recourse to ``operations'' is entirely unnecessary. But, if $x$~is a mere number, the equation $x + 3 = 1$ is nonsense. For $x$~should be the number of things which remain when you have taken $3$~things away from $1$~thing; and no such procedure is possible. At this point our idea of algebraic form steps in, itself only generalization under another aspect. We consider, therefore, the \PageSep{83} \index{Positive and Negative Numbers|EtSeq}% general equation of the same form as $x + 1 = 3$. This equation is $x + a = b$, and its solution is $x = b - a$. Here our difficulties become acute; for this form can only be used for the numerical interpretation so long as $b$~is greater than~$a$, and we cannot say without qualification that $a$ and $b$ may be any constants. In other words we have introduced a limitation on the variability of the ``constants'' $a$~and~$b$, which we must drag like a chain throughout all our reasoning. Really prolonged mathematical investigations would be impossible under such conditions. Every equation would at last be buried under a pile of limitations. But if we now interpret our symbols as ``operations,'' all limitation vanishes like magic. The equation $x + 1 = 3$ gives $x = +2$, the equation $x + 3 = 1$ gives $x = -2$, the equation $x + a = b$ gives $x = b - a$ which is an operation of addition or subtraction as the case may be. We need never decide whether $b - a$ represents the operation of addition or of subtraction, for the rules of procedure with the symbols are the same in either case. It does not fall within the plan of this work to write a detailed chapter of elementary algebra. Our object is merely to make plain the fundamental ideas which guide the formation of the science. Accordingly we do not further explain the detailed rules by which the ``positive and negative numbers'' are \PageSep{84} multiplied and otherwise combined. We have explained above that positive and negative numbers are operations. They have also been called ``steps.'' Thus $+3$~is the step by which we go from $2$ to~$5$, and $-3$~is the step backwards by which we go from $5$ to~$2$. Consider the line~$OX$ divided in the way explained in the earlier part of the chapter, so that its points represent numbers. Then~$+2$ %[** TN: In original, negative numbers placed below axis, primed letters above] \Diagram{pg86} is the step from $O$ to~$B$, or from $A$ to~$C$, or (if the divisions are taken backwards along~$OX'$) from $C'$ to~$A'$, or from $D'$ to~$B'$, and so on. Similarly $-2$ is the step from $O$ to~$B'$, or from $B'$ to~$D'$, or from $B$ to~$O$, or from $C$ to~$A$. We may consider the point which is reached by a step from~$O$, as representative of that step. Thus $A$~represents~$+1$, $B$~represents~$+2$, $A'$~represents~$-1$, $B'$~represents~$-2$, and so on. It will be noted that, whereas previously with the mere ``unsigned'' real numbers the points on one side of~$O$ only, namely along~$OX$, were representative of numbers, now with steps every point on the whole line stretching on both sides of~$O$ is representative of a step. This is a pictorial representation of the superior generality introduced by the positive and negative numbers, namely the \PageSep{85} operations or steps. These ``signed'' numbers are also particular cases of what have been called vectors (from the Latin \Foreign{veho}, I \index{Vectors}% draw or carry). For we may think of a particle as carried from $O$ to~$A$, or from $A$ to~$B$. In suggesting a few pages ago that the practical man would object to the subtlety involved by the introduction of the positive and negative numbers, we were libelling that excellent individual. For in truth we are on the scene of one of his greatest triumphs. If the truth must be confessed, it was the practical man himself who first employed the actual symbols $+$ and~$-$. Their origin is not very certain, but it seems most probable that they arose from the marks chalked on chests of goods in German warehouses, to denote excess or defect from some standard weight. The earliest notice of them occurs in a book published at Leipzig, in \AD~1489. They seem first to have been employed in mathematics by a German mathematician, Stifel, in a book \index{Stifel}% published at Nuremburg in 1544~\AD. But then it is only recently that the Germans have come to be looked on as emphatically a practical nation. There is an old epigram which assigns the empire of the sea to the English, of the land to the French, and of the clouds to the Germans. Surely it was from the clouds that the Germans fetched $+$ and~$-$; \PageSep{86} the ideas which these symbols have generated are much too important for the welfare of humanity to have come from the sea or from the land. The possibilities of application of the positive and negative numbers are very obvious. If lengths in one direction are represented by positive numbers, those in the opposite direction are represented by negative numbers. If a velocity in one direction is positive, that in the opposite direction is negative. If a rotation round a dial in the opposite direction to the hands of a clock (anti-clockwise) is positive, that in the clockwise direction is negative. If a balance at the bank is positive, an overdraft is negative. If vitreous electrification is positive, resinous electrification is negative. Indeed, in this latter case, the terms positive electrification and negative electrification, considered as mere names, have practically driven out the other terms. An endless series of examples could be given. The idea of positive and negative numbers has been practically the most successful of mathematical subtleties. \PageSep{87} \Chapter{VII}{Imaginary Numbers} \First{If} the mathematical ideas dealt with in the \index{Imaginary Numbers|EtSeq}% last chapter have been a popular success, those of the present chapter have excited almost as much general attention. But their success has been of a different character, it has been what the French term a \Foreign{succès de scandale}. Not only the practical man, but also men of letters and philosophers have expressed their bewilderment at the devotion of mathematicians to mysterious entities which by their very name are confessed to be imaginary. At this point it may be useful to observe that a certain type of intellect is always worrying itself and others by discussion as to the applicability of technical terms. Are the incommensurable numbers properly called numbers? Are the positive and negative numbers really numbers? Are the imaginary numbers imaginary, and are they numbers?---are types of such futile questions. Now, it cannot be too clearly understood that, in science, technical terms are names arbitrarily assigned, like Christian \PageSep{88} names to children. There can be no question of the names being right or wrong. They may be judicious or injudicious; for they can sometimes be so arranged as to be easy to remember, or so as to suggest relevant and important ideas. But the essential principle involved was quite clearly enunciated in Wonderland to Alice by Humpty Dumpty, when he told her, à~propos of his use of words, ``I pay them extra and make them mean what I like.'' So we will not bother as to whether imaginary numbers are imaginary, or as to whether they are numbers, but will take the phrase as the arbitrary name of a certain mathematical idea, which we will now endeavour to make plain. The origin of the conception is in every way similar to that of the positive and negative numbers. In exactly the same way it is due to the three great mathematical ideas of the variable, of algebraic form, and of generalization. The positive and negative numbers arose from the consideration of equations like $x + 1 = 3$, $x + 3 = 1$, and the general form $x + a = b$. Similarly the origin of imaginary numbers is due to equations like $x^{2} + 1 = 3$, $x^{2} + 3 = 1$, and $x^{2} + a = b$. Exactly the same process is gone through. The equation $x^{2} + 1 = 3$ becomes $x^{2} = 2$, and this has two solutions, either $x = +\sqrt{2}$, or $x = -\sqrt{2}$. The statement that there are these alternative \PageSep{89} solutions is usually written $x = ±\sqrt{2}$. So far all is plain sailing, as it was in the previous case. But now an analogous difficulty arises. For the equation $x^{2} + 3 = 1$ gives $x^{2} = -2$ and there is no positive or negative number which, when multiplied by itself, will give a negative square. Hence, if our symbols are to mean the ordinary positive or negative numbers, there is no solution to $x^{2} = -2$, and the equation is in fact nonsense. Thus, finally taking the general form $x^{2} + a = b$, we find the pair of solutions $x = ±\sqrt{(b - a)}$, when, and only when, $b$~is not less than~$a$. Accordingly we cannot say unrestrictedly that the ``constants'' $a$~and~$b$ may be any numbers, that is, the ``constants'' $a$~and~$b$ are not, as they ought to be, independent unrestricted ``variables''; and so again a host of limitations and restrictions will accumulate round our work as we proceed. The same task as before therefore awaits us: we must give a new interpretation to our symbols, so that the solutions $±\sqrt{(b - a)}$ for the equation $x^{2} + a = b$ always have meaning. In other words, we require an interpretation of the symbols so that $\sqrt{a}$~always has meaning whether $a$~be positive or negative. Of course, the interpretation must be such that all the ordinary formal laws for addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division hold good; and also it must not interfere with the \PageSep{90} generality which we have attained by the use of the positive and negative numbers. In fact, it must in a sense include them as special cases. When $a$~is negative we may write $-c^{2}$ for it, so that $c^{2}$~is positive. Then \begin{align*} \sqrt{a} &= \sqrt{(-c^{2})} = \sqrt{\{(-1) × c^{2}\}} \\ &= \sqrt{(-1)} \sqrt{c^{2}} = c\sqrt{(-1)}. \end{align*} Hence, if we can so interpret our symbols that $\sqrt{(-1)}$~has a meaning, we have attained our object. Thus $\sqrt{(-1)}$~has come to be looked on as the head and forefront of all the imaginary quantities. This business of finding an interpretation for~$\sqrt{(-1)}$ is a much tougher job than the analogous one of interpreting~$-1$. In fact, while the easier problem was solved almost instinctively as soon as it arose, it at first hardly occurred, even to the greatest mathematicians, that here a problem existed which was perhaps capable of solution. Equations like $x^{2} = -3$, when they arose, were simply ruled aside as nonsense. However, it came to be gradually perceived during the eighteenth century, and even earlier, how very convenient it would be if an interpretation could be assigned to these nonsensical symbols. Formal reasoning with these symbols was gone through, merely assuming that they obeyed the ordinary \PageSep{91} algebraic laws of transformation; and it was seen that a whole world of interesting results could be attained, if only these symbols might legitimately be used. Many mathematicians were not then very clear as to the logic of their procedure, and an idea gained ground that, in some mysterious way, symbols which mean nothing can by appropriate manipulation yield valid proofs of propositions. Nothing can be more mistaken. A symbol which has not been properly defined is not a symbol at all. It is merely a blot of ink on paper which has an easily recognized shape. Nothing can be proved by a succession of blots, except the existence of a bad pen or a careless writer. It was during this epoch that the epithet ``imaginary'' came to be applied to~$\sqrt{(-1)}$. What these mathematicians had really succeeded in proving were a series of hypothetical propositions, of which this is the blank form: If interpretations exist for $\sqrt{(-1)}$ and for the addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division of~$\sqrt{(-1)}$ which make the ordinary algebraic rules (\eg\ $x + y = y + x$, etc.)\ to be satisfied, then such and such results follows. It was natural that the mathematicians should not always appreciate the big ``If,'' which ought to have preceded the statements of their results. As may be expected the interpretation, \PageSep{92} when found, was a much more elaborate affair than that of the negative numbers and the reader's attention must be asked for some careful preliminary explanation. We have already come across the representation of a point by two numbers. By the aid of the \Figure{8} positive and negative numbers we can now represent the position of any point in a plane by a pair of such numbers. Thus we take the pair of straight lines $XOX'$ and $YOY'$, at right angles, as the ``axes'' from which we start all our measurements. Lengths measured along $OX$ and $OY$ are positive, and measured backwards along $OX'$ and $OY'$ are negative. Suppose that a pair of numbers, written in order, \eg~$(+3, +1)$, so that there \PageSep{93} \index{Ordered Couples|EtSeq}% is a first number ($+3$~in the above example), and a second number ($+1$~in the above example), represents measurements from~$O$ along $XOX'$ for the first number, and along $YOY'$ for the second number. Thus (\Chg{cf.}{\cf}\ \Fig[fig.]{9}) in $(+3, +1)$ a length of $3$~units is to be measured along $XOX'$ in the positive direction, that is from~$O$ towards~$X$, and a length~$+1$ measured along $YOY'$ in the positive direction, that is from~$O$ towards~$Y$. Similarly in $(-3, +1)$ the length of $3$~units is to be measured from~$O$ towards~$X'$, and of $1$~unit from towards~$Y$. Also in $(-3, -1)$ the two lengths are to be measured along $OX'$ and $OY'$ respectively, and in $(+3, -1)$ along $OX$ and $OY'$ respectively. Let us for the moment call such a pair of numbers an ``ordered couple.'' Then, from the two numbers $1$~and~$3$, eight ordered couples can be generated, namely \begin{gather*} (+1, +3),\ (-1, +3),\ (-1, -3),\ (+1, -3), \\ (+3, +1),\ (-3, +1),\ (-3, -1),\ (+3, -1). \end{gather*} Each of these eight ``ordered couples'' directs a process of measurement along $XOX'$ and $YOY'$ which is different from that directed by any of the others. The processes of measurement represented by the last four ordered couples, mentioned above, are given pictorially in the figure. The lengths $OM$ and $ON$ together correspond \PageSep{94} to $(+3, +1)$, the lengths $OM'$ and $ON$ together correspond to $(-3, +1)$, $OM'$~and $ON'$ together to $(-3, -1)$, and $OM$~and $ON'$ together to $(+3, -1)$. But by completing the various rectangles, it is easy to see that the point~$P$ completely determines and is determined by the ordered couple \Figure{9} $(+3, +1)$, the point~$P'$ by $(-3, +1)$, the point~$P''$ by $(-3, -1)$, and the point~$P'''$ by $(+3, -1)$. More generally in the previous figure~(\FigNum{8}), the point~$P$ corresponds to the ordered couple~$(x, y)$, where $x$~and~$y$ in the figure are both assumed to be positive, the point~$P'$ corresponds to $(x', y)$, where $x'$~in the figure is assumed to be negative, $P''$~to $(x' y')$, and $P'''$~to $(x, y')$. Thus an ordered \PageSep{95} couple $(x, y)$, where $x$~and~$y$ are any positive or negative numbers, and the corresponding point reciprocally determine each other. It is convenient to introduce some names at this juncture. In the ordered couple $(x, y)$ the first number~$x$ is called the ``abscissa'' of the \index{Abscissa}% corresponding point, and the second number~$y$ is called the ``ordinate'' of the point, and \index{Ordinate}% the two numbers together are called the ``coordinates'' \index{Coordinates}% of the point. The idea of determining the position of a point by its ``coordinates'' was by no means new when the theory of ``imaginaries'' was being formed. It was due to Descartes, the great French \index{Descartes}% mathematician and philosopher, and appears in his \Title{Discours} published at Leyden in 1637~\AD. The idea of the ordered couple as a thing on its own account is of later growth and is the outcome of the efforts to interpret imaginaries in the most abstract way possible. It may be noticed as a further illustration of this idea of the ordered couple, that the point~$M$ in \Fig[fig.]{9} is the couple $(+3, 0)$, the point~$N$ is the couple $(0, +1)$, the point~$M'$ the couple $(-3, 0)$, the point~$N'$ the couple $(0, -1)$, the point~$O$ the couple~$(0, 0)$. Another way of representing the ordered couple $(x, y)$ is to think of it as representing the dotted line~$OP$ (\Chg{cf.}{\cf}\ \Fig[fig.]{8}), rather than the point~$P$. Thus the ordered couple represents a line drawn from an ``origin,''~$O$, of a certain \index{Origin}% \PageSep{96} \index{Steps}% length and in a certain direction. The line~$OP$ may be called the vector line from $O$ to~$P$, or the step from $O$ to~$P$. We see, therefore, that we have in this chapter only extended the interpretation which we gave formerly of the positive and negative numbers. This method of representation by vectors is very \index{Vectors}% useful when we consider the meaning to be assigned to the operations of the addition and multiplication of ordered couples. {\Loosen We will now go on to this question, and ask what meaning we shall find it convenient to assign to the addition of the two ordered couples $(x, y)$ and $(x', y')$. The interpretation must, (\textit{a})~make the result of addition to be another ordered couple, (\textit{b})~make the operation commutative so that $(x, y) + (x', y') = (x', y') + (x, y)$, (\textit{c})~make the operation associative so that} \[ \{(x, y) + (x', y')\} + (u, v) = (x, y) + \{(x', y') + (u, v)\}, \] (\textit{d})~make the result of subtraction unique, so that when we seek to determine the unknown ordered couple $(x, y)$ so as to satisfy the equation \[ (x, y) + (a, b) = (c, d), \] there is one and only one answer which we can represent by \[ (x, y) = (c, d) - (a, b). \] \PageSep{97} All these requisites are satisfied by taking $(x, y) + (x', y')$ to mean the ordered couple $(x + x', y + y')$. Accordingly by definition we put \[ (x, y) + (x', y') = (x + x', y + y'). \] Notice that here we have adopted the mathematical habit of using the same symbol~$+$ in different senses. The $+$ on the left-hand side of the equation has the new meaning of~$+$ which we are just defining; while the two~$+$'s on the right-hand side have the meaning of the addition of positive and negative numbers (operations) which was defined in the last chapter. No practical confusion arises from this double use. As examples of addition we have \begin{align*} (+3, +1) + (+2, +6) &= (+5, +7), \\ (+3, -1) + (-2, -6) &= (+1, -7), \\ (+3, +1) + (-3, -1) &= (0, 0). \end{align*} The meaning of subtraction is now settled for us. We find that \[ (x, y) - (u, v) = (x - u, y - v). \] Thus \[ (+3, +2) - (+1, +1) = (+2, +1), \] and \[ (+1, -2) - (+2, -4) = (-1, +2), \] and \[ (-1, -2) - (+2, +3) = (-3, -5). \] \PageSep{98} It is easy to see that \[ (x, y) - (u, v) = (x, y) + (-u, -v). \] Also \[ (x, y) - (x, y) = (0, 0). \] Hence $(0, 0)$~is to be looked on as the zero ordered couple. For example \[ (x, y) + (0, 0) = (x, y). \] The pictorial representation of the addition of ordered couples is surprisingly easy. \Figure{10} {\Loosen Let $OP$ represent $(x, y)$ so that $OM = x$ and $PM = y$; let $OQ$ represent $(x_{1}, y_{1})$ so that $OM_{1} = x_{1}$ and $QM_{1} = y_{1}$. Complete the parallelogram $OPRQ$ by the dotted lines $PR$ and~$QR$, then the diagonal~$OR$ is the ordered couple $(x + x_{1}, y + y_{1})$. For draw $PS$ parallel \PageSep{99} to~$OX$; then evidently the triangles $OQM_{1}$ and $PRS$ are in all respects equal. Hence $MM' = PS = x_{1}$, and $RS = QM_{1}$ and therefore} \begin{gather*} OM' = OM + MM' = x + x_{1}, \\ RM' = SM' + RS = y + y_{1}. \end{gather*} Thus $OR$~represents the ordered couple as required. This figure can also be drawn with $OP$ and $OQ$ in other quadrants. It is at once obvious that we have here come back to the parallelogram law, which \index{Parallelogram Law}% was mentioned in \ChapRef{VI}., on the laws of motion, as applying to velocities and forces. It will be remembered that, if $OP$ and $OQ$ represent two velocities, a particle is said to be moving with a velocity equal to the two velocities added together if it be moving with the velocity~$OR$. In other words $OR$~is said to be the resultant of the two velocities $OP$ and~$OQ$. Again forces acting at a point of a body can be represented by lines just as velocities can be; and the same parallelogram law holds, namely, that the resultant of the two forces $OP$ and $OQ$ is the force represented by the diagonal~$OR$. It follows that we can look on an ordered couple as representing a velocity or a force, and the rule which we have just given for the addition of ordered couples then represents the fundamental laws of mechanics for the addition of forces and \PageSep{100} velocities. One of the most fascinating characteristics of mathematics is the surprising way in which the ideas and results of different parts of the subject dovetail into each other. During the discussions of this and the previous chapter we have been guided merely by the most abstract of pure mathematical considerations; and yet at the end of them we have been led back to the most fundamental of all the laws of nature, laws which have to be in the mind of every engineer as he designs an engine, and of every naval architect as he calculates the stability of a ship. It is no paradox to say that in our most theoretical moods we may be nearest to our most practical applications. \PageSep{101} \Chapter[Imaginary Numbers] {VIII}{Imaginary Numbers (\textit{C\MakeLowercase{ontinued}})} \First{The} definition of the multiplication of ordered couples is guided by exactly the same considerations as is that of their addition. The interpretation of multiplication must be such that \Eq{(\alpha)} the result is another ordered couple, \Eq{(\beta)} the operation is commutative, so that \[ (x, y) × (x', y') = (x', y') × (x, y), \] \Eq{(\gamma)} the operation is associative, so that \[ \{(x, y) × (x', y')\} × (u, v) = (x, y) × \{(x', y') × (u, v)\}, \] \Eq{(\delta)} must make the result of division unique [with an exception for the case of the zero couple $(0, 0)$], so that when we seek to determine the unknown couple $(x, y)$ so as to satisfy the equation \[ (x, y) × (a, b) = (c, d), \] there is one and only one answer, which we can represent by \[ (x, y) = (c, d) ÷ (a, b),\quad\text{or by}\quad (x, y) = \frac{(c, d)}{(a, b)}\Add{.} \] \PageSep{102} \Eq{(\epsilon)} Furthermore the law involving both addition and multiplication, called the distributive law, must be satisfied, namely \begin{multline*} (x,y) × \{(a, b) + (c, d)\} \\ = \{(x, y) × (a, b)\} + \{(x, y) × (c, d)\}. \end{multline*} All these conditions \Eq{(\alpha)}, \Eq{(\beta)}, \Eq{(\gamma)}, \Eq{(\delta)}, \Eq{(\epsilon)} can be satisfied by an interpretation which, though it looks complicated at first, is capable of a simple geometrical interpretation. By definition we put \[ (x, y) × (x', y') = \{(xx' - yy'), (xy' + x'y)\}\Add{.} \Tag{(A)} \] This is the definition of the meaning of the symbol~$×$ when it is written between two ordered couples. It follows evidently from this definition that the result of multiplication is another ordered couple, and that the value of the right-hand side of equation~\Eq{(A)} is not altered by simultaneously interchanging $x$~with~$x'$, and $y$~with~$y'$. Hence conditions \Eq{(\alpha)} and \Eq{(\beta)} are evidently satisfied. The proof of the satisfaction of \Eq{(\gamma)}, \Eq{(\delta)}, \Eq{(\epsilon)} is equally easy when we have given the geometrical interpretation, which we will proceed to do in a moment. But before doing this it will be interesting to pause and see whether we have attained the object for which all this elaboration was initiated. We came across equations of the form $x^{2} = -3$, to which no solutions could be \PageSep{103} assigned in terms of positive and negative real numbers. We then found that all our difficulties would vanish if we could interpret the equation $x^{2} = -1$, \ie, if we could so define $\sqrt{(-1)}$ that $\sqrt{(-1)} × \sqrt{(-1)} = -1$. Now let us consider the three special \index{Zero}% ordered couples\footnote {For the future we follow the custom of omitting the $+$~sign wherever possible, thus $(1, 0)$ stands for $(+1, 0)$ and $(0, 1)$ for $(0, +1)$.} $(0, 0)$, $(1, 0)$, and $(0, 1)$. We have already proved that \[ (x, y) + (0, 0) = (x, y). \] Furthermore we now have \[ (x, y) × (0, 0) = (0, 0). \] Hence both for addition and for multiplication the couple $(0, 0)$ plays the part of zero in elementary arithmetic and algebra; compare the above equations with $x + 0 = x$, and $x × 0 = 0$. Again consider $(1, 0)$: this plays the part of~$1$ in elementary arithmetic and algebra. In these elementary sciences the special characteristic of~$1$ is that $x × 1 = x$, for all values of~$x$. Now by our law of multiplication \[ (x, y) × (1, 0) = \{(x - 0), (y + 0)\} = (x, y). \] Thus $(1, 0)$ is the unit couple. \PageSep{104} Finally consider $(0, 1)$: this will interpret for us the symbol~$\sqrt{(-1)}$. The symbol must therefore possess the characteristic property that $\sqrt{(-1)} × \sqrt{(-1)} = -1$. Now by the law of multiplication for ordered couples \[ (0, 1) × (0, 1) = \{(0 - 1), (0 + 0)\} = (-1, 0). \] But $(1, 0)$ is the unit couple, and $(-1, 0)$ is the negative unit couple; so that $(0, 1)$ has the desired property. There are, however, two roots of~$-1$ to be provided for, namely $±\sqrt{(-1)}$. Consider $(0, -1)$; here again remembering that $(-1)^{2} = 1$, we find, $(0, -1) × (0, -1) = (-1, 0)$. Thus $(0, -1)$ is the other square root of~$\Typo{\sqrt{(-1)}}{-1}$. Accordingly the ordered couples $(0, 1)$ and $(0, -1)$ are the interpretations of $±\sqrt{(-1)}$ in terms of ordered couples. But which corresponds to which? Does $(0, 1)$ correspond to $+\sqrt{(-1)}$ and $(0, -1)$ to~$-\sqrt{(-1)}$, or $(0, 1)$ to~$-\sqrt{(-1)}$, and $(0, -1)$ to~$+\sqrt{(-1)}$? The answer is that it is perfectly indifferent which symbolism we adopt. The ordered couples can be divided into three types, (i)~the ``complex imaginary'' type~$(x, y)$, in which neither $x$ nor~$y$ is zero; (ii)~the ``real'' type~$(x, 0)$; (iii)~the ``pure imaginary'' type~$(0, y)$. Let us consider the relations of these types to each other. First multiply together the ``complex imaginary'' \PageSep{105} couple $(x, y)$ and the ``real'' couple $(a, 0)$, we find \[ (a, 0) × (x, y) = (ax, ay). \] Thus the effect is merely to multiply each term of the couple $(x, y)$ by the positive or negative real number~$a$. Secondly, multiply together the ``complex imaginary'' couple $(x, y)$ and the ``pure imaginary'' couple $(0, b)$, we find \[ (0, b) × (x, y) = (-by, bx). \] Here the effect is more complicated, and is best comprehended in the geometrical interpretation to which we proceed after noting three yet more special cases. Thirdly, we multiply the ``real'' couple $(a, 0)$ by the imaginary $(0, b)$ and obtain \[ (a, 0) × (0, b) =(0, ab). \] Fourthly, we multiply the two ``real'' couples $(a, 0)$ and $(a', 0)$ and obtain \[ (a, 0) × (a', 0) =( aa', 0). \] Fifthly, we multiply the two ``imaginary couples'' $(0, b)$ and $(0, \Typo{b}{b'})$ and obtain \[ (0, b) × (0, b') = (-bb', 0). \] We now turn to the geometrical interpretation, beginning first with some special cases. \PageSep{106} Take the couples $(1, 3)$ and $(2, 0)$ and consider the equation \[ (2, 0) × (1, 3) = (2, 6)\Add{.} \] \Figure{11} In the diagram (\Fig[fig.]{11}) the vector~$OP$ represents~$(1, 3)$, and the vector~$ON$ represents~$(2, 0)$, and the vector~$OQ$ represents~$(2, 6)$. Thus the product $(2, 0) × (1, 3)$ is found geometrically by taking the length of the vector~$OQ$ to be the product of the lengths of the vectors $OP$ and~$ON$, and (in this case) by producing $OP$ to~$Q$ to be of the required length. Again, consider the product $(0, 2) × (1, 3)$, we have \[ (0, 2) × (1, 3) = (-6, 2)\Add{.} \] The vector~$ON_{1}$, corresponds to~$(0, 2)$ and the vector~$OR$ to~$(-6,2)$. Thus $OR$ which \PageSep{107} represents the new product is at right angles to~$OQ$ and of the same length. Notice that we have the same law regulating the length of~$OQ$ as in the previous case, namely, that its length is the product of the lengths of the two vectors which are multiplied together; but now that we have $ON_{1}$ along the ``ordinate'' axis~$OY$, instead of $ON$ along the ``abscissa'' axis~$OX$, the direction of~$OP$ has been turned through a right-angle. Hitherto in these examples of multiplication we have looked on the vector~$OP$ as modified by the vectors $ON$ and~$ON_{1}$. We shall get a clue to the general law for the direction by inverting the way of thought, and by thinking of the vectors $ON$ and~$ON_{1}$ as modified by the vector~$OP$. The law for the length remains unaffected; the resultant length is the length of the product of the two vectors. The new direction for the enlarged~$ON$ (\ie~$OQ$) is found by rotating it in the (anti-clockwise) direction of rotation from $OX$ towards~$OY$ through an angle equal to the angle~$XOP$: it is an accident of this particular case that this rotation makes $OQ$ lie along the line~$OP$. Again consider the product of $ON_{1}$ and~$OP$; the new direction for the enlarged~$ON_{1}$ (\ie~$OR$) is found by rotating~$ON$ in the anti-clockwise direction of rotation through an angle equal to the angle~$XOP$, namely, the angle~$N_{1}OR$ is equal to the angle~$XOP$. \PageSep{108} The general rule for the geometrical representation of multiplication can now be enunciated thus: \Figure[3in]{12} The product of the two vectors $OP$ and~$OQ$ is a vector~$OR$, whose length is the product of the lengths of $OP$ and~$OQ$ and whose direction~$OR$ is such that the angle~$XOR$ is equal to the sum of the angles $XOP$ and~$XOQ$. Hence we can conceive the vector~$OP$ as making the vector~$OQ$ rotate through an angle~$XOP$ (\ie\ $\text{the angle } QOR = \text{the angle } XOP$), or the vector~$OQ$ as making the vector~$OP$ rotate through the angle~$XOQ$ (\ie $\text{the angle } POR = \text{the angle } XOQ$). We do not prove this general law, as we \PageSep{109} should thereby be led into more technical processes of mathematics than falls within the design of this book. But now we can immediately see that the associative law [numbered~\Eq{(\gamma)} above] for multiplication is satisfied. Consider first the length of the resultant vector; this is got by the ordinary process of multiplication for real numbers; and thus the associative law holds for it. Again, the direction of the resultant vector is got by the mere addition of angles, and the associative law holds for this process also. So much for multiplication. We have now rapidly indicated, by considering addition and multiplication, how an algebra or ``calculus'' of vectors in one plane can be constructed, which is such that any two vectors in the plane can be added, or subtracted, and can be multiplied, or divided one by the other. We have not considered the technical details of all these processes because it would lead us too far into mathematical details; but we have shown the general mode of procedure. When we are interpreting our algebraic symbols in this way, we are said to be employing ``imaginary quantities'' or ``complex \index{Complex Quantities}% \index{Imaginary Quantities}% quantities.'' These terms are mere details, and we have far too much to think about to stop to enquire whether they are or are not very happily chosen. %[** TN: [sic] "nett", variant spelling] The nett result of our investigations is that \PageSep{110} any equations like $x + 3 = 2$ or $(x + 3)^{2} = -2$ can now always be interpreted into terms of vectors, and solutions found for them. In seeking for such interpretations it is well to note that $3$~becomes $(3, 0)$, and $-2$~becomes $(-2, 0)$, and $x$~becomes the ``unknown'' couple $(u, v)$: so the two equations become respectively $(u, v) + (3, 0) = (2, 0)$, and $\{(u, v) + (3, 0)\}^{2} = (-2, 0)$. We have now completely solved the initial difficulties which caught our eye as soon as we considered even the elements of algebra. The science as it emerges from the solution is much more complex in ideas than that with which we started. We have, in fact, created a new and entirely different science, which will serve all the purposes for which the old science was invented and many more in addition. But, before we can congratulate ourselves on this result to our labours, we must allay a suspicion which ought by this time to have arisen in the mind of the student. The question which the reader ought to be asking himself is: Where is all this invention of new interpretations going to end? It is true that we have succeeded in interpreting algebra so as always to be able to solve a quadratic equation like $x^{2} - 2x + 4 = 0$; but there are an endless number of other equations, for example, $x^{3} - 2x + 4 = 0$, $x^{4} + x^{3} + 2 = 0$, and so on without limit. Have we got to make a \PageSep{111} new science whenever a new equation appears? Now, if this were the case, the whole of our preceding investigations, though to some minds they might be amusing, would in truth be of very trifling importance. But the great fact, which has made modern analysis possible, is that, by the aid of this calculus of vectors, every formula which arises can receive its proper interpretation; and the ``unknown'' quantity in every equation can be shown to indicate some vector. Thus the science is now complete in itself as far as its fundamental ideas are concerned. It was receiving its final form about the same time as when the steam engine was being perfected, and will remain a great and powerful weapon for the achievement of the victory of thought over things when curious specimens of that machine repose in museums in company with the helmets and breastplates of a slightly earlier epoch. \PageSep{112} \Chapter{IX}{Coordinate Geometry} \First{The} methods and ideas of coordinate geometry \index{Coordinate Geometry|EtSeq}% have already been employed in the previous chapters. It is now time for us to consider them more closely for their own sake; and in doing so we shall strengthen our hold on other ideas to which we have attained. In the present and succeeding chapters we will go back to the idea of the positive and negative real numbers and will ignore the imaginaries which were introduced in the last two chapters. We have been perpetually using the idea that, by taking two axes, $XOX'$ and~$YOY'$, in a plane, any point~$P$ in that plane can be determined in position by a pair of positive or negative numbers $x$ and~$y$, where (\Chg{cf.}{\cf}\ \Fig[fig.]{13}) $x$~is the length~$OM$ and $y$~is the length~$PM$. This conception, simple as it looks, is the main idea of the great subject of coordinate geometry. Its discovery marks a momentous epoch in the history of mathematical thought. It is due (as has been \PageSep{113} already said) to the philosopher Descartes, \index{Descartes}% and occurred to him as an important mathematical method one morning as he lay in bed. Philosophers, when they have possessed a thorough knowledge of mathematics, have been among those who have enriched the \Figure{13} science with some of its best ideas. On the other hand it must be said that, with hardly an exception, all the remarks on mathematics made by those philosophers who have possessed but a slight or hasty and late-acquired knowledge of it are entirely worthless, being either trivial or wrong. The fact is a curious one; since the ultimate ideas of mathematics \PageSep{114} seem, after all, to be very simple, almost childishly so, and to lie well within the province of philosophical thought. Probably their very simplicity is the cause of error; we are not used to think about such simple abstract things, and a long training is necessary to secure even a partial immunity from error as soon as we diverge from the beaten track of thought. The discovery of coordinate geometry, and also that of projective geometry about the same time, illustrate another fact which is being continually verified in the history of knowledge, namely, that some of the greatest discoveries are to be made among the most well-known topics. By the time that the seventeenth century had arrived, geometry had already been studied for over two thousand years, even if we date its rise with the Greeks. Euclid, taught in the University of Alexandria, \index{Euclid}% being born about 330~\BC; and he only systematized and extended the work of a long series of predecessors, some of them men of genius. After him generation after generation of mathematicians laboured at the improvement of the subject. Nor did the subject suffer from that fatal bar to progress, namely, that its study was confined to a narrow group of men of similar origin and outlook---quite the contrary was the case; by the seventeenth century it had passed \PageSep{115} through the minds of Egyptians and Greeks, of Arabs and of Germans. And yet, after all this labour devoted to it through so many ages by such diverse minds its most important secrets were yet to be discovered. No one can have studied even the elements of elementary geometry without feeling the lack of some guiding method. Every proposition has to be proved by a fresh display of ingenuity; and a science for which this is true lacks the great requisite of scientific thought, namely, method. Now the especial point of coordinate geometry is that for the first time it introduced method. The remote deductions of a mathematical science are not of primary theoretical importance. The science has not been perfected, until it consists in essence of the exhibition of great allied methods by which information, on any desired topic which falls within its scope, can easily be obtained. The growth of a science is not primarily in bulk, but in ideas; and the more the ideas grow, the fewer are the deductions which it is worth while to write down. Unfortunately, mathematics is always encumbered by the repetition in text-books of numberless subsidiary propositions, whose importance has been lost by their absorption into the role of particular cases of more general truths---and, as we have already insisted, generality is the soul of mathematics. \PageSep{116} Again, coordinate geometry illustrates another feature of mathematics which has already been pointed out, namely, that mathematical sciences as they develop dovetail into each other, and share the same ideas in common. It is not too much to say that the various branches of mathematics undergo a perpetual process of generalization, and that as they become generalized, they coalesce. Here again the reason springs from the very nature of the science, its generality, that is to say, from the fact that the science deals with the general truths which apply to all things in virtue of their very existence as things. In this connection the interest of coordinate geometry lies in the fact that it relates together geometry, which started as the science of space, and algebra, which has its origin in the science of number. Let us now recall the main ideas of the two sciences, and then see how they are related by Descartes' method of coordinates. Take \index{Descartes}% algebra in the first place. We will not trouble ourselves about the imaginaries and will think merely of the real numbers with positive or negative signs. The fundamental idea is that of any number, the variable number, which is denoted by a letter and not by any definite numeral. We then proceed to the consideration of correlations between variables. For example, if $x$ and~$y$ are two variables, \PageSep{117} we may conceive them as correlated by the equations $x + y = 1$, or by $x - y = 1$, or in any one of an indefinite number of other ways. This at once leads to the application of the \index{Form, Algebraic}% idea of algebraic form. We think, in fact, of any correlation of some interesting type, thus rising from the initial conception of variable numbers to the secondary conception of variable correlations of numbers. Thus we generalize the correlation $x + y = 1$, into the correlation $ax + by = c$. Here $a$~and $b$ and~$c$, being letters, stand for any numbers and are in fact themselves variables. But they are the variables which determine the variable correlation; and the correlation, when determined, correlates the variable numbers $x$ and~$y$. Variables, like $a$,~$b$, and~$c$ above, which are used to determine the correlation are called ``constants,'' or parameters. The use \index{Constants}% \index{Parameters}% of the term ``constant'' in this connection for what is really a variable may seem at first sight to be odd; but it is really very natural. For the mathematical investigation is concerned with the relation between the variables $x$ and~$y$, after $a$,~$b$,~$c$ are supposed to have been determined. So in a sense, relatively to $x$ and~$y$, the ``constants'' $a$,~$b$, and~$c$ are constants. Thus $ax + by = c$ stands for the general example of a certain algebraic form, that is, for a variable correlation belonging to a certain class. \PageSep{118} Again we generalize $x^{2} + y^{2} = 1$ into $ax^{2} + by^{2} = c$, or still further into $ax^{2} + 2hxy + by^{2} = c$, or, still further, into $ax^{2} + 2hxy + by^{2} + 2gx + 2fy = c$. Here again we are led to variable correlations which are indicated by their various algebraic forms. Now let us turn to geometry. The name of the science at once recalls to our minds the thought of figures and diagrams exhibiting triangles and rectangles and squares and circles, all in special relations to each other. The study of the simple properties of these figures is the subject matter of elementary geometry, as it is rightly presented to the beginner. Yet a moment's thought will show that this is not the true conception of the subject. It may be right for a child to commence his geometrical reasoning on shapes, like triangles and squares, which he has cut out with scissors. What, however, is a triangle? It is a figure marked out and bounded by three bits of three straight lines. Now the boundary of spaces by bits of lines is a very complicated idea, and not at all one which gives any hope of exhibiting the simple general conceptions which should form the bones of the subject. We want something more simple and more general. It is this obsession with the wrong initial ideas---very natural and good ideas for the creation \PageSep{119} of first thoughts on the subject---which was the cause of the comparative sterility of the study of the science during so many centuries. Coordinate geometry, and Descartes its inventor, must have the credit of disclosing the true simple objects for geometrical thought. In the place of a bit of a straight line, let us think of the whole of a straight line throughout its unending length in both directions. This is the sort of general idea from which to start our geometrical investigations. The Greeks never seem to have found any use for this conception which is now fundamental in all modern geometrical thought. Euclid always contemplates a straight line as drawn between two definite points, and is very careful to mention when it is to be produced beyond this segment. He never thinks of the line as an entity given once for all as a whole. This careful definition and limitation, so as to exclude an infinity not immediately apparent to the senses, was very characteristic of the Greeks in all their many activities. It is enshrined in the difference between Greek architecture and Gothic architecture, and between the Greek religion and the modern religion. The spire on a Gothic cathedral and the importance of the unbounded straight line in modern geometry are both emblematic of the transformation of the modern world. \PageSep{120} The straight line, considered as a whole, is accordingly the root idea from which modern geometry starts. But then other sorts of lines occur to us, and we arrive at the conception of the complete curve which at every point of it exhibits some uniform characteristic, just as the straight line exhibits at all points the characteristic of straightness. For example, there is the circle which \index{Circle}% at all points exhibits the characteristic of being at a given distance from its centre, and again there is the ellipse, which is an oval \index{Ellipse}% curve, such that the sum of the two distances of any point on it from two fixed points, called \index{Focus}% its \emph{foci}, is constant for all points on the curve. It is evident that a circle is merely a particular case of an ellipse when the two foci are superposed in the same point; for then the sum of the two distances is merely twice the radius of the circle. The ancients knew the properties of the ellipse and the circle and, of course, considered them as wholes. For example, Euclid never starts with mere segments (\ie,~bits) of circles, which are then prolonged. He always considers the whole circle as described. It is unfortunate that the circle is not the true fundamental line in geometry, so that his defective consideration of the straight line might have been of less consequence. This general idea of a curve which at any \PageSep{121} \index{Locus|EtSeq}% point of it exhibits some uniform property is expressed in geometry by the term ``locus.'' A locus is the curve (or surface, if we do not confine ourselves to a plane) formed by points, all of which possess some given property. To every property in relation to each other which points can have, there corresponds some locus, which consists of all the points possessing the property. In investigating the properties of a locus considered as a whole, we consider \emph{any} point or points on the locus. Thus in geometry we again meet with the fundamental idea of the variable. Furthermore, in classifying loci under such headings as straight lines, circles, ellipses, etc., we again find the idea of form. Accordingly, as in algebra we are concerned with variable numbers, correlations between variable numbers, and the classification of correlations into types by the idea of algebraic form; so in geometry we are concerned with variable points, variable points satisfying some condition so as form to a locus, and the classification of \emph{loci} into types by the idea of conditions of the same form. Now, the essence of coordinate geometry is the identification of the algebraic correlation with the geometrical locus. The point on a plane is represented in algebra by its two coordinates, $x$~and~$y$, and the condition satisfied by any point on the locus is represented \PageSep{122} by the corresponding correlation between $x$~and~$y$. Finally to correlations expressible in some general algebraic form, such as $ax + by = c$, there correspond loci of some general type, whose geometrical conditions are all of the same form. We have thus arrived at a position where we can effect a complete interchange in ideas and results between the two sciences. Each science throws light on the other, and itself gains immeasurably in power. It is impossible not to feel stirred at the thought of the emotions of men at certain historic moments of adventure and discovery---Columbus \index{Columbus}% when he first saw the Western shore, Pizarro when he stared at the Pacific \index{Pizarro}% Ocean, Franklin when the electric spark came \index{Franklin}% from the string of his kite, Galileo when he \index{Galileo}% first turned his telescope to the heavens. Such moments are also granted to students in the abstract regions of thought, and high among them must be placed the morning when Descartes lay in bed and invented the method \index{Descartes}% of coordinate geometry. When one has once grasped the idea of coordinate geometry, the immediate question which starts to the mind is, What sort of loci correspond to the well-known algebraic forms? For example, the simplest among the general types of algebraic forms is $ax + by = c$. The sort of locus which corresponds \PageSep{123} to this is a straight line, and conversely to every straight line there corresponds an equation of this form. It is fortunate that the simplest among the geometrical loci should correspond to the simplest among the algebraic forms. Indeed, it is this general correspondence of geometrical and algebraic simplicity which gives to the whole subject its power. It springs from the fact that the connection between geometry and algebra is not casual and artificial, but deep-seated and essential. The equation which corresponds to a locus is called the equation ``of'' (or ``to'') the locus. Some examples of equations of straight lines will illustrate the subject. \Figure[3.75in]{14} \PageSep{124} Consider $y - x = 0$; here the $a$,~$b$, and~$c$, of the general form have been replaced by $-1$,~$1$, and $0$ respectively. This line passes through the ``origin,''~$O$, in the diagram and bisects the angle~$XOY$. It is the line~$L'OL$ of the diagram. The fact that it passes through the origin,~$O$, is easily seen by observing that the equation is satisfied by putting $x = 0$ and $y = 0$ simultaneously, but $0$~and~$0$ are the coordinates of~$O$. In fact it is easy to generalize and to see by the same method that the equation of any line through the origin is of the form $ax + by = 0$. The locus of\Typo{}{ the} equation $y + x = 0$ also passes through the origin and bisects the angle~$X'OY$: it is the line~$L_{1}OL_{1}'$ of the diagram. Consider $y - x = 1$: the corresponding locus does not pass through the origin. We therefore seek where it cuts the axes. It must cut the axis of~$x$ at some point of coordinates $x$~and~$0$. But putting $y = 0$ in the equation, we get $x = -1$; so the coordinates of this point~$(A)$ are $1$~and~$0$. Similarly the point~$(B)$ where the line cuts the axis~$OY$ are $0$~and~$1$. The locus is the line~$AB$ in the figure and is parallel to~$LOL'$. Similarly $y + x = 1$ is the equation of line~$A_{1}B$ of the figure; and the locus is parallel to~$L_{1}OL_{1}'$. It is easy to prove the general theorem that two lines represented by equations of the forms $ax + by = 0$ and $ax + by = c$ are parallel. \PageSep{125} The group of loci which we next come upon are sufficiently important to deserve a chapter to themselves. But before going on to them we will dwell a little longer on the main ideas of the subject. The position of any point~$P$ is determined by arbitrarily choosing an origin,~$O$, two axes, \index{Axes}% $OX$~and~$OY$, at right-angles, and then by noting its coordinates $x$~and~$y$, \ie\ $OM$ and~$PM$ (\cf\ \Fig[fig.]{13}). Also, as we have seen in the last chapter, $P$~can be determined by the ``vector''~$OP$, where the idea of the vector includes a determinate direction as well as a determinate length. From an abstract mathematical point of view the idea of an arbitrary origin may appear artificial and clumsy, and similarly for the arbitrarily drawn axes, $OX$~and~$OY$. But in relation to the application of mathematics to the event of the Universe we are here symbolizing with direct simplicity the most fundamental fact respecting the outlook on the world afforded to us by our senses. We each of us refer our sensible perceptions of things to an origin which we call ``here'': our location in a particular part of space round which we group the whole Universe is the essential fact of our bodily existence. We can imagine beings who observe all phenomena in all space with an equal eye, unbiassed in favour of any part. With us it is otherwise, a cat at our \PageSep{126} feet claims more attention than an earthquake at Cape Horn, or than the destruction of a world in the Milky Way. It is true that in making a common stock of our knowledge with our fellowmen, we have to waive something of the strict egoism of our own individual ``here.'' We substitute ``nearly here'' for ``here''; thus we measure miles from the town hall of the nearest town, or from the capital of the country. In measuring the earth, men of science will put the origin at the earth's centre; astronomers \index{Origin}% even rise to the extreme altruism of putting their origin inside the sun. But, far as this last origin may be, and even if we go further to some convenient point amid the nearer fixed stars, yet, compared to the immeasurable infinities of space, it remains true that our first procedure in exploring the Universe is to fix upon an origin ``nearly here.'' Again the relation of the coordinates $OM$ and~$MP$ (\ie\ $x$~and~$y$) to the vector~$OP$ is an instance of the famous parallelogram law, as \index{Parallelogram Law}% can easily be seen (\cf\ \Fig[fig.]{8}) by completing the parallelogram~$OMPN$. The idea of the ``vector''~$OP$, that is, of a directed magnitude, is the root-idea of physical science. Any moving body has a certain magnitude of velocity in a certain direction, that is to say, its velocity is a directed magnitude, a vector. Again a force has a certain magnitude \PageSep{127} and has a definite direction. Thus, when in analytical geometry the ideas of the ``origin,'' of ``coordinates,'' and of ``vectors'' are introduced, we are studying the abstract conceptions which correspond to the fundamental facts of the physical world. \PageSep{128} \Chapter{X}{Conic Sections} \First{When} the Greek geometers had exhausted, \index{Conic Sections|EtSeq}% as they thought, the more obvious and interesting properties of figures made up of straight lines and circles, they turned to the study of other curves; and, with their almost infallible instinct for hitting upon things worth thinking about, they chiefly devoted themselves to conic sections, that is, to the curves in which planes would cut the surfaces of circular cones. The man who must have the credit of inventing the study is Menaechmus (born 375~\BC\ and \index{Menaechmus}% died 325~\BC); he was a pupil of Plato and one of the tutors of Alexander the Great. Alexander, by the by, is a conspicuous \index{Alexander the Great}% example of the advantages of good tuition, for another of his tutors was the philosopher Aristotle. We may suspect that \index{Aristotle}% Alexander found Menaechmus rather a dull teacher, for it is related that he asked for the \PageSep{129} proofs to be made shorter. It was to this request that Menaechmus replied: ``In the \index{Menaechmus}% country there are private and even royal roads, but in geometry there is only one road for all.'' This reply no doubt was true enough in the sense in which it would have been immediately understood by Alexander. But if Menaechmus thought that his proofs could not be shortened, he was grievously mistaken; and most modern mathematicians would be horribly bored, if they were compelled to study the Greek proofs of the properties of conic sections. Nothing illustrates better the gain in power which is obtained by the introduction of relevant ideas into a science than to observe the progressive shortening of proofs which accompanies the growth of richness in idea. There is a certain type of mathematician who is always rather impatient at delaying over the ideas of a subject: he is anxious at once to get on to the proofs of ``important'' problems. The history of the science is entirely against him. There are royal roads in science; but those who first tread them are men of genius and \index{Alexander the Great}% not kings. The way in which conic sections first presented themselves to mathematicians was as follows: think of a cone (\cf\ \Fig[fig.]{15}), whose vertex (or point) is~$V$, standing on a circular base~$STU$. For example, a conical shade to \PageSep{130} an electric light is often an example of such a surface. Now let the ``generating'' lines which pass through~$V$ and lie on the surface be all produced backwards; the result is a double cone, and $PQR$~is another circular cross section on the opposite side of~$V$ to the cross section~$STU$. The axis of the cone~$CVC'$ passes through all the centres of these circles and is perpendicular to their planes, which are parallel to each other. In the diagram the parts of the curves which are supposed to lie behind the plane of the paper are dotted lines, and the parts on the plane or in front of it are continuous lines. Now suppose this double cone is cut by a plane not perpendicular to the axis~$CVC'$, or at least not necessarily perpendicular to it. Then three cases can arise:--- (1) The plane may cut the cone in a closed \index{Ellipse|EtSeq}% oval curve, such as~$ABA'B'$ which lies entirely on one of the two half-cones. In this case the plane will not meet the other half-cone at all. Such a curve is called an ellipse; it is an oval curve. A particular case of such a section of the cone is when the plane is perpendicular to the axis~$CVC'$, then the section, such as $STU$ or $PQR$, is a circle. Hence a \index{Circle}% circle is a particular case of the ellipse. (2) The plane may be parallelled to a tangent plane touching the cone along one of its ``generating'' lines as for example the plane of the \PageSep{131} \index{Parabola|EtSeq}% curve $D_{1}A_{1}D_{1}'$ in the diagram is parallel to the tangent plane touching the cone along the generating line~$VS$; the curve is still confined to one of the half-cones, but it is now not a closed oval curve, it goes on endlessly as long as the generating lines of the half-cone are produced away from the vertex. Such a conic section is called parabola. (3) The plane may cut both the half-cones, \index{Hyperbola|EtSeq}% so that the complete curve consists of two detached portions, or ``branches'' as they are called, this case is illustrated by the two branches $G_{2}A_{2}G_{2}'$ and $L_{2}A_{2}'L_{2}'$ which together make up the curve. Neither branch is closed, each of them spreading out endlessly as the two half-cones are prolonged away from the vertex. Such a conic section is called a hyperbola. There are accordingly three types of conic sections, namely, ellipses, parabolas, and hyperbolas. It is easy to see that, in a sense, parabolas are limiting cases lying between ellipses and hyperbolas. They form a more special sort and have to satisfy a more particular condition. These three names are apparently due to Apollonius of Perga (born \index{Apollonius of Perga}% about 260~\BC, and died about 200~\BC), who wrote a systematic treatise on conic sections which remained the standard work till the sixteenth century. %[** TN: Moved to top of paragraph] \Figure{15} It must at once be apparent how awkward \PageSep{132} and difficult the investigation of the properties of these curves must have been to the Greek geometers. The curves are plane curves, and yet their investigation involves the drawing in perspective of a solid figure. Thus in the diagram given above we have practically drawn no subsidiary lines and yet the figure is sufficiently complicated. The \PageSep{133} curves are plane curves, and it seems obvious that we should be able to define them without \Figure{16} going beyond the plane into a solid figure. At the same time, just as in the ``solid'' \Figure[2.5in]{17} definition there is one uniform method of definition---namely, the section of a cone by \PageSep{134} a plane---which yields three cases, so in any ``plane'' definition there also should be one uniform method of procedure which falls into three cases. Their shapes when drawn on their planes are those of the curved lines in the three figures \FigNum{16},~\FigNum{17}, and~\FigNum{18}. The points $A$~and~$A'$ in the figures are called %[** TN: Labels A, A', M, and line PM added to match the text] \Figure[4in]{18} the vertices and the line~$AA'$ the major axis. It will be noted that a parabola (\cf\ \Fig[fig.]{17}) \index{Apollonius of Perga}% \index{Vertex}% has only one vertex. Apollonius proved\footnote {\Chg{Cf.}{\Cf}\ Ball, \Foreign{loc.\ cit.}, for this account of Apollonius and Pappus.} that the ratio of $PM^{2}$ to $AM·MA'$ $\left(\ie\ \dfrac{PM^{2}}{AM·\Typo{MA}{MA'}}\right)$ remains constant both for the ellipse and the hyperbola (figs.\ \FigNum{16} and \FigNum{18}), and that the ratio \PageSep{135} of $PM^{2}$ to~$AM$ is constant for the parabola of \Fig[fig.]{17}; and he bases most of his work on this fact. We are evidently advancing towards the desired uniform definition which does not go out of the plane; but have not yet quite attained to uniformity. In the diagrams \FigNum{16} and~\FigNum{18}, two points, $S$ and~$S'$, will be seen marked, and in \Fig[diagram]{17} one point,~$S$. These are the \emph{foci} of the curves, and are points of the greatest importance. Apollonius knew that for an ellipse the sum of $SP$ and~$S'P$ (\ie\ $SP + S'P$) is constant as $P$~moves on the curve, and is equal to~$AA'$. Similarly for a hyperbola the difference $S'P - SP$ is constant, and equal to~$AA'$ when $P$~is on one branch, and the difference $SP' - S'P'$ is constant and equal to~$AA'$ when $P'$~is on the other branch. But no corresponding point seemed to exist for the parabola. Finally $500$~years later the last great Greek geometer, Pappus of Alexandria, discovered \index{Pappus}% the final secret which completed this line of thought. In the diagrams \FigNum{16} and~\FigNum{18} will be seen two lines, $XN$~and~$X'N'$, and in \Fig[diagram]{17} the single line,~$XN$. These are the directrices of the curves, two each for the ellipse and the hyperbola, and one for the parabola. Each directrix corresponds to its nearer focus. \index{Directrix}% \index{Focus}% The characteristic property of a focus,~$S$, and its corresponding directrix,~$XN$, for any one of the three types of curve, is that the ratio \PageSep{136} $SP$ to~$PN$ $\left(\ie\ \dfrac{SP}{PN}\right)$ is constant, where $PN$~is the perpendicular on the directrix from~$P$, and $P$~is any point on the curve. Here we have finally found the desired property of the curves which does not require us to leave the plane, and is stated uniformly for all three curves. For ellipses the ratio\footnote {\Chg{Cf.}{\Cf}\ Note~B, \Pageref{noteB}.\Pagelabel{136}} is less than~$1$, for parabolas it is equal to~$1$, and for hyperbolas it is greater than~$1$. When Pappus had finished his investigations, \index{Pappus}% he must have felt that, apart from minor extensions, the subject was practically exhausted; and if he could have foreseen the history of science for more than a thousand years, it would have confirmed his belief. Yet in truth the really fruitful ideas in connection with this branch of mathematics had not yet been even touched on, and no one had guessed their supremely important applications in nature. No more impressive warning can be given to those who would confine knowledge and research to what is apparently useful, than the reflection that conic sections were studied for eighteen hundred years merely as an abstract science, without a thought of any utility other than to satisfy the craving for knowledge on the part of mathematicians, and that then at the end of this long period of abstract study, they \PageSep{137} were found to be the necessary key with which to attain the knowledge of one of the most important laws of nature. Meanwhile the entirely distinct study of astronomy had been going forward. The \index{Astronomy}% great Greek astronomer Ptolemy (died 168~\AD) \index{Ptolemy}% published his standard treatise on the subject in the University of Alexandria, explaining the apparent motions among the fixed stars of the sun and planets by the conception of the earth at rest and the sun and the planets circling round it. During the next thirteen hundred years the number and the accuracy of the astronomical observations increased, with the result that the description of the motions of the planets on Ptolemy's hypothesis had to be made more and more complicated. Copernicus (born \index{Copernicus}% 1473~\AD\ and died 1543~\AD) pointed out that the motions of these heavenly bodies could be explained in a simpler manner if the sun were supposed to rest, and the earth and planets were conceived as moving round it. However, he still thought of these motions as essentially circular, though modified by a set of small corrections arbitrarily superimposed on the primary circular motions. So the matter stood when Kepler was born at Stuttgart \index{Kepler}% in Germany in 1571~\AD. There were two sciences, that of the geometry of conic sections and that of astronomy, both of which \PageSep{138} had been studied from a remote antiquity without a suspicion of any connection between the two. Kepler was an astronomer, \index{Kepler}% but he was also an able geometer, and on the subject of conic sections had arrived at ideas in advance of his time\Add{.} He is only one of many examples of the falsity of the idea that success in scientific research demands an exclusive absorption in one narrow line of study. Novel ideas are more apt to spring from an unusual assortment of knowledge---not necessarily from vast knowledge, but from a thorough conception of the methods and ideas of distinct lines of thought. It will be remembered that Charles Darwin was helped \index{Darwin}% to arrive at his conception of the law of evolution by reading Malthus' famous \Title{Essay \index{Malthus}% on Population}, a work dealing with a different subject---at least, as it was then thought. Kepler enunciated three laws of planetary \index{Kepler's Laws}% motion, the first two in~1609, and the third ten years later. They are as follows: (1) The orbits of the planets are ellipses, the sun being in the focus. (2) As a planet moves in its orbit, the radius vector from the sun to the planet sweeps out equal areas in equal times. (3) The squares of the periodic times of the several planets are proportional to the cubes of their major axes. \PageSep{139} These laws proved to be only a stage towards a more fundamental development of ideas. Newton (born 1642~\AD\ and died \index{Newton}% 1727~\AD) conceived the idea of universal gravitation, namely, that any two pieces of \index{Gravitation}% matter attract each other with a force proportional to the product of their masses and inversely proportional to the square of their distance from each other. This sweeping general law, coupled with the three laws of motion which he put into their final general shape, proved adequate to explain all astronomical phenomena, including Kepler's laws, and has formed the basis of modern physics. Among other things he proved that comets might move in very elongated ellipses, or in parabolas, or in hyperbolas, which are nearly parabolas. The comets which return---such as Halley's comet---must, of course, move in \index{Halley}% ellipses. But the essential step in the proof of the law of gravitation, and even in the suggestion of its initial conception, was the verification of Kepler's laws connecting the motions of the planets with the theory of conic sections. From the seventeenth century onwards the abstract theory of the curves has shared in the double renaissance of geometry due to the introduction of coordinate geometry and of projective geometry. In projective geometry \index{Projective Geometry}% the fundamental ideas cluster round \PageSep{140} the consideration of sets (or pencils, as they \index{Pencils}% are called) of lines passing through a common point (the vertex of the ``pencil''). Now (\cf\ \Fig[fig.]{19}) if $A$,~$B$, $C$,~$D$, be any four fixed points on a conic section and $P$~be a variable point on the curve, the pencil of lines $PA$, \Figure[2.5in]{19} $PB$, $PC$, and~$PD$, has a special property, known as the constancy of its cross ratio. It \index{Cross Ratio}% will suffice here to say that cross ratio is a fundamental idea in projective geometry. For projective geometry this is really the definition of the curves, or some analogous property which is really equivalent to it. It \PageSep{141} will be seen how far in the course of ages of study we have drifted away from the old original idea of the sections of a circular cone. We know now that the Greeks had got hold of a minor property of comparatively slight importance; though by some divine good fortune the curves themselves deserved all the attention which was paid to them. This unimportance of the ``section'' idea is now marked in ordinary mathematical phraseology by dropping the word from their names. As often as not, they are now named merely ``conics'' instead of ``conic sections.'' Finally, we come back to the point at \index{Locus}% which we left coordinate geometry in the last chapter. We had asked what was the type of \emph{loci} corresponding to the general algebraic form $ax + by = c$, and had found that it was the class of straight lines in the plane. We had seen that every straight line possesses an equation of this form, and that every equation of this form corresponds to a straight line. We now wish to go on to the next general type of algebraic forms. This is evidently to be obtained by introducing terms involving $x^{2}$~and $xy$ and~$y^{2}$. Thus the new general form must be written\Add{:}--- \[ ax^{2} + 2hxy + by^{2} + 2gx + 2fy + c = 0\Add{.} \] What does this represent? The answer is \PageSep{142} that (when it represents any locus) it always represents a conic section, and, furthermore, that the equation of every conic section can always be put into this shape. The discrimination of the particular sorts of conics as given by this form of equation is very easy. It entirely depends upon the consideration of $ab - h^{2}$, where $a$,~$b$, and~$h$, are the ``constants'' as written above. If $ab - h^{2}$ is a positive number, the curve is an ellipse; if $ab - h^{2} = 0$, the curve is a parabola: and if $ab - h^{2}$ is a negative number, the curve is a hyperbola. For example, put $a = b = 1$, $h = g = f = 0$, $c = -4$. We then get the equation $x^{2} + y^{2} - 4 = 0$. It is easy to prove that this is the equation of a circle, whose centre is at the origin, and radius is $2$~units of length. Now $ab - h^{2}$ becomes $1 × 1 - 0^{2}$, that is,~$1$, and is therefore positive. Hence the circle is a particular case of an ellipse, as it ought to be. Generalising, the equation of any circle can be put into the form $a(x^{2} + y^{2}) + 2gx + 2fy + c = 0$. Hence $ab - h^{2}$ becomes $a^{2} - 0$, that is,~$a^{2}$, which is necessarily positive. Accordingly all circles satisfy the condition for ellipses. The general form of the equation of a parabola is \[ (dx + ey)^{2} + 2gx + 2fy + c = 0, \] so that the terms of the second degree, as \PageSep{143} they are called, can be written as a perfect square. For squaring out, we get \[ d^{2} x^{2} + 2dexy + e^{2} y^{2} + 2gx + 2fy + c; \] so that by comparison $a = d^{2}$, $h = de$, $b = e^{2}$, and therefore $ab - h^{2} = d^{2} e^{2} - (de)^{2} = 0$. Hence the necessary condition is automatically satisfied. The equation $2xy - 4 = 0$, where $a = b = g = f = 0$, $h = 1$, $c = -4$, represents a hyperbola. For the condition $ab - h^{2}$ becomes $0 - 1^{2}$, that is,~$-1$, which is negative. {\Loosen The limitation, introduced by saying that, \index{Circular Cylinder}% \emph{when the general equation represents any locus}, it represents a conic section, is necessary, because some particular cases of the general equation represent no real locus. For example $x^{2} + y^{2} + 1 = 0$ can be satisfied by no real values of $x$~and~$y$. It is usual to say that the locus is now one composed of imaginary points. But this idea of imaginary points in geometry is really one of great complexity, which we will not now enter into.} Some exceptional cases are included in the general form of the equation which may not be immediately recognized as conic sections. By properly choosing the constants the equation can be made to represent two straight lines. Now two intersecting straight lines may fairly be said to come under the Greek idea of a conic section. For, by referring to \PageSep{144} the picture of the double cone above, it will be seen that some planes through the vertex,~$V$, will cut the cone in a pair of straight lines intersecting at~$V$. The case of two parallel straight lines can be included by considering a circular cylinder as a particular case of a cone. Then a plane, which cuts it and is parallel to its axis, will cut it in two parallel straight lines. Anyhow, whether or no the %[** TN: [sic] "Greek", not "Greeks"] ancient Greek would have allowed these special cases to be called conic sections, they are certainly included among the curves represented by the general algebraic form of the second degree. This fact is worth noting; for it is characteristic of modern mathematics to include among general forms all sorts of particular cases which would formerly have received special treatment. This is due to its pursuit of generality. \PageSep{145} \Chapter{XI}{Functions} \First{The} mathematical use of the term function %[** TN: Index entry reads "p. 144" in the original] \index{Function|EtSeq}% has been adopted also in common life. For example, ``His temper is a function of his digestion,'' uses the term exactly in this mathematical sense. It means that a rule can be assigned which will tell you what his temper will be when you know how his digestion is working. Thus the idea of a ``function'' is simple enough, we only have to see how it is applied in mathematics to variable numbers. Let us think first of some concrete examples: If a train has been travelling at the rate of twenty miles per hour, the distance ($s$~miles) gone after any number of hours, say~$t$, is given by $s = 20 × t$; and $s$~is called a function of~$t$. Also $20 × t$ is the function of~$t$ with which $s$~is identical. If John is one year older than Thomas, then, when Thomas is at any age of $x$~years, John's age ($y$~years) is given by $y = x + 1$; and $y$~is a function of~$x$, namely, is the function~$x + 1$. In these examples $t$ and~$x$ are called the \PageSep{146} \index{Argument of a Function}% \index{Value of a Function}% ``arguments'' of the functions in which they appear. Thus $t$~is the argument of the function $20 × t$, and $x$~is the argument of the function $x + 1$. If $s = 20 × t$, and $y = x + 1$, then $s$ and~$y$ are called the ``values'' of the functions $20 × t$ and $x + 1$ respectively. Coming now to the general case, we can define a function in mathematics as a correlation between two variable numbers, called respectively the argument and the value of the function, such that whatever value be assigned to the ``argument of the function'' the ``value of the function'' is definitely (\ie~uniquely) determined. The converse is not necessarily true, namely, that when the value of the function is determined the argument is also uniquely determined. Other functions of the argument~$x$ are $y = x^{2}$, %[** TN: log, sin italicized throughout in the original] $y = 2x^{2} + 3x + 1$, $y = x$, $y = \log x$, $y = \sin x$. The last two functions of this group will be readily recognizable by those who understand a little algebra and trigonometry. It is not worth while to delay now for their explanation, as they are merely quoted for the sake of example. Up to this point, though we have defined what we mean by a function in general, we have only mentioned a series of special functions. But mathematics, true to its general methods of procedure, symbolizes the general idea of any function. It does this by writing \PageSep{147} \index{Variable Function}% $F(x)$, $f(x)$, $g(x)$, $\phi(x)$,~etc., for any function of~$x$, where the argument~$x$ is placed in a bracket, and some letter like $F$,~$f$, $g$, $\phi$,~etc., is prefixed to the bracket to stand for the function. This notation has its defects. Thus it obviously clashes with the convention that the single letters are to represent variable numbers; since here $F$,~$f$, $g$, $\phi$,~etc., prefixed to a bracket stand for variable functions. It would be easy to give examples in which we can only trust to common sense and the context to see what is meant. One way of evading the confusion is by using Greek letters (\eg~$\phi$ as above) for functions; another way is to keep to $f$~and~$F$ (the initial letter of function) for the functional letter, and, if other variable functions have to be symbolized, to take an adjacent letter like~$g$. With these explanations and cautions, we write $y = f(x)$, to denote that $y$~is the value of some undetermined function of the argument~$x$; where $f(x)$ may stand for anything such as $x + 1$, $x^{2} - 2x + 1$, $\sin x$, $\log x$, or merely for $x$~itself. The essential point is that when $x$~is given, then $y$~is thereby definitely determined. It is important to be quite clear as to the generality of this idea. Thus in $y = f(x)$, we may determine, if we choose, $f(x)$~to mean that when $x$~is an integer, $f(x)$~is zero, and when $x$~has any other value, $f(x)$~is~$1$. Accordingly, putting $y = f(x)$, with this choice \PageSep{148} for the meaning of~$f$, $y$~is either $0$ or~$1$ according as the value of~$x$ is integral or otherwise. Thus $f(1) = 0$, $f(2) = 0$, $f(\frac{2}{3}) = 1$, $f(\sqrt{2}) = 1$, and so on. This choice for the meaning of~$f(x)$ gives a perfectly good function of the argument~$x$ according to the general definition of a function. A function, which after all is only a sort \index{Graphs|EtSeq}% of correlation between two variables, is represented like other correlations by a graph, that is in effect by the methods of coordinate geometry. For example, \Fig[fig.]{2} in \ChapRef{II}.\ is the graph of the function~$\dfrac{1}{v}$ where $v$~is the argument and $p$~the value of the function. In this case the graph is only drawn for positive values of~$v$, which are the only values possessing any meaning for the physical application considered in that chapter. Again in \Fig[fig.]{14} of \ChapRef{IX}.\ the whole length of the line~$AB$, unlimited in both directions, is the graph of the function~$x + 1$, where $x$~is the argument and $y$~is the value of the function; and in the same figure the unlimited line~$A_{1}B$ is the graph of the function~$1 - x$, and the line~$LOL'$ is the graph of the function~$x$, $x$~being the argument and $y$~the value of the function. These functions, which are expressed by simple algebraic formulæ, are adapted for representation by graphs. But for some functions \PageSep{149} this representation would be very misleading without a detailed explanation, or might even be impossible. Thus, consider the function mentioned above, which has the value~$1$ for all values of its argument~$x$, except those which are integral, \eg\ except for $x = 0$, $x = 1$, $x = 2$, etc., when it has the value~$0$. Its appearance on a graph would be that of the straight line~$ABA'$ drawn parallel to the \Figure{20} axis~$XOX'$ at a distance from it of $1$~unit of length. But the points, $B$,~$C_{1}$, $C_{2}$, $C_{3}$, $C_{4}$,~etc., corresponding to the values $0$,~$1$, $2$, $3$, $4$,~etc., of the argument~$x$, are to be omitted, and instead of them the points $O$,~$B_{1}$, $B_{2}$, $B_{3}$, $B_{4}$,~etc., on the axis~$OX$, are to be taken. It is easy to find functions for which the graphical representation is not only inconvenient but impossible. Functions which do not lend themselves to graphs are important in the \PageSep{150} higher mathematics, but we need not concern ourselves further about them here. The most important division between functions \index{Continuous Functions|EtSeq}% \index{Discontinuous Functions|EtSeq}% is that between continuous and discontinuous functions. A function is continuous when its value only alters gradually for gradual alterations of the argument, and is discontinuous when it can alter its value by sudden jumps. Thus the two functions $x + 1$ and $1 - x$, whose graphs are depicted as straight lines in \Fig[fig.]{14} of \ChapRef{IX}., are continuous functions, and so is the function~$\dfrac{1}{v}$, depicted in \ChapRef{II}., if we only think of positive values of~$v$. But the function depicted in \Fig[fig.]{20} of this chapter is discontinuous since at the values $x = 1$, $x = 2$, etc., of its argument, its value gives sudden jumps. Let us think of some examples of functions presented to us in nature, so as to get into our heads the real bearing of continuity and discontinuity. Consider a train in its journey along a railway line, say from Euston Station, the terminus in London of the London and North-Western Railway. Along the line in order lie the stations of Bletchley and Rugby. Let $t$~be the number of hours which the train has been on its journey from Euston, and $s$~be the number of miles passed over. Then $s$~is a function of~$t$, \ie~is the variable value corresponding to the variable argument~$t$. \PageSep{151} If we know the circumstances of the train's run, we know~$s$ as soon as any special value of~$t$ is given. Now, miracles apart, we may confidently assume that $s$~is a continuous function of~$t$. It is impossible to allow for the contingency that we can trace the train continuously from Euston to Bletchley, and that then, without any intervening time, however short, it should appear at Rugby. The idea is too fantastic to enter into our calculation: it contemplates possibilities not to be found outside the \Title{Arabian Nights}; and even in those tales sheer discontinuity of motion hardly enters into the imagination, they do not dare to tax our credulity with anything more than very unusual speed. But unusual speed is no contradiction to the great law of continuity of motion which appears to hold in nature. Thus light moves at the rate of about $190,000$ miles per~second and comes to us from the sun in seven or eight minutes; but, in spite of this speed, its distance travelled is always a continuous function of the time. It is not quite so obvious to us that the velocity of a body is invariably a continuous function of the time. Consider the train at any time~$t$: it is moving with some definite velocity, say $v$~miles per~hour, where $v$~is zero when the train is at rest in a station and is negative when the train is backing. Now we readily allow that $v$~cannot change its \PageSep{152} value suddenly for a big, heavy train. The train certainly cannot be running at forty miles per hour from 11.45~a.m.\ up to noon, and then suddenly, without any lapse of time, commence running at $50$~miles per~hour. We at once admit that the change of velocity will be a gradual process. But how about sudden blows of adequate magnitude? Suppose two trains collide; or, to take smaller objects, suppose a man kicks a football. It certainly appears to our sense as though the football began suddenly to move. Thus, in the case of velocity our senses do not revolt at the idea of its being a discontinuous function of the time, as they did at the idea of the train being instantaneously transported from Bletchley to Rugby. As a matter of fact, if the laws of motion, with their conception of mass, are true, there is no such thing as discontinuous velocity in nature. Anything that appears to our senses as discontinuous change of velocity must, according to them, be considered to be a case of gradual change which is too quick to be perceptible to us. It would be rash, however, to rush into the generalization that no discontinuous functions are presented to us in nature. A man who, trusting that the mean height of the land above sea-level between London and Paris was a continuous function of the distance from London, walked at night on Shakespeare's \PageSep{153} Cliff by Dover in contemplation of the Milky Way, would be dead before he had had time to rearrange his ideas as to the necessity of caution in scientific conclusions. It is very easy to find a discontinuous function, even if we confine ourselves to the \Figure{21} simplest of the algebraic formulæ. For example, take the function $y = \dfrac{1}{x}$, which we have already considered in the form $p = \dfrac{1}{v}$, where $v$~was confined to positive values. But \PageSep{154} now let $x$ have any value, positive or negative. The graph of the function is exhibited in \Fig[fig.]{21}. Suppose $x$ to change continuously from a large negative value through a numerically decreasing set of negative values up to~$0$, and thence through the series of increasing positive values. Accordingly, if a moving point,~$M$, represents~$x$ on~$XOX'$, $M$~starts at the extreme left of the axis~$XOX'$ and successively moves through $M_{1}$,~$M_{2}$, $M_{3}$, $M_{4}$,~etc. The corresponding points on the function are $P_{1}$,~$P_{2}$, $P_{3}$, $P_{4}$,~etc. It is easy to see that there is a point of discontinuity at $x = 0$, \ie~at the origin~$O$. For the value of the function on the negative (left) side of the origin becomes endlessly great, but negative, and the function reappears on the positive (right) side as endlessly great but positive. Hence, however small we take the length~$M_{2} M_{3}$, there is a finite jump between the values of the function at $M_{2}$ and~$M_{3}$. Indeed, this case has the peculiarity that the smaller we take the length between $M_{2}$ and~$M_{3}$, so long as they enclose the origin, the bigger is the jump in value of the function between them. This graph brings out, what is also apparent in \Fig[fig.]{20} of this chapter, that for many functions the discontinuities only occur at isolated points, so that by restricting the values of the argument we obtain a continuous function for these remaining values. Thus it is evident \PageSep{155} from \Fig[fig.]{21} that in $y = \dfrac{1}{x}$, if we keep to positive values only and exclude the origin, we obtain a continuous function. Similarly the same function, if we keep to negative values only, excluding the origin, is continuous. Again the function which is graphed in \Fig[fig.]{20} is continuous between $B$ and~$C_{1}$, and between $C_{1}$ and~$C_{2}$, and between $C_{2}$ and $C_{3}$, and so on, always in each case excluding the end points. It is, however, easy to find functions such that their discontinuities occur at all points. For example, consider a function~$f(x)$, such that when $x$~is any fractional number $f(x) = 1$, and when $x$~is any incommensurable number $f(x) = 2$. This function is discontinuous at all points. Finally, we will look a little more closely at the definition of continuity given above. We have said that a function is continuous when its value only alters gradually for gradual alterations of the argument, and is discontinuous when it can alter its value by sudden jumps. This is exactly the sort of definition which satisfied our mathematical forefathers and no longer satisfies modern mathematicians. It is worth while to spend some time over it; for when we understand the modern objections to it, we shall have gone a long way towards the understanding of the spirit of modern mathematics. The \PageSep{156} whole difference between the older and the newer mathematics lies in the fact that vague half-metaphorical terms like ``gradually'' are no longer tolerated in its exact statements. Modern mathematics will only admit statements and definitions and arguments which exclusively employ the few simple ideas about number and magnitude and variables on which the science is founded. Of two numbers one can be greater or less than the other; and one can be such and such a multiple of the other; but there is no relation of ``graduality'' between two numbers, and hence the term is inadmissible. Now this may seem at first sight to be great pedantry. To this charge there are two answers. In the first place, during the first half of the nineteenth century it was found by some great mathematicians, especially Abel in \index{Abel}% Sweden, and Weierstrass in Germany, that \index{Weierstrass}% large parts of mathematics as enunciated in the old happy-go-lucky manner were simply wrong. Macaulay in his essay on Bacon \index{Bacon}% \index{Macaulay}% contrasts the certainty of mathematics with the uncertainty of philosophy; and by way of a rhetorical example he says, ``There has been no reaction against Taylor's theorem.'' \index{Taylor's Theorem}% He could not have chosen a worse example. For, without having made an examination of English text-books on mathematics contemporary with the publication of this essay, the \PageSep{157} \index{Taylor's Theorem}% assumption is a fairly safe one that Taylor's theorem was enunciated and proved wrongly in every one of them. Accordingly, the anxious precision of modern mathematics is necessary for accuracy. In the second place it is necessary for research. It makes for clearness of thought, and thence for boldness of thought and for fertility in trying new combinations of ideas. When the initial statements are vague and slipshod, at every subsequent stage of thought common sense has to step in to limit applications and to explain meanings. Now in creative thought common sense is a bad master. Its sole criterion for judgment is that the new ideas shall look like the old ones. In other words it can only act by suppressing originality. In working our way towards the precise definition of continuity (as applied to functions) let us consider more closely the statement that there is no relation of ``graduality'' between numbers. It may be asked, Cannot one number be only slightly greater than another number, or in other words, cannot the difference between the two numbers be small? The whole point is that in the abstract, apart from some arbitrarily assumed application, there is no such thing as a great or a small number. A million miles is a small number of miles for an astronomer investigating the fixed stars, but a million \PageSep{158} pounds is a large yearly income. Again, one-quarter is a large fraction of one's income to give away in charity, but is a small fraction of it to retain for private use. Examples can be accumulated indefinitely to show that great or small in any absolute sense have no abstract application to numbers. We can say of two numbers that one is greater or smaller than another, but not without specification of particular circumstances that any one number is great or small. Our task therefore is to define continuity without any mention of a ``small'' or ``gradual'' change in value of the function. In order to do this we will give names to some ideas, which will also be useful when we come to consider limits and the differential calculus. An ``interval'' of values of the argument~$x$ \index{Interval|EtSeq}% of a function~$f(x)$ is all the values lying between some two values of the argument. For example, the interval between $x = 1$ and $x = 2$ consists of all the values which~$x$ can take lying between $1$ and~$2$, \ie\ it consists of all the real numbers between $1$ and~$2$. But the bounding numbers of an interval need not be integers. An interval of values of the argument \emph{contains} a number~$a$, when $a$~is a member of the interval. For example, the interval between $1$ and~$2$ contains $\frac{3}{2}$, $\frac{5}{3}$, $\frac{7}{4}$, and so on. \PageSep{159} A set of numbers approximates to a number~$a$ \index{Standard of Approximation|EtSeq}% within a \emph{standard}~$k$, when the numerical difference between $a$ and every number of the set is less than~$k$. Here $k$~is the ``standard of approximation.'' Thus the set of numbers $3$,~$4$, $6$,~$8$, approximates to the number~$5$ within the standard~$4$. In this case the standard~$4$ is not the smallest which could have been chosen, the set also approximates %[** TN: Original uses center dot for decimal point] to~$5$ within any of the standards $3.1$ or $3.01$ or~$3.001$. Again, the numbers, $3.1$, $3.141$, $3.1415$, $3.14159$ approximate to $3.13102$ within the standard~$.032$, and also within the smaller standard~$.03103$. These two ideas of an interval and of \index{Neighbourhood|EtSeq}% approximation to a number within a standard are easy enough; their only difficulty is that they look rather trivial. But when combined with the next idea, that of the ``neighbourhood'' of a number, they form the foundation of modern mathematical reasoning. What do we mean by saying that something is true for a function~$f(x)$ in the neighbourhood of the value~$a$ of the argument~$x$? It is this fundamental notion which we have now got to make precise. The values of a function~$f(x)$ are said to possess a characteristic in the ``neighbourhood of~$a$'' when some interval can be found, which (i)~contains the number~$a$ not as an end-point, and (ii)~is such that every value \PageSep{160} of the function for arguments, other than~$a$, lying within that interval possesses the characteristic. The value~$f(a)$ of the function for the argument~$a$ may or may not possess the characteristic. Nothing is decided on this point by statements about the \emph{neighbourhood} of~$a$. For example, suppose we take the particular function~$x^{2}$. Now \emph{in the neighbourhood of~$2$}, the values of~$x^{2}$ are less than~$5$. For we can find an interval, \eg\ from $1$ to~$2.1$, which (i)~contains $2$ not as an end-point, and (ii)~is such that, for values of~$x$ lying within it, $x^{2}$~is less than~$5$. Now, combining the preceding ideas we know what is meant by saying that \emph{in the neighbourhood of~$a$} the function~$f(x)$ approximates to~$c$ within the \emph{standard}~$k$. It means that some interval can be found which (i)~includes $a$ not as an end-point, and (ii)~is such that all values of~$f(x)$, where $x$~lies in the interval and is not~$a$, differ from~$c$ by less than~$k$. For example, in the neighbourhood of~$2$, the function~$\sqrt{x}$ approximates to~$1.41425$ within the standard~$.0001$. This is true because the square root of~$1.99996164$ is~$1.4142$ and the square root of~$2.00024449$ is~$1.4143$; hence for values of~$x$ lying in the interval $1.99996164$ to~$2.00024449$, which contains $2$ not as an end-point, the values of the function~$\sqrt{x}$ all lie between $1.4142$ and $1.4143$, and \PageSep{161} they therefore all differ from~$1.41425$ by less than~$.0001$. In this case we can, if we like, fix a smaller standard of approximation, namely $.000051$ or $.0000501$. Again, to take another example, in the neighbourhood of~$2$ the function~$x^{2}$ approximates to~$4$ within the standard~$.5$. For $(1.9)^{2} = 3.61$ and $(2.1)^{2} = 4.41$, and thus the required interval $1.9$ to~$2.1$, containing $2$ not as an end-point, has been found. This example brings out the fact that statements about a function~$f(x)$ in the neighbourhood of a number~$a$ are distinct from statements about the value of~$f(x)$ when $x = a$. The production of an \emph{interval}, throughout which the statement is true, is required. Thus the mere fact that $2^{2} = 4$ does not by itself justify us in saying that in the \emph{neighbourhood} of~$2$ the function~$x^{2}$ is equal to~$4$. This statement would be untrue, because no interval can be produced with the required property. Also, the fact that $2^{2} = 4$ does not by itself justify us in saying that in the \emph{neighbourhood} of~$2$ the function~$x^{2}$ approximates to~$4$ within the standard~$.5$; although as a matter of fact, the statement has just been proved to be true. If we understand the preceding ideas, we understand the foundations of modern mathematics. We shall recur to analogous ideas in the chapter on Series, and again in the chapter on the Differential Calculus. \PageSep{162} \index{Continuous Functions@Continuous Functions (\emph{defined})}% Meanwhile, we are now prepared to define ``continuous functions.'' A function~$f(x)$ is ``continuous'' at a value~$a$ of its argument, when in the neighbourhood of~$a$ its values approximate to~$f(a)$ (\ie~to its value at~$a$) within \emph{every} standard of approximation. This means that, whatever standard~$k$ be chosen, in the neighbourhood of~$a$ $f(x)$~approximates to~$f(a)$ within the standard~$k$. For example, $x^{2}$~is continuous at the value~$2$ of its argument,~$x$, because however $k$~be chosen we can always find an interval, which (i)~contains $2$ not as an end-point, and (ii)~is such that the values of~$x^{2}$ for arguments lying within it approximate to~$4$ (\ie~$2^{2}$) within the standard~$k$. Thus, suppose we choose the standard~$.1$; now $(1.999)^{2} = 3.996001$, and $(2.01)^{2} = 4.0401$, and both these numbers differ from~$4$ by less than~$.1$. Hence, within the interval $1.999$ to $2.01$ the values of~$x^{2}$ approximate to~$4$ within the standard~$.1$. Similarly an interval can be produced for any other standard which we like to try. Take the example of the railway train. Its velocity is continuous as it passes the signal box, if whatever velocity you like to assign (say one-millionth of a mile per hour) an interval of time can be found extending before and after the instant of passing, such that at all instants within it the train's velocity \PageSep{163} differs from that with which the train passed the box by less than one-millionth of a mile per hour; and the same is true whatever other velocity be mentioned in the place of one-millionth of a mile per hour. \PageSep{164} \Chapter{XII}{Periodicity in Nature} \First{The} whole life of Nature is dominated by \index{Periodicity|EtSeq}% the existence of periodic events, that is, by the existence of successive events so analogous to each other that, without any straining of language, they may be termed recurrences of the same event. The rotation of the earth produces the successive days. It is true that each day is different from the preceding days, however abstractly we define the meaning of a day, so as to exclude casual phenomena. But with a sufficiently abstract definition of a day, the distinction in properties between two days becomes faint and remote from practical interest; and each day may then be conceived as a recurrence of the phenomenon of one rotation of the earth. Again the path of the earth round the sun leads to the yearly recurrence of the seasons, and imposes another periodicity on all the operations of nature. Another less fundamental periodicity is provided by the phases of the moon. In modern civilized life, with its artificial light, these phases are of slight importance, but in \PageSep{165} ancient times, in climates where the days are burning and the skies clear, human life was apparently largely influenced by the existence of moonlight. Accordingly our divisions into weeks and months, with their religious associations, have spread over the European races from Syria and Mesopotamia, though independent observances following the moon's phases are found amongst most nations. It is, however, through the tides, and not through its phases of light and darkness, that the moon's periodicity has chiefly influenced the history of the earth. Our bodily life is essentially periodic. It is dominated by the beatings of the heart, and the recurrence of breathing. The presupposition of periodicity is indeed fundamental to our very conception of life. We cannot imagine a course of nature in which, as events progressed, we should be unable to say: ``This has happened before.'' The whole conception of experience as a guide to conduct would be absent. Men would always find themselves in new situations possessing no substratum of identity with anything in past history. The very means of measuring time as a quantity would be absent. Events might still be recognized as occurring in a series, so that some were earlier and others later. But we now go beyond this bare recognition. We can not only say that \PageSep{166} \index{Time|EtSeq}% three events, $A$,~$B$,~$C$, occurred in this order, so that $A$~came before~$B$, and $B$~before~$C$; but also we can say that the length of time between the occurrences of $A$ and~$B$ was twice as long as that between $B$ and~$C$. Now, quantity of time is essentially dependent on observing the number of natural recurrences which have intervened. We may say that the length of time between $A$ and~$B$ was so many days, or so many months, or so many years, according to the type of recurrence to which we wish to appeal. Indeed, at the beginning of civilization, these three modes of measuring time were really distinct. It has been one of the first tasks of science among civilized or semi-civilized nations, to fuse them into one coherent measure. The full extent of this task must be grasped. It is necessary to determine, not merely what number of days (\eg~$365.25$\dots) go to some one year, but also previously to determine that the same number of days do go to the successive years. We can imagine a world in which periodicities exist, but such that no two are coherent. In some years there might be $200$~days and in others~$350$. The determination of the broad general consistency of the more important periodicities was the first step in natural science. This consistency arises from no abstract intuitive law of thought; it is merely an observed fact of nature \PageSep{167} guaranteed by experience. Indeed, so far is it from being a necessary law, that it is not even exactly true There are divergencies in every case. For some instances these divergencies are easily observed and are therefore immediately apparent. In other cases it requires the most refined observations and astronomical accuracy to make them apparent. Broadly speaking, all recurrences depending on living beings, such as the beatings of the heart, are subject in comparison with other recurrences to rapid variations. The great stable obvious recurrences---stable in the sense of mutually agreeing with great accuracy---are those depending on the motion of the earth as a whole, and on similar motions of the heavenly bodies. We therefore assume that these astronomical \index{Laws of Motion|EtSeq}% recurrences mark out equal intervals of time. But how are we to deal with their discrepancies which the refined observations of astronomy detect? Apparently we are reduced to the arbitrary assumption that one or other of these sets of phenomena marks out equal times---\eg\ that either all days are of equal length, or that all years are of equal length. This is not so: some assumptions must be made, but the assumption which underlies the whole procedure of the astronomers in determining the measure of time is that the laws of motion are exactly verified. \PageSep{168} Before explaining how this is done, it is interesting to observe that this relegation of the determination of the measure of time to the astronomers arises (as has been said) from the stable consistency of the recurrences with which they deal. If such a superior consistency had been noted among the recurrences characteristic of the human body, we should naturally have looked to the doctors of medicine for the regulation of our clocks. In considering how the laws of motion come into the matter, note that two inconsistent modes of measuring time will yield different variations of velocity to the same body. For example, suppose we define an hour as one twenty-fourth of a day, and take the case of a train running uniformly for two hours at the rate of twenty miles per hour. Now take a grossly inconsistent measure of time, and suppose that it makes the first hour to be twice as long as the second hour. Then, according to this other measure of duration, the time of the train's run is divided into two parts, during each of which it has traversed the same distance, namely, twenty miles; but the duration of the first part is twice as long as that of the second part. Hence the velocity of the train has not been uniform, and on the average the velocity during the second period is twice that during the first period. Thus the question as to \PageSep{169} whether the train has been running uniformly or not entirely depends on the standard of time which we adopt. Now, for all ordinary purposes of life on the earth, the various astronomical recurrences may be looked on as absolutely consistent; and, furthermore assuming their consistency, and thereby assuming the velocities and changes of velocities possessed by bodies, we find that the laws of motion, which have been considered above, are almost exactly verified. But only \emph{almost} exactly when we come to some of the astronomical phenomena. We find, however, that by assuming slightly different velocities for the rotations and motions of the planets and stars, the laws would be exactly verified. This assumption is then made; and we have, in fact thereby, adopted a measure of time, which is indeed defined by reference to the astronomical phenomena, but not so as to be consistent with the uniformity of any one of them. But the broad fact remains that the uniform flow of time on which so much is based, is itself dependent on the observation of periodic events. Even phenomena, which on the surface seem casual and exceptional, or, on the other hand, maintain themselves with a uniform persistency, may be due to the remote influence of periodicity. Take for example, the \PageSep{170} principle of resonance. Resonance arises \index{Resonance}% when two sets of connected circumstances have the same periodicities. It is a dynamical law that the small vibrations of all bodies when left to themselves take place in definite times characteristic of the body. Thus a pendulum with a small swing always vibrates in some definite time, characteristic of its shape and distribution of weight and length. A more complicated body may have many ways of vibrating; but each of its modes of vibration will have its own peculiar ``period.'' Those \index{Period}% periods of vibration of a body are called its ``free'' periods. Thus a pendulum has but one period of vibration, while a suspension bridge will have many. We get a musical instrument, like a violin string, when the periods of vibration are all simple submultiples of the longest; \ie~if $t$~seconds be the longest period, the others are $\frac{1}{2}t$, $\frac{1}{3}t$, and so on, where any of these smaller periods may be absent. Now, suppose we excite the vibrations of a body by a cause which is itself periodic; then, if the period of the cause is very nearly that of one of the periods of the body, that mode of vibration of the body is very violently excited; even although the magnitude of the exciting cause is small. This phenomenon is called ``resonance.'' The general reason is easy to understand. Any one wanting to upset a rocking stone will push ``in tune'' \PageSep{171} with the oscillations of the stone, so as always to secure a favourable moment for a push. If the pushes are out of tune, some increase the oscillations, but others check them. But when they are in tune, after a time all the pushes are favourable. The word ``resonance'' \index{Resonance}% comes from considerations of sound: but the phenomenon extends far beyond the region of sound. The laws of absorption and emission of light depend on it, the ``tuning'' of receivers for wireless telegraphy, the comparative importance of the influences of planets on each other's motion, the danger to a suspension bridge as troops march over it in step, and the excessive vibration of some ships under the rhythmical beat of their machinery at certain speeds. This coincidence of periodicities may produce steady phenomena when there is a constant association of the two periodic events, or it may produce violent and sudden outbursts when the association is fortuitous and temporary. Again, the characteristic and constant periods of vibration mentioned above are the underlying causes of what appear to us as steady excitements of our senses. We work for hours in a steady light, or we listen to a steady unvarying sound. But, if modern science be correct, this steadiness has no counterpart in nature. The steady light is due to the impact on the eye of a countless \PageSep{172} number of periodic waves in a vibrating ether, and the steady sound to similar waves in a vibrating air. It is not our purpose here to explain the theory of light or the theory of sound. We have said enough to make it evident that one of the first steps necessary to make mathematics a fit instrument for the investigation of Nature is that it should be able to express the essential periodicity of things. If we have grasped this, we can understand the importance of the mathematical conceptions which we have next to consider, namely, periodic functions. \PageSep{173} \Chapter{XIII}{Trigonometry} \First{Trigonometry} did not take its rise from \index{Trigonometry|EtSeq}% the general consideration of the periodicity of nature. In this respect its history is analogous to that of conic sections, which also had their origin in very particular ideas. Indeed, a comparison of the histories of the two sciences yields some very instructive analogies and contrasts. Trigonometry, like conic sections, had its origin among the Greeks. Its inventor was Hipparchus (born about 160~\BC), \index{Hipparchus}% a Greek astronomer, who made his observations at Rhodes. His services to astronomy were very great, and it left his \index{Astronomy}% hands a truly scientific subject with important results established, and the right method of progress indicated. Perhaps the invention of trigonometry was not the least of these services to the main science of his study. The next man who extended trigonometry was Ptolemy, the great Alexandrian astronomer, \index{Ptolemy}% whom we have already mentioned. We now \PageSep{174} see at once the great contrast between conic sections and trigonometry. The origin of trigonometry was practical; it was invented because it was necessary for astronomical research. The origin of conic sections was purely theoretical. The only reason for its initial study was the abstract interest of the ideas involved. Characteristically enough conic sections were invented about $150$~years earlier than trigonometry, during the very best period of Greek thought. But the importance of trigonometry, both to the theory and the application of mathematics, is only one of innumerable instances of the fruitful ideas which the general science has gained from its practical applications. We will try and make clear to ourselves what trigonometry is, and why it should be generated by the scientific study of astronomy. \index{Astronomy}% In the first place: What are the measurements which can be made by an astronomer? They are measurements of time and measurements of angles. The astronomer may adjust a telescope (for it is easier to discuss the familiar instrument of modern astronomers) so that it can only turn about a fixed axis pointing east and west; the result is that the telescope can only point to the south, with a greater or less elevation of direction, or, if turned round beyond the zenith, point to the north. This is the transit instrument, the \PageSep{175} great instrument for the exact measurement of the times at which stars are due south or due north. But indirectly this instrument measures angles. For when the time elapsed between the transits of two stars has been noted, by the assumption of the uniform rotation of the earth, we obtain the angle through which the earth has turned in that period of time. Again, by other instruments, the angle between two stars can be directly measured. For if $E$~is the eye of the astronomer, \Figure[2in]{22} and $EA$~and $EB$ are the directions in which the stars are seen, it is easy to devise instruments which shall measure the angle~$AEB$. Hence, when the astronomer is forming a survey of the heavens, he is, in fact, measuring angles so as to fix the relative directions of the stars and planets at any instant. Again, in the analogous problem of \PageSep{176} \index{Surveys|EtSeq}% \index{Triangle|EtSeq}% land-surveying, angles are the chief subject of measurements. The direct measurements of length are only rarely possible with any accuracy; rivers, houses, forests, mountains, and general irregularities of ground all get in the way. The survey of a whole country will depend only on one or two direct measurements of length, made with the greatest elaboration in selected places like Salisbury Plain. The main work of a survey is the measurement of angles. For example, $A$,~$B$, and~$C$ will be conspicuous points in the district \Figure[2in]{23} surveyed, say the tops of church towers. These points are visible each from the others. Then it is a very simple matter at~$A$ to measure the angle~$BAC$, and at~$B$ to measure the angle~$ABC$, and at~$C$ to measure the angle~$BCA$. Theoretically, it is only necessary to measure two of these angles; for, by a well-known proposition in geometry, the sum of the three angles of a triangle amounts to two \PageSep{177} right-angles, so that when two of the angles are known, the third can be deduced. It is better, however, in practice to measure all three, and then any small errors of observation can be checked. In the process of map-making a country is completely covered with triangles in this way. This process is called triangulation, and is the fundamental process \index{Triangulation}% in a survey. Now, when all the angles of a triangle are \index{Similarity|EtSeq}% known, the shape of the triangle is known---that is, the shape as distinguished from the size. We here come upon the great principle of geometrical similarity. The idea is very familiar to us in its practical applications. We are all familiar with the idea of a plan drawn to scale. Thus if the scale of a plan be an inch to a yard, a length of three inches in the plan means a length of three yards in the original. Also the shapes depicted in the plan are the shapes in the original, so that a right-angle in the original appears as a right-angle in the plan. Similarly in a map, which is only a plan of a country, the proportions of the lengths in the map are the proportions of the distances between the places indicated, and the directions in the map are the directions in the country. For example, if in the map one place is north-north-west of the other, so it is in reality; that is to say, in a map the angles are the same as in reality. \PageSep{178} \index{Scale of a Map}% Geometrical similarity may be defined thus: Two figures are similar (i)~if to any point in one figure a point in the other figure corresponds, so that to every line there is a corresponding line, and to every angle a corresponding angle, and (ii)~if the lengths of corresponding lines are in a fixed proportion, and the magnitudes of corresponding angles are the same. The fixed proportion of the lengths of corresponding lines in a map (or plan) and in the original is called the scale of the map. The scale should always be indicated on the margin of every map and plan. It has already been pointed out that two triangles whose angles are respectively equal are similar. Thus, if the two triangles \Figure{24} $ABC$ and~$DEF$ have the angles at $A$ and $D$ equal, and those at $B$ and~$E$, and those at $C$ and~$F$, then $DE$~is to~$AB$ in the same proportion \PageSep{179} as $EF$~is to~$BC$, and as $FD$~is to~$CA$. But it is not true of other figures that similarity is guaranteed by the mere equality of angles. Take for example, the familiar cases of a rectangle and a square. Let $ABCD$~be a square, and $ABEF$~be a rectangle. Then all the corresponding angles are equal. But \Figure[2.75in]{25} whereas the side~$AB$ of the square is equal to the side~$AB$ of the rectangle, the side~$BC$ of the square is about half the size of the side~$BE$ of the rectangle. Hence it is not true that the square $ABCD$ is similar to the rectangle $ABEF$. This peculiar property of the triangle, which is not shared by other rectilinear figures, makes it the fundamental figure in the theory of similarity. Hence in surveys, triangulation is the fundamental process; and hence also arises the word ``trigonometry,'' \PageSep{180} \index{Circle|EtSeq}% derived from the two Greek words \Foreign{trigonon} a triangle and \Foreign{metria} measurement. The fundamental question from which trigonometry arose is this: Given the magnitudes of the angles of a triangle, what can be stated as to the relative magnitudes of the sides. Note that we say ``\emph{relative} magnitudes of the sides,'' since by the theory of similarity it is only the proportions of the sides which are known. In order to answer this question, certain functions of the magnitudes of an angle, considered as the argument, are introduced. In their origin these functions were got at by considering a right-angled triangle, and the magnitude of the angle was defined by the length of the arc of a circle. In modern elementary books, the fundamental position of the arc of the circle as defining the magnitude of the angle has been pushed somewhat to the background, not to the advantage either of theory or clearness of explanation. It must first be noticed that, in relation to similarity, the circle holds the same fundamental position among curvilinear figures, as does the triangle among rectilinear figures. Any two circles are similar figures; they only differ in scale. The lengths of the circumferences of two circles, such as $APA'$ and $A_{1} P_{1} A_{1}'$ in the \Fig[fig.]{26} are in proportion to the lengths of their radii. Furthermore, if the two circles have the same \PageSep{181} centre~$O$, as do the two circles in \Fig[fig.]{26}, then the arcs $AP$ and $A_{1} P_{1}$ intercepted by the arms of any angle~$AOP$, are also in proportion to their radii. Hence the ratio of the \Figure{26} length of the arc~$AP$ to the length of the radius~$OP$, that is $\dfrac{\text{arc } AP}{\text{radius } OP}$ is a number which is quite independent of the length~$OP$, and is the same as the fraction $\dfrac{\text{arc } A_{1} P_{1}}{\text{radius } OP_{1}}$. This fraction of ``arc divided by radius'' is the proper theoretical way to measure the magnitude of \PageSep{182} \index{Cosine|EtSeq}% \index{Sine|EtSeq}% an angle; for it is dependent on no arbitrary unit of length, and on no arbitrary way of dividing up any arbitrarily assumed angle, such as a right-angle. Thus the fraction~$\dfrac{AP}{OA}$ represents the magnitude of the angle~$AOP$. Now draw $PM$ perpendicularly to~$OA$. Then the Greek mathematicians called the line~$PM$ the sine of the arc~$AP$, and the line~$OM$ the cosine of the arc~$AP$. They were well aware that the importance of the relations of these various lines to each other was dependent on the theory of similarity which we have just expounded. But they did not make their definitions express the properties which arise from this theory. Also they had not in their heads the modern general ideas respecting functions as correlating pairs of variable numbers, nor in fact were they aware of any modern conception of algebra and algebraic analysis. Accordingly, it was natural to them to think merely of the relations between certain lines in a diagram. For us the case is different: we wish to embody our more powerful ideas. Hence, in modern mathematics, instead of considering the arc~$AP$, we consider the fraction~$\dfrac{AP}{OP}$, which is a number the same for all lengths of~$OP$; and, instead of considering the lines $PM$ and~$OM$, we consider \PageSep{183} the fractions $\dfrac{PM}{OP}$ and~$\dfrac{OM}{OP}$, which again are numbers not dependent on the length of~$OP$, \ie~not dependent on the scale of our diagrams. Then we define the number $\dfrac{PM}{OP}$ to be the \emph{sine} of the number $\dfrac{PA}{OP}$, and the number $\dfrac{OM}{OP}$ to be the \emph{cosine} of the number $\dfrac{PA}{OP}$. These fractional forms are clumsy to print; so let us put $u$ for the fraction~$\dfrac{AP}{OP}$, which represents the magnitude of the angle~$AOP$, and put $v$ for the fraction~$\dfrac{PM}{OM}$, and $w$~for the fraction~$\dfrac{OM}{OP}$. Then $u$,~$v$,~$w$, are numbers, and, since we are talking of \emph{any} angle~$AOP$, they are variable numbers. But a correlation exists between their magnitudes, so that when $u$ (\ie\ the angle~$AOP$) is given the magnitudes of $v$~and~$w$ are definitely determined. Hence $v$~and~$w$ are functions of the argument~$u$. We have called $v$ the \emph{sine} of~$u$, and $w$ the \emph{cosine} of~$u$. We wish to adapt the general functional notation $y = f(x)$ to these special cases: so in modern mathematics %[** TN: Function names italicized in the original] we write \Chg{$\sin$}{``$\sin$''} for~``$f$'' when we want to \PageSep{184} indicate the special function of ``sine,'' and ``$\cos$'' for~``$f$'' when we want to indicate the special function of ``cosine.'' Thus, with the above meanings for $u$,~$v$,~$w$, we get \[ v = \sin u,\quad\text{and}\quad w = \cos u, \] where the brackets surrounding the~$x$ in~$f(x)$ are omitted for the special functions. The meaning of these functions $\sin$ and $\cos$ as correlating the pairs of numbers $u$~and~$v$, and $u$~and~$w$ is, that the functional relations are to be found by constructing (\cf\ \Fig[fig.]{26}) an angle~$AOP$, whose measure ``$AP$~divided by~$OP$'' is equal to~$u$, and that then $v$~is the number given by ``$PM$~divided by~$OP$'' and $w$~is the number given by ``$OM$~divided by~$OP$.'' It is evident that without some further definitions we shall get into difficulties when the number~$u$ is taken too large. For then the arc~$AP$ may be greater than one-quarter of the circumference of the circle, and the point~$M$ (\cf\ figs.\ \FigNum{26} and~\FigNum{27}) may fall between $O$ and~$A'$ and not between $O$ and~$A$. Also $P$~may be below the line~$AOA'$ and not above it as in \Fig[fig.]{26}. In order to get over this difficulty we have recourse to the ideas and conventions of coordinate geometry in making our complete definitions of the sine and cosine. Let one arm~$OA$ of the angle be the axis~$OX$, and produce the axis backwards to obtain its negative part~$OX'$. Draw the \PageSep{185} other axis~$YOY'$ perpendicular to it. Let any point~$P$ at a distance~$r$ from~$O$ have coordinates $x$ and~$y$. These coordinates are both positive in the first ``quadrant'' of the plan, \eg\ the coordinates $x$ and~$y$ of~$P$ \Figure{27} in \Fig[fig.]{27}. In the other quadrants, either one or both of the coordinates are negative, for example, $x'$~and~$y$ for~$P'$, and $x'$ and~$y'$ for~$P''$, and $x$ and~$y'$ for~$P'''$ in \Fig[fig.]{27}, where $x'$ and~$y'$ are both negative numbers. The positive angle~$POA$ is the arc~$AP$ divided by~$r$, its sine is~$\dfrac{y}{r}$ and its cosine is~$\dfrac{x}{r}$; the positive \PageSep{186} angle~$AOP'$ is the arc~$ABP'$ divided by~$r$, its sine is~$\dfrac{y}{r}$ and cosine~$\dfrac{x'}{r}$; the positive angle~$AOP''$ is the arc $ABA'P''$ divided by~$r$, its sine is~$\dfrac{y'}{r}$ and its cosine is~$\dfrac{x'}{r}$; the positive angle~$AOP'''$ is the arc $ABA'B'P'''$ divided by~$r$, its sine is~$\dfrac{y'}{r}$ and its cosine is~$\dfrac{x}{r}$. But even now we have not gone far enough. For suppose we choose~$u$ to be a number greater than the ratio of the whole circumference of the circle to its radius. Owing to the similarity of all circles this ratio is the same for all circles. It is always denoted in mathematics by the symbol~$2\pi$, where $\pi$~is the Greek form of the letter~\Foreign{p} and its name in the Greek alphabet is ``pi.'' It can be proved that $\pi$~is an incommensurable number, and that therefore its value cannot be expressed by any fraction, or by any terminating or recurring decimal. Its value to a few decimal places is~$3.14159$; for many purposes a sufficiently accurate approximate value is~$\dfrac{22}{7}$. Mathematicians can easily calculate~$\pi$ to any degree of accuracy required, just as~$\sqrt{2}$ can be so calculated. Its value has been actually given to $707$~places of \PageSep{187} decimals. Such elaboration of calculation is merely a curiosity, and of no practical or theoretical interest. The accurate determination of~$\pi$ is one of the two parts of the famous problem of squaring the circle. \index{Squaring the Circle}% The other part of the problem is, by the theoretical methods of pure geometry to describe a straight line equal in length to the circumference. Both parts of the problem are now known to be impossible; and the insoluble problem has now lost all special practical or theoretical interest, having become absorbed in wider ideas. After this digression on the value of~$\pi$, we now return to the question of the general definition of the magnitude of an angle, so as to be able to produce an angle corresponding to any value~$u$. Suppose a moving point,~$Q$, to start from~$A$ on~$OX$ (\Chg{cf.}{\cf}\ \Fig[fig.]{27}), and to rotate in the positive direction (anti-clockwise, in the figure considered) round the circumference of the circle for any number of times, finally resting at any point, \eg~at $P$ or~$P'$ or~$P''$ or~$P'''$. Then the total length of the curvilinear circular path traversed, divided by the radius of the circle,~$r$, is the generalized definition of a positive angle of \emph{any} size. Let $x$,~$y$ be the coordinates of the point in which the point~$Q$ rests, \ie~in one of the four alternative positions mentioned in \Fig[fig.]{27}; $x$~and~$y$ (as here used) will either \Typo{}{be} $x$~and~$y$, or $x'$~and~$y$, or $x'$~and~$y'$, or $x$~and~$y'$. \PageSep{188} Then the sign of this generalized angle is~$\dfrac{y}{r}$ and its cosine is~$\dfrac{x}{r}$. With these definitions the functional relations $v = \sin u$ and $w = \cos u$, are at last defined for all positive real values of~$u$. For negative values of~$u$ we simply take rotation of~$Q$ in the opposite (clockwise) direction; but it is not worth our while to elaborate further on this point, now that the general method of procedure has been explained. These functions of sine and cosine, as thus defined, enable us to deal with the problems concerning the triangle from which Trigonometry took its rise. But we are now in a position to relate Trigonometry to the wider idea of Periodicity of which the importance \index{Periodicity}% was explained in the last chapter. It is easy to see that the functions $\sin u$ and $\cos u$ are periodic functions of~$u$. For consider the position,~$P$ (in \Fig[fig.]{27}), of a moving point,~$Q$, which has started from~$A$ and revolved round the circle. This position,~$P$, marks the angles $\dfrac{\text{arc } AP}{r}$, and $2\pi + \dfrac{\text{arc } AP}{r}$, and $4\pi + \dfrac{\text{arc } AP}{r}$, and $6\pi + \dfrac{\text{arc } AP}{r}$, and so on indefinitely. Now, all these angles have the same sine and cosine, namely, $\dfrac{y}{r}$~and~$\dfrac{x}{r}$. Hence it is easy to see that, \PageSep{189} \index{Period|EtSeq}% if $u$ be chosen to have any value, the arguments $u$~and~$2\pi + u$, and $4\pi + u$, and $6\pi + u$, and $8\pi + u$ and so on indefinitely, have all the same values for the corresponding sines and cosines. In other words, \begin{alignat*}{4} \sin u &= \sin(2\pi + u) &&= \sin(4\pi + u) &&= \sin(6\pi + u) &&= \text{etc.}; \\ \cos u &= \cos(2\pi + u) &&= \cos(4\pi + u) &&= \cos(6\pi + u) &&= \text{etc.} \end{alignat*} This fact is expressed by saying that $\sin u$ and $\cos u$ are periodic functions with their period equal to~$2\pi$. The graph of the function $y = \sin x$ (notice that we now abandon $v$~and~$u$ for the more familiar $y$~and~$x$) is shown in \Fig[fig.]{28}. We take on the axis of~$x$ any arbitrary length at pleasure to represent the number~$\pi$, and on the axis of~$y$ any arbitrary length at pleasure to represent the number~$1$. The numerical values of the sine and cosine can never exceed unity. The recurrence of the figure after periods of~$2\pi$ will be noticed. This graph represents the simplest style of periodic function, out of which all others are constructed. The cosine gives nothing fundamentally different from the sine. For it is easy to prove that $\cos x = \sin(x + \dfrac{\pi}{2})$; hence it can be seen that the graph of $\cos x$ is simply \Fig[fig.]{28} modified by \PageSep{190} drawing the axis of~$OY$ through the point on~$OX$ marked~$\dfrac{\pi}{2}$, instead of drawing it in its actual position on the figure. It is easy to construct a `sine' function in \Figure{28} which the period has any assigned value~$a$. For we have only to write \[ y = \sin \frac{2\pi x}{a}, \] and then \[ \sin \frac{2\pi (x + a)}{a} %[** TN: Changed curly braces to parentheses] = \sin \left(\frac{2\pi x}{a} + 2\pi\right) = \sin \frac{2\pi x}{a}. \] Thus the period of this new function is now~$a$. Let us now give a general definition of what \PageSep{191} we mean by a periodic function. The function~$f(x)$ is periodic, with the period~$a$, if (i)~for \emph{any} value of~$x$ we have $f(x) = f(x + a)$, and (ii)~there is no number~$b$ smaller than~$a$ such that for \emph{any} value of~$x$, $f(x) = f(x + b)$. The second clause is put into the definition because when we have $\sin \dfrac{2\pi x}{a}$, it is not only periodic in the period~$a$, but also in the periods $2a$ and~$3a$, and so on; this arises since \[ \sin \frac{2\pi (x + 3a)}{a} = \sin \left(\frac{2\pi x}{a} + 6\pi\right) = \sin \frac{2\pi x}{a}. \] So it is the smallest period which we want to get hold of and call \emph{the} period of the function. The greater part of the abstract theory of periodic functions and the whole of the applications of the theory to Physical Science are dominated by an important theorem called Fourier's Theorem; namely that, if $f(x)$ be a \index{Fourier's Theorem}% periodic function with the period~$a$ and if $f(x)$ also satisfies certain conditions, which practically are always presupposed in functions suggested by natural phenomena, then $f(x)$ can be written as the sum of a set of terms in the form\Pagelabel{191} \begin{multline*} c_{0} + c_{1} \sin \left(\frac{2\pi x}{a} + e_{1}\right) + c_{2} \sin \left(\frac{4\pi x}{a} + e_{2}\right) \\ + c_{3} \sin \left(\frac{6\pi x}{a} + e_{3}\right) + \text{etc.} \end{multline*} \PageSep{192} In this formula $c_{0}$,~$c_{1}$, $c_{2}$, $c_{3}$,~etc., and also $e_{1}$,~$e_{2}$, $e_{3}$,~etc., are constants, chosen so as to suit the particular function. Again we have to ask, How many terms have to be chosen? And here a new difficulty arises: for we can prove that, though in some particular cases a definite number will do, yet in general all we can do is to approximate as closely as we like to the value of the function by taking more and more terms. This process of gradual approximation brings us to the consideration of the theory of infinite series, an essential part of mathematical theory which we will consider in the next chapter. The above method of expressing a periodic \index{Harmonic Analysis}% function as a sum of sines is called the ``harmonic analysis'' of the function. For example, at any point on the sea coast the tides rise and fall periodically. Thus at a point near the Straits of Dover there will be two daily tides due to the rotation of the earth. The daily rise and fall of the tides are complicated by the fact that there are two tidal waves, one coming up the English Channel, and the other which has swept round the North of Scotland, and has then come southward down the North Sea. Again some high tides are higher than others: this is due to the fact that the Sun has also a tide-generating influence as well as the Moon. In this way monthly and other periods are introduced. \PageSep{193} We leave out of account the exceptional influence of winds which cannot be foreseen. The general problem of the harmonic analysis of the tides is to find sets of terms like those in the expression on \Pageref[page]{191} above, such that each set will give with approximate accuracy the contribution of the tide-generating influences of one ``period'' to the height of the tide at any instant. The argument~$x$ will therefore be the \emph{time} reckoned from any convenient commencement. Again, the motion of vibration of a violin string is submitted to a similar harmonic analysis, and so are the vibrations of the ether and the air, corresponding respectively to waves of light and waves of sound. We are here in the presence of one of the fundamental processes of mathematical physics---namely, nothing less than its general method of dealing with the great natural fact of Periodicity. \PageSep{194} \Chapter{XIV}{Series} \First{No} part of Mathematics suffers more from \index{Order|EtSeq}% \index{Series|EtSeq}% the triviality of its initial presentation to beginners than the great subject of series. Two minor examples of series, namely arithmetic and geometric series, are considered; these examples are important because they are the simplest examples of an important general theory. But the general ideas are never disclosed; and thus the examples, which exemplify nothing, are reduced to silly trivialities. The general mathematical idea of a series is that of a set of things ranged in order, that is, in sequence; This meaning is accurately represented in the common use of the term. Consider for example, the series of English Prime Ministers during the nineteenth century, arranged in the order of their first tenure of that office within the century. The series commences with William Pitt, and ends with \index{Pitt, William}% \index{Rosebery, Lord}% Lord Rosebery, who, appropriately enough, is the biographer of the first member. We \PageSep{195} might have considered other serial orders for the arrangement of these men; for example, according to their height or their weight. These other suggested orders strike us as trivial in connection with Prime Ministers, and would not naturally occur to the mind; but abstractly they are just as good orders as any other. When one order among terms is very much more important or more obvious than other orders, it is often spoken of as \emph{the} order of those terms. Thus \emph{the} order of the integers would always be taken to mean their order as arranged in order of magnitude. But of course there is an indefinite number of other ways of arranging them. When the number of things considered is finite, the number of ways of arranging them in order is called the number of their permutations. The number of permutations of a set of $n$~things, where $n$~is some finite integer, is \[ n × (n - 1) × (n - 2) × (n - 3) × \dots × 4 × 3 × 2 × 1\Add{,} \] that is to say, it is the product of the first $n$ integers; this product is so important in mathematics that a special symbolism, is used for it, and it is always written~`$n!$\Add{.}' Thus, $2! = 2 × 1 = 2$, and $3! = 3 × 2 × 1 = 6$, and $4! = 4 × 3 × 2 × 1 = 24$, and $5! = 5 × 4 × 3 × 2 × 1 = 120$. As $n$~increases, the value of~$n!$ increases very quickly; thus $100!$~is a hundred times as large as~$99!$\Add{.} \PageSep{196} It is easy to verify in the case of small values of~$n$ that $n!$ is the number of ways of arranging $n$~things in order. Thus consider two things $a$ and~$b$; these are capable of the two orders $ab$ and~$ba$, and $2! = 2$. Again, take three things $a$,~$b$, and~$c$; these are capable of the six orders, $abc$, $acb$, $bac$, $bca$, $cab$, $cba$, and $3! = 6$. Similarly for the twenty-four orders in which four things $a$,~$b$,~$c$, and~$d$, can be arranged. When we come to the infinite sets of things---like \index{Order, Type of}% the sets of all the integers, or all the fractions, or all the real numbers for instance---we come at once upon the complications of the theory of order-types. This subject was touched upon in \ChapRef{VI}. in considering the possible orders of the integers, and of the fractions, and of the real numbers. The whole question of order-types forms a comparatively new branch of mathematics of great importance. We shall not consider it any further. All the infinite series which we consider now are of the same order-type as the integers arranged in ascending order of magnitude, namely, with a first term, and such that each term has a couple of next-door neighbours, one on either side, with the exception of the first term which has, of course, only one next-door neighbour. Thus, if $m$~be any integer (not zero), there will be always an $m$th~term. A series with a finite \PageSep{197} number of terms (say $n$~terms) has the same characteristics as far as next-door neighbours are concerned as an infinite series; it only differs from infinite series in having a last term, namely, the~$n$th. The important thing to do with a series of numbers---using for the future ``series'' in the restricted sense which has just been mentioned---is to add its successive terms together. Thus if $u_{1}$,~$u_{2}$, $u_{3}$,~\dots\Add{,} $u_{n}$,~\dots\ are respectively the $1$st,~$2$nd, $3$rd, $4$th,~\dots\Add{,} $n$th,~\dots\ terms of a series of numbers, we form successively the series $u_{1}$, $u_{1} + u_{2}$, $u_{1} + u_{2} + u_{3}$, $u_{1} + u_{2} + u_{3} + u_{4}$, and so on; thus the sum of the $1$st $n$~terms may be written\Typo{.}{} \[ u_{1} + u_{2} + u_{3} + \dots + u_{n}. \] If the series has only a finite number of \index{Approximation|EtSeq}% terms, we come at last in this way to the sum of the whole series of terms. But, if the series has an infinite number of terms, this process of successively forming the sums of the terms never terminates; and in this sense there is no such thing as the sum of an infinite series. But why is it important successively to add the terms of a series in this way? The answer is that we are here symbolizing the fundamental mental process of approximation. This is a process which has significance far \PageSep{198} beyond the regions of mathematics. Our limited intellects cannot deal with complicated material all at once, and our method of arrangement is that of approximation. The statesman in framing his speech puts the dominating issues first and lets the details fall naturally into their subordinate places. There is, of course, the converse artistic method of preparing the imagination by the presentation of subordinate or special details, and then gradually rising to a crisis. In either way the process is one of gradual summation of effects; and this is exactly what is done by the successive summation of the terms of a series. Our ordinary method of stating numbers is such a process of gradual summation, at least, in the case of large numbers. Thus $568,213$ presents itself to the mind as\Add{:}--- \[ 500,000 + 60,000 + 8,000 + 200 + 10 + 3\Add{.} \] In the case of decimal fractions this is so more avowedly. Thus $3.14159$ is\Add{:}--- \[ 3 + \tfrac{1}{10} + \tfrac{4}{100} + \tfrac{1}{1000} + \tfrac{5}{10000} + \tfrac{9}{100000}\Add{.} \] Also, $3$ and~$3 + \frac{1}{10}$, and $3 + \tfrac{1}{10} + \tfrac{4}{100}$, and $3 + \tfrac{1}{10} + \tfrac{4}{100} + \tfrac{1}{1000}$, and $3 + \tfrac{1}{10} + \tfrac{4}{100} + \tfrac{1}{1000} + \tfrac{5}{10000}$ are successive approximations to the complete result $3.14159$. If we read $568,213$ backwards from right to left, starting with the $3$~units, \PageSep{199} we read it in the artistic way, gradually preparing the mind for the crisis of~$500,000$. The ordinary process of numerical multiplication proceeds by means of the summation of a series, Consider the computation \[ \begin{array}{*{6}{@{}c@{}}} & & &3&4&2 \\ & & &6&5&8 \\ \cline{4-6} \Strut & &2&7&3&6 \\ &1&7&1&0& \\ 2&0&5&2& & \\ \cline{1-6} \Strut 2&2&5&0&3&6 \end{array} \] Hence the three lines to be added form a series of which the first term is the upper line. This series follows the artistic method of presenting the most important term last, not from any feeling for art, but because of the convenience gained by keeping a firm hold on the units' place, thus enabling us to omit some~$0$'s, formally necessary. But when we approximate by gradually \index{Limit of a Series|EtSeq}% adding the successive terms of an infinite series, what are we approximating to? The difficulty is that the series has no ``sum'' in the straightforward sense of the word, because the operation of adding together its terms can never be completed. The answer is that we are approximating to the \emph{limit} of the summation of the series, and we must now \PageSep{200} proceed to explain what the ``limit'' of a series is. The summation of a series approximates to a limit when the sum of any number of its terms, provided the number be large enough, is as nearly equal to the limit as you care to approach. But this description of the meaning of approximating to a limit evidently will not stand the vigorous scrutiny of modern mathematics. What is meant by \emph{large enough}, and by \emph{nearly equal}, and by \emph{care to approach}? All these vague phrases must be explained in terms of the simple abstract ideas which alone are admitted into pure mathematics. Let the successive terms of the series be $u_{1}$,~$u_{2}$, $u_{3}$, $u_{4}$,~\dots, $u_{n}$, etc., so that $u_{n}$~is the $n$th~term of the series. Also let $s_{n}$ be the sum of the $1$st $n$~terms, whatever $n$~may be. So that\Add{:}--- \begin{gather*} s_{1} = u_{1},\quad s_{2} = u_{1} + u_{2},\quad s_{3} = u_{1} + u_{2} + u_{3},\quad\text{and} \\ s_{n} = u_{1} + u_{2} + u_{3} + \dots + u_{n}. \end{gather*} Then the terms $s_{1}$,~$s_{2}$, $s_{3}$,~\dots\Add{,} $s_{n}$,~\dots\ form a new series, and the formation of this series is the process of summation of the original series. Then the ``approximation'' of the \emph{summation} of the original series to a ``limit'' means the ``approximation of the \emph{terms} of this new series to a limit.'' And we have \PageSep{201} now to explain what we mean by the approximation to a limit of the terms of a series. Now, remembering the definition (given in \ChapRef[chapter]{XII}.)\ of a \emph{standard of approximation}, \index{Standard of Approximation|EtSeq}% \index{Sum to Infinity|EtSeq}% the idea of a limit means this: $l$~is the limit of the terms of the series $s_{1}$,~$s_{2}$, $s_{3}$,~\dots\Add{,} $s_{n}$,~\dots, if, corresponding to each real number~$k$, taken as a standard of approximation, a term~$s_{n}$ of the series can be found so that all succeeding terms (\ie\ $s_{n+1}$, $s_{n+2}$, etc.)\ approximate to~$l$ within that standard of approximation. If another smaller standard~$k^{1}$ be chosen, the term~$s_{n}$ may be too early in the series, and a later term~$s_{m}$ with the above property will then be found. If this property holds, it is evident that as you go along to series $s_{1}$,~$s_{2}$, $s_{3}$,~\dots, $s_{n}$,~\dots\ from left to right, after a time you come to terms \emph{all} of which are nearer to~$l$ than any number which you may like to assign. In other words you approximate to~$l$ as closely as you like. The close connection of this definition of the limit of a series with the definition of a continuous function given in \ChapRef[chapter]{XI}.\ will be immediately perceived. Then coming back to the original series $u_{1}$,~$u_{2}$, $u_{3}$,~\dots, $u_{n}$,~\dots, the limit of the terms of the series $s_{1}$,~$s_{2}$, $s_{3}$,~\dots, $s_{n}$,~\dots, is called the ``sum to infinity'' of the original series. But it is evident that this use of the word \PageSep{202} ``sum'' is very artificial, and we must not assume the analogous properties to those of the ordinary sum of a finite number of terms without some special investigation. Let us look at an example of a ``sum to infinity.'' Consider the recurring decimal $.1111\dots$. This decimal is merely a way of symbolizing the ``sum to infinity'' of the series $.1$, $.01$, $.001$, $.0001$, etc. The corresponding series found by summation is $s_{1} = .1$, $s_{2} = .11$, $s_{3} = .111$, $s_{4} = .1111$, etc. The limit of the terms of this series is~$\frac{1}{9}$; this is easy to see by simple division, for \[ \tfrac{1}{9} = .1 + \tfrac{1}{90} = .11 + \tfrac{1}{900} = .111 + \tfrac{1}{9000} = \text{etc.} \] Hence, if $\frac{3}{17}$ is given (the $k$ of the definition), $.1$~and \emph{all} succeeding terms differ from~$\frac{1}{9}$ by less than~$\frac{3}{17}$; if $\frac{1}{1000}$ is given (another choice for the $k$ of the definition), $.111$ and all succeeding terms differ from~$\frac{1}{9}$ by less than~$\frac{1}{1000}$; and so on, whatever choice for~$k$ be made. It is evident that nothing that has been said gives the slightest idea as to how the ``sum to infinity'' of a series is to be found. We have merely stated the conditions which such a number is to satisfy. Indeed, a general method for finding in all cases the sum to infinity of a series is intrinsically out of the question, for the simple reason that such a ``sum,'' as here defined, does not always exist. Series which possess a sum to \PageSep{203} \index{Convergent|EtSeq}% \index{Divergent|EtSeq}% infinity are called \emph{convergent}, and those which do not possess a sum to infinity are called \emph{divergent}. An obvious example of a divergent series is $1$,~$2$, $3$,~\dots, $n$~\dots\Add{,} \ie~the series of integers in their order of magnitude. For whatever number~$l$ you try to take as its sum to infinity, and whatever standard of approximation~$k$ you choose, by taking enough terms of the series you can always make their sum differ from~$l$ by more than~$k$. Again, another example of a divergent series is $1$,~$1$, $1$,~etc., \ie~the series of which each term is equal to~$1$. Then the sum of $n$~terms is~$n$, and this sum grows without limit as $n$~increases. Again, another example of a divergent series is $1$,~$-1$, $1$,~$-1$, $1$,~$-1$, etc., \ie~the series in which the terms are alternately $1$ and~$-1$. The sum of an odd number of terms is~$1$, and of an even number of terms is~$0$. Hence the terms of the series $s_{1}$,~$s_{2}$, $s_{3}$,~\dots\Add{,} $s_{n}$,~\dots\ do not approximate to a limit, although they do not increase without limit. It is tempting to suppose that the condition for $u_{1}$,~$u_{2}$,~\dots\Add{,} $u_{n}$,~\dots\ to have a sum to infinity is that $u_{n}$~should decrease indefinitely as $n$~increases. Mathematics would be a much easier science than it is, if this were the case. Unfortunately the supposition is not true. \PageSep{204} For example the series \[ 1,\quad \frac{1}{2},\quad \frac{1}{3},\quad \frac{1}{4},\ \dots,\quad \frac{1}{n},\ \dots \] is divergent. It is easy to see that this is the case; for consider the sum of $n$~terms %[** TN: "(n + 1)^{th} term" in the original beginning at the $(n + 1)$th term. These $n$~terms are $\dfrac{1}{n + 1}$, $\dfrac{1}{n + 2}$, $\dfrac{1}{n + 3}$,~\dots\Add{,} $\dfrac{1}{2n}$: there are $n$~of them and $\dfrac{1}{2n}$~is the least among them. Hence their sum is greater than $n$~times~$\dfrac{1}{2n}$, \ie~is greater than~$\dfrac{1}{2}$. Now, without altering the sum to infinity, if it exist, we can add together neighbouring terms, and obtain the series \[ 1,\quad \tfrac{1}{2},\quad \tfrac{1}{3} + \tfrac{1}{4},\quad \tfrac{1}{5} + \tfrac{1}{6} + \tfrac{1}{7} + \tfrac{1}{8},\quad \text{etc.}, \] that is, by what has been said above, a series whose terms after the~$2$nd are greater than those of the series, \[ 1,\quad \tfrac{1}{2},\quad \tfrac{1}{2},\quad \tfrac{1}{2},\quad \text{etc.}, \] where all the terms after the first are equal. But this series is divergent. Hence the original series is divergent.\footnote {\Chg{Cf.}{\Cf}\ Note~C, \Pageref{noteC}.\Pagelabel{204}} This question of divergency shows how careful we must be in arguing from the properties \PageSep{205} of the sum of a finite number of terms to that of the sum of an infinite series. For the most elementary property of a finite number of terms is that of course they possess a sum: but even this fundamental property is not necessarily possessed by an infinite series. This caution merely states that we must not be misled by the suggestion of the technical term ``\emph{sum} of an infinite series.'' It is usual to indicate the sum of the infinite series \[ u_{1},\quad u_{2},\quad u_{3},\ \dots\Add{,}\quad u_{n}\Add{,}\ \dots \] by \[ u_{1} + u_{2} + u_{3} + \dots + u_{n} + \dots\Add{.} \] We now pass on to a generalization of the idea of a series, which mathematics, true to its method, makes by use of the variable. Hitherto, we have only contemplated series in which each definite term was a definite number. But equally well we can generalize, and make each term to be some mathematical expression containing a variable~$x$. Thus we may consider the series $1$,~$x$, $x^{2}$, $x^{3}$,~\dots, $x^{n}$,~\dots, and the series \[ x,\quad \frac{x^{2}}{2},\quad \frac{x^{3}}{3},\ \dots,\quad \frac{x^{n}}{n},\ \dots\Add{.} \] In order to symbolize the general idea of any such function, conceive of a function of~$x$, $f_{n}(x)$~say, which involves in its formation a variable integer~$n$, then, by giving~$n$ the \PageSep{206} values $1$,~$2$, $3$,~etc., in succession, we get the series \[ f_{1}(x),\quad f_{2}(x),\quad f_{3}(x),\ \dots,\quad f_{n}(x),\dots\Add{.} \] Such a series may be convergent for some values of~$x$ and divergent for others. It is, in fact, rather rare to find a series involving a variable~$x$ which is convergent for all values of~$x$,---at least in any particular instance it is very unsafe to assume that this is the case. For example, let us examine the simplest of all instances, namely, the ``geometrical'' \index{Geometrical Series|EtSeq}% series \[ 1,\quad x,\quad x^{2},\quad x^{3},\ \dots,\quad x^{n},\ \dots\Add{.} \] The sum of $n$~terms is given by \[ s_{n} = 1 + x + x^{2} + x^{3} + \dots + x^{n}. \] Now multiply both sides by~$x$ and we get \[ xs_{n} = x + x^{2} + x^{3} + x^{4} + \dots + x^{n} + x^{n+1}\Add{.} \] Now subtract the last line from the upper line and we get \[ s_{n}(1 - x) = s_{n} - xs_{n} = 1 - x^{n+1}, \] and hence (if $x$~be not equal to~$1$) \[ s_{n} = \frac{1 - x^{n+1}}{1 - x} = \frac{1}{1 - x} - \frac{x^{n+1}}{1 - x}\Add{.} \] Now if $x$~be numerically less than~$1$, for sufficiently large values of~$n$, $\dfrac{x^{n+1}}{1 - x}$~is always numerically \PageSep{207} less than~$k$, however $k$~be chosen. Thus, if $x$~be numerically less than~$1$, the series $1$,~$x$, $x^{2}$,~\dots\Add{,} $x^{n}$,~\dots\ is convergent, and $\dfrac{1}{1 - x}$~is its limit. This statement is symbolized by \[ \frac{1}{1 - x} = 1 + x + x^{2} + \dots + x^{n} + \dots,\quad (-1 < x < 1). \] But if $x$~is numerically greater than~$1$, or numerically equal to~$1$, the series is divergent. In other words, if $x$~lie between $-1$ and~$+1$, the series is convergent; but if $x$~be equal to~$-1$ or~$+1$, or if $x$~lie outside the interval $-1$~to~$+1$, then the series is divergent. Thus the series is convergent at all ``points'' within the interval $-1$~to~$+1$, exclusive of the end points. At this stage of our enquiry another question arises. Suppose that the series \[ f_{1}(x) + f_{2}(x) + f_{3}(x) + \dots + f_{n}(x) + \dots \] is convergent for all values of~$x$ lying within the interval $a$~to~$b$, \ie~the series is convergent for any value of~$x$ which is greater than~$a$ and less than~$b$. Also, suppose we want to be sure that in approximating to the limit we add together enough terms to come within some standard of approximation~$k$. Can we always state some number of terms, say~$n$, such that, if we take $n$~or more terms to form the sum, then \emph{whatever} value $x$~has \PageSep{208} within the interval we have satisfied the desired standard of approximation? Sometimes we can and sometimes we cannot \index{Non-Uniform Convergence|EtSeq}% \index{Uniform Convergence|EtSeq}% do this for each value of~$k$. When we can, the series is called uniformly convergent throughout the interval, and when we cannot do so, the series is called non-uniformly convergent throughout the interval. It makes a great difference to the properties of a series whether it is or is not uniformly convergent through an interval. Let us illustrate the matter by the simplest example and the simplest numbers. Consider the geometric series \[ 1 + x + x^{2} + x^{3} + \dots + x^{n} + \dots\Add{.} \] It is convergent throughout the interval $-1$~to~$+1$, excluding the end values $x = ±1$. But it is not uniformly convergent throughout this interval. For if $s_{n}(x)$~be the sum of $n$~terms, we have proved that the difference between $s_{n}(x)$ and the limit~$\dfrac{1}{1 - x}$ is~$\dfrac{x^{n+1}}{1 - x}$. Now suppose $n$~be any given number of terms, say~$20$, and let $k$~be any assigned standard of approximation, say~$.001$. Then, by taking $x$~near enough to~$+1$ or near enough to~$-1$, we can make the numerical value of~$\dfrac{x^{21}}{1 - x}$ to be greater than~$.001$. Thus $20$~terms will \PageSep{209} not do over the whole interval, though it is more than enough over some parts of it. The same reasoning can be applied whatever other number we take instead of~$20$, and whatever standard of approximation instead of~$.001$. Hence the geometric series $1 + x + x^{2} + x^{3} + \dots + x^{n} + \dots$ is non-uniformly convergent over its \emph{whole} interval of convergence $-1$~to~$+1$. But if we take any smaller interval lying at both ends within the interval $-1$~to~$+1$, the geometric series is uniformly convergent within it. For example, take the interval $0$~to~$+\frac{1}{10}$. Then any value for~$n$ which makes $\dfrac{x^{n+1}}{1 - x}$~numerically less than~$k$ \emph{at} these limits for~$x$ also serves for all values of~$x$ between these limits, since it so happens that $\dfrac{x^{n+1}}{1 - x}$ diminishes in numerical value as $x$~diminishes in numerical value. For example, take $k = .001$; then, putting $x = \frac{1}{10}$, we find:\Add{---} \begin{alignat*}{3} &\text{for $n = 1$,}\quad & \frac{x^{n+1}}{1 - x} &= \frac{(\frac{1}{10})^{2}}{1 - \frac{1}{10}} &&= \tfrac{1}{90} = .0111\dots, \\ % &\text{for $n = 2$,}\quad & \frac{x^{n+1}}{1 - x} &= \frac{(\frac{1}{10})^{3}}{1 - \frac{1}{10}} &&= \tfrac{1}{900} = .00111\dots, \\ % &\text{for $n = 3$,}\quad & \frac{x^{n+1}}{1 - x} &= \frac{(\frac{1}{10})^{4}}{1 - \frac{1}{10}} &&= \tfrac{1}{9000} = .000111\dots\Typo{,}{.} \end{alignat*} Thus three terms will do for the whole interval, \PageSep{210} though, of course, for some parts of the interval it is more than is necessary. Notice that, because $1 + x + x^{2} + \dots + x^{n} + \dots$ is convergent (though not uniformly) throughout the interval $-1$~to~$+1$, for each value of~$x$ in the interval some number of terms~$n$ can be found which will satisfy a desired standard of approximation; but, as we take $x$ nearer and nearer to either end value $+1$ or~$-1$, larger and larger values of~$n$ have to be employed. It is curious that this important distinction between uniform and non-uniform convergence was not published till 1847 by Stokes---afterwards, \index{Stokes, Sir George}% Sir~George Stokes---and later, independently in~1850 by Seidel, a German \index{Seidel}% mathematician. The critical points, where non-uniform convergence comes in, are not necessarily at the limits of the interval throughout which convergence holds. This is a speciality belonging to the geometric series. In the case of the geometric series $1 + x + x^{2} + \dots + x^{n} + \dots$, a simple algebraic expression~$\dfrac{1}{1 - x}$ can be given for its limit in its interval of convergence. But this is not always the case. Often we can prove a series to be convergent within a certain interval, though we know nothing more about its limit except that it is the limit of the series. \PageSep{211} But this is a very good way of defining a function; \viz.\ as the limit of an infinite convergent series, and is, in fact, the way in which most functions are, or ought to be, defined. Thus, the most important series in elementary \index{Exponential Series|EtSeq}% analysis is \[ 1 + x + \frac{x^{2}}{2!} + \frac{x^{3}}{3!} + \dots + \frac{x^{n}}{n!} + \dots, \] where $n!$ has the meaning defined earlier in this chapter. This series can be proved to be absolutely convergent for \emph{all} values of~$x$, and to be uniformly convergent within any interval which we like to take. Hence it has all the comfortable mathematical properties which a series should have. It is called the exponential series. Denote its sum to infinity by~$\exp x$. Thus, by definition, \[ \exp x = 1 + x + \frac{x^{2}}{2!} + \frac{x^{3}}{3!} + \dots + \frac{x^{n}}{n!} + \dots\Add{.} \] $\exp x$ is called the exponential function. It is fairly easy to prove, with a little knowledge of elementary mathematics, that \[ (\exp x) × (\exp y) = \exp(x + y). \Tag{(A)} \] In other words that \begin{multline*} (\exp x) × (\exp y) \\ = 1 + (x + y) + \frac{(x + y)^{2}}{2!} + \frac{(x + y)^{3}}{3!} + \dots + \frac{(x + y)^{n}}{n!} + \dots\Add{.} \end{multline*} \PageSep{212} This property~\Eq{(A)} is an example of what is called an addition-theorem. When any \index{Addition-Theorem}% function [say~$f(x)$] has been defined, the first thing we do is to try to express $f(x + y)$ in terms of known functions of $x$~only, and known functions of $y$~only. If we can do so, the result is called an addition-theorem. Addition-theorems play a great part in mathematical analysis. Thus the addition-theorem for the sine is given by \[ \sin(x + y) = \sin x \cos y + \cos x \sin y, \] and for the cosine by \[ \cos(x + y) = \cos x \cos y - \sin x \sin y. \] As a matter of fact the best ways of defining $\sin x$ and $\cos x$ are not by the elaborate geometrical methods of the previous chapter, but as the limits respectively of the series \[ x - \frac{x^{3}}{3!} + \frac{x^{5}}{5!} - \frac{x^{7}}{7!} + \text{etc.} \dots, \] and \[ 1 - \frac{x^{2}}{2!} + \frac{x^{4}}{4!} - \frac{x^{6}}{6!} + \text{etc.} \dots, \] so that we put \begin{align*} \sin x &= x - \frac{x^{3}}{3!} + \frac{x^{5}}{5!} - \frac{x^{7}}{7!} + \text{etc.} \dots, \\ \cos x &= 1 - \frac{x^{2}}{2!} + \frac{x^{4}}{4!} - \frac{x^{6}}{6!} + \text{etc.} \dots\Typo{,}{.} \end{align*} \PageSep{213} These definitions are equivalent to the geometrical definitions, and both series can be proved to be convergent for all values of~$x$, and uniformly convergent throughout any interval. These series for sine and cosine have a general likeness to the exponential series given above. They are, indeed, intimately connected with it by means of the theory of imaginary numbers explained in Chapters \ChapNum{VII}.\ and~\ChapNum{VIII}. \Figure{29} The graph of the exponential function is given in \Fig[fig.]{29}. It cuts the axis~$OY$ at the point $y = 1$, as evidently it ought to do, since when $x = 0$ every term of the series except the first is zero. The importance of the exponential function is that it represents any changing physical quantity whose rate of increase at any instant is a uniform percentage of its value at that instant. For \PageSep{214} example, the above graph represents the size at any time of a population with a uniform birth-rate, a uniform death-rate, and no emigration, where the $x$ corresponds to the time reckoned from any convenient day, and the $y$ represents the population to the proper scale. The scale must be such that $OA$~represents the population at the date which is taken as the origin. But we have here come upon the idea of ``rates of increase'' which is the topic for the next chapter. An important function nearly allied to the \index{Normal Error, Curve of}% exponential function is found by putting~$-x^{2}$ for~$x$ as the argument in the exponential function. %[** TN: Omitted period following "exp"] We thus get $\exp (-x^{2})$. The graph $y = \exp(-x^{2})$ is given in \Fig[fig.]{30}. \Figure{30} The curve, which is something like a cocked hat, is called the curve of normal error. Its \PageSep{215} corresponding function is vitally important to the theory of statistics, and tells us in many cases the sort of deviations from the average results which we are to expect. Another important function is found by combining the exponential function with the sine, in this way:\Add{---} \[ y = \exp(-cx) × \sin \frac{2\pi x}{p}\Add{.} \] \Figure{31} Its graph is given in \Fig[fig.]{31}. The points $A$,~$B$, $O$, $C$, $D$, $E$,~$F$, are placed at equal intervals~$\frac{1}{2}p$, and an unending series of them should be drawn forwards and backwards. This function represents the dying away of vibrations under the influence of friction or of ``damping'' forces. Apart from the friction, the vibrations would be periodic, with a period~$p$; but the influence of the friction \PageSep{216} makes the extent of each vibration smaller than that of the preceding by a constant percentage of that extent. This combination of the idea of ``periodicity'' (which requires \index{Periodicity}% the sine or cosine for its symbolism) and of ``constant percentage'' (which requires the exponential function for its symbolism) is the reason for the form of this function, namely, its form as a product of a sine-function into an exponential function. \PageSep{217} \Chapter{XV}{The Differential Calculus} \First{The} invention of the differential calculus \index{Differential Calculus|EtSeq}% marks a crisis in the history of mathematics. The progress of science is divided between periods characterized by a slow accumulation of ideas and periods, when, owing to the new material for thought thus patiently collected, some genius by the invention of a new method or a new point of view, suddenly transforms the whole subject on to a higher level. These contrasted periods in the progress of the history of thought are compared by Shelley to the formation of an avalanche. \begin{verse} \footnotesize \index{Shelley (quotation from)}% The sun-awakened avalanche! whose mass, \\ Thrice sifted by the storm, had gathered there \\ Flake after flake,---in heaven-defying minds \\ As thought by thought is piled, till some great truth \\ Is loosened, and the nations echo round, \\ \dotfill \end{verse} The comparison will bear some pressing. The final burst of sunshine which awakens the avalanche is not necessarily beyond comparison in magnitude with the other powers of nature which have presided over its slow \PageSep{218} formation. The same is true in science. The genius who has the good fortune to produce the final idea which transforms a whole region of thought, does not necessarily excel all his predecessors who have worked at the preliminary formation of ideas. In considering the history of science, it is both silly and ungrateful to confine our admiration with a gaping wonder to those men who have made the final advances towards a new epoch\Add{.} In the particular instance before us, the \index{Leibniz|EtSeq}% \index{Newton|EtSeq}% subject had a long history before it assumed its final form at the hands of its two inventors. There are some traces of its methods even among the Greek mathematicians, and finally, just before the actual production of the subject, Fermat (born 1601~\AD, \index{Fermat}% and died 1665~\AD), a distinguished French mathematician, had so improved on previous ideas that the subject was all but created by him. Fermat, also, may lay claim to be the joint inventor of coordinate geometry in company with his contemporary and countryman, Descartes. It was, in fact, \index{Descartes}% Descartes from whom the world of science received the new ideas, but Fermat had certainly arrived at them independently. We need not, however, stint our admiration either for Newton or for Leibniz. Newton was a mathematician and a student of physical science, Leibniz was a mathematician \PageSep{219} and a philosopher, and each of them in his own department of thought was one of the greatest men of genius that the world has known. The joint invention was the occasion of an unfortunate and not very creditable dispute. Newton was using the methods of Fluxions, as he called the subject, \index{Fluxions}% in~1666, and employed it in the composition of his \Title{Principia}, although in the work as printed any special algebraic notation is avoided. But he did not print a direct statement of his method till~1693. Leibniz published his first statement in~1684. He was accused by Newton's friends of having got it from a MS. by Newton, which he had been shown privately. Leibniz also accused Newton of having plagiarized from him. There is now not very much doubt but that both should have the credit of being independent discoverers. The subject had arrived at a stage in which it was ripe for discovery, and there is nothing surprising in the fact that two such able men should have independently hit upon it. These joint discoveries are quite common in science. Discoveries are not in general made before they have been led up to by the previous trend of thought, and by that time many minds are in hot pursuit of the important idea. If we merely keep to discoveries in which Englishmen are \PageSep{220} concerned, the simultaneous enunciation of the law of natural selection by Darwin and \index{Darwin}% Wallace, and the simultaneous discovery of \index{Wallace}% Neptune by Adams and the French astronomer, \index{Adams}% Leverrier, at once occur to the mind. \index{Leverrier}% The disputes, as to whom the credit ought to be given, are often influenced by an unworthy spirit of nationalism. The really inspiring reflection suggested by the history of mathematics is the unity of thought and interest among men of so many epochs, so many nations, and so many races. Indians, Egyptians, Assyrians, Greeks, Arabs, Italians, Frenchmen, Germans, Englishmen, and Russians, have all made essential contributions to the progress of the science. Assuredly the jealous exaltation of the contribution of one particular nation is not to show the larger spirit. The importance of the differential calculus \index{Rate of Increase of Functions|EtSeq}% arises from the very nature of the subject, which is the systematic consideration of the rates of increase of functions. This idea is immediately presented to us by the study of nature; velocity is the rate of increase of the distance travelled, and acceleration is the rate of increase of velocity. Thus the fundamental idea of change, which is at the basis of our whole perception of phenomena, immediately suggests the enquiry as to the rate of change. The familiar terms of ``quickly'' and ``slowly'' gain their meaning from a tacit \PageSep{221} reference to rates of change. Thus the differential calculus is concerned with the very key of the position from which mathematics can be successfully applied to the explanation of the course of nature. This idea of the rate of change was certainly in Newton's mind, and was embodied in the \Figure{32} language in which he explained the subject. It may be doubted, however, whether this point of view, derived from natural phenomena, was ever much in the minds of the preceding mathematicians who prepared the subject for its birth. They were concerned with the more abstract problems of drawing tangents \index{Tangents}% to curves, of finding the lengths of curves, and of finding the areas enclosed by curves. The \PageSep{222} last two problems, of the rectification of curves and the quadrature of curves as they are named, belong to the Integral Calculus, which \index{Integral Calculus}% is however involved in the same general subject as the Differential Calculus. The introduction of coordinate geometry \index{Tangents}% makes the two points of view coalesce. For (\Chg{cf.}{\cf}\ \Fig[fig.]{32}) let $AQP$ be any curved line and let $PT$ be the tangent at the point~$P$ on it. Let the axes of coordinates be $OX$ and~$OY$; and let $y = f(x)$ be the equation to the curve, so that $OM = x$, and $PM = y$. Now let $Q$ be any moving point on the curve, with coordinates $x_{1}$,~$y_{1}$; then $y_{1} = f(x_{1})$. And let $Q'$ be the point on the tangent with the same abscissa~$x_{1}$; suppose that the coordinates of~$Q'$ are $x_{1}$ and~$y'$. Now suppose that $N$~moves along the axis~$OX$ from left to right with a uniform velocity; then it is easy to see that the ordinate~$y'$ of the point~$Q'$ on the tangent~$TP$ also increases uniformly as $Q'$~moves along the tangent in a corresponding way. In fact it is easy to see that the ratio of the rate of increase of~$Q'N$ to the rate of increase of~$ON$ is in the ratio of $Q'N$ to~$TN$, which is the same at all points of the straight line. But the rate of increase of~$QN$, which is the rate of increase of~$f(x_{1})$, varies from point to point of the curve so long as it is not straight. As $Q$~passes through the point~$P$, the rate of increase of~$f(x_{1})$ (where $x_{1}$~coincides with~$x$ for the moment) \PageSep{223} is the same as the rate of increase of~$y'$ on the tangent at~$P$. Hence, if we have a general method of determining the rate of increase of a function~$f(x)$ of a variable~$x$, we can determine the slope of the tangent at any point $(x, y\Typo{,}{})$ on a curve, and thence can draw it. Thus the problems of drawing tangents to a curve, and of determining the rates of increase of a function are really identical. It will be noticed that, as in the cases of Conic Sections and Trigonometry, the more artificial of the two points of view is the one in which the subject took its rise. The really fundamental aspect of the science only rose into prominence comparatively late in the day. It is a well-founded historical generalization, that the last thing to be discovered in any science is what the science is really about. Men go on groping for centuries, guided merely by a dim instinct and a puzzled curiosity, till at last ``some great truth is loosened.'' Let us take some special cases in order to familiarize ourselves with the sort of ideas which we want to make precise. A train is in motion---how shall we determine its velocity at some instant, let us say, at noon? We can take an interval of five minutes which includes noon, and measure how far the train has gone in that period. Suppose we find it to be five \PageSep{224} miles, we may then conclude that the train was running at the rate of $60$~miles per~hour. But five miles is a long distance, and we cannot be sure that just at noon the train was moving at this pace. At noon it may have been running $70$~miles per~hour, and afterwards the \Typo{break}{brake} may have been put on. It will be safer to work with a smaller interval, say one minute, which includes noon, and to measure the space traversed during that period. But for some purposes greater accuracy may be required, and one minute may be too long. In practice, the necessary inaccuracy of our measurements makes it useless to take too small a period for measurement. But in theory the smaller the period the better, and we are tempted to say that for ideal accuracy an infinitely small period is required. The older mathematicians, in particular Leibniz, were not only tempted, but yielded to the temptation, and did say it. Even now it is a useful fashion of speech, provided that we know how to interpret it into the language of common sense. It is curious that, in his exposition of the foundations of the calculus, Newton, the natural scientist, is much more philosophical than Leibniz, the philosopher, and on the other hand, Leibniz provided the admirable notation which has been so essential for the progress of the subject. \PageSep{225} Now take another example within the region of pure mathematics. Let us proceed to find the rate of increase of the function~$x^{2}$ for any value~$x$ of its argument. We have not yet really defined what we mean by rate of increase. We will try and grasp its meaning in relation to this particular case. When $x$~increases to $x + h$, the function~$x^{2}$ increases to $(x + h)^{2}$; so that the total increase has been $(x + h)^{2} - x^{2}$, due to an increase~$h$ in the argument. Hence throughout the interval $x$~to $(x + h)$ the average increase of the function per unit increase of the argument is $\dfrac{(x + h)^{2} - x^{2}}{h}$. But \[ (x + h)^{2} = x^{2} + 2hx + h^{2}, \] and therefore \[ \frac{(x + h)^{2} - x^{2}}{h} = \frac{2hx + h^{2}}{h} = 2x + h. \] Thus $2x + h$ is the average increase of the function~$x^{2}$ per unit increase in the argument, the average being taken over by the interval $x$~to~$x + h$. But $2x + h$ depends on~$h$, the size of the interval. We shall evidently get what we want, namely the \emph{rate} of increase at the value~$x$ of the argument, by diminishing~$h$ more and more. Hence \emph{in the limit} when $h$~has \PageSep{226} \index{Infinitely Small Quantities|EtSeq}% \emph{decreased indefinitely}, we say that $2x$~is the rate of increase of~$x^{2}$ at the value~$x$ of the argument. Here again we are apparently driven up against the idea of infinitely small quantities in the use of the words ``in the limit when $h$~has decreased indefinitely.'' Leibniz held that, mysterious as it may sound, there were actually existing such things as infinitely small quantities, and of course infinitely small numbers corresponding to them. Newton's language and ideas were more on the modern lines; but he did not succeed in explaining the matter with such explicitness so as to be evidently doing more than explain Leibniz's ideas in rather indirect language. The real explanation of the subject was first given by Weierstrass and the Berlin School of mathematicians \index{Weierstrass}% about the middle of the nineteenth century. But between Leibniz and Weierstrass a copious literature, both mathematical and philosophical, had grown up round these mysterious infinitely small quantities which mathematics had discovered and philosophy proceeded to explain. Some philosophers, \index{Berkeley, Bishop}% Bishop Berkeley, for instance, correctly denied the validity of the whole idea, though for reasons other than those indicated here. But the curious fact remained that, despite all criticisms of the foundations of the subject, there could be no doubt but that the mathematical \PageSep{227} procedure was substantially right. In fact, the subject was right, though the explanations were wrong. It is this possibility of being right, albeit with entirely wrong explanations as to what is being done, that so often makes external criticism---that is so far as it is meant to stop the pursuit of a method---singularly barren and futile in the progress of science. The instinct of trained observers, and their sense of curiosity, due to the fact that they are obviously getting at something, are far safer guides. Anyhow the general effect of the success of the Differential Calculus was to generate a large amount of bad philosophy, centring round the idea of the infinitely small. The relics of this verbiage may still be found in the explanations of many elementary mathematical text-books on the Differential Calculus. It is a safe rule to apply that, when a mathematical or philosophical author writes with a misty profundity, he is talking nonsense. \medskip Newton would have phrased the question \index{Limit of a Function|EtSeq}% by saying that, as $h$~approaches zero, in the limit $2x + h$ becomes~$2x$. It is our task so to explain this statement as to show that it does not in reality covertly assume the existence of Leibniz's infinitely small quantities. In reading over the Newtonian method of statement, it is tempting to seek simplicity by \PageSep{228} saying that $2x + h$ is~$2x$, when $h$~is zero. But this will not do; for it thereby abolishes the interval from $x$ to~$x + h$, over which the average increase was calculated. The problem is, how to keep an interval of length~$h$ over which to calculate the average increase, and at the same time to treat~$h$ as if it were zero. Newton did this by the conception of a limit, and we now \index{Weierstrass}% proceed to give Weierstrass's explanation of its real meaning. In the first place notice that, in discussing $2x + h$, we have been considering~$x$ as fixed in value and $h$~as varying. In other words $x$~has been treated as a ``constant'' variable, or parameter, as explained in \ChapRef{IX}.; and we have really been considering $2x + h$ as a function of the argument~$h$. Hence we can generalize the question on hand, and ask what we mean by saying that the function~$f(h)$ tends to the limit~$l$, say, as its argument~$h$ tends to the value zero. But again we shall see that the special value \emph{zero} for the argument does not belong to the essence of the subject; and again we generalize still further, and ask, what we mean by saying that the function~$f(h)$ tends to the limit~$l$ as $h$~tends to the value~$a$. Now, according to the Weierstrassian explanation the whole idea of $h$~tending to the value~$a$, though it gives a sort of metaphorical picture of what we are driving at, is really off the point entirely. Indeed it is fairly obvious \PageSep{229} that, as long as we retain anything like ``$h$~tending to~$a$,'' as a fundamental idea, we are really in the clutches of the infinitely small; for we imply the notion of $h$~being infinitely near to~$a$. This is just what we want to get rid of. Accordingly, we shall yet again restate our phrase to be explained, and ask what we mean by saying that the limit of the function~$f(h)$ at~$a$ is~$l$. The limit of~$f(h)$ at~$a$ is a property of the \index{Standard of Approximation|EtSeq}% neighbourhood of~$a$, where ``neighbourhood'' is used in the sense defined in \ChapRef{XI}.\ during the discussion of the continuity of functions. The value of the function~$f(h)$ at~$a$ is~$f(a)$; but the limit is distinct in idea from the value, and may be different from it, and may exist when the value has not been defined. We shall also use the term ``standard of approximation'' in the sense in which it is defined in \ChapRef{XI}. In fact, in the definition of ``continuity'' given towards the end of that chapter we have practically defined a limit. The definition of a limit is:--- A function~$f(x)$ has the limit~$l$ at a value~$a$ of its argument~$x$, when in the neighbourhood of~$a$ its values approximate to~$l$ within \emph{every} standard of approximation. Compare this definition with that already given for continuity, namely:--- \PageSep{230} A function~$f(x)$ is continuous at a value~$a$ of its argument, when in the neighbourhood of~$a$ its values approximate to its value at~$a$ within \emph{every} standard of approximation. It is at once evident that a function is continuous at~$a$ when (i)~it possesses a limit at~$a$, and (ii)~that limit is equal to its value at~$a$. Thus the illustrations of continuity which have been given at the end of \ChapRef{XI}.\ are illustrations of the idea of a limit, namely, they were all directed to proving that $f(a)$~was the limit of~$f(x)$ at~$a$ for the functions considered and the value of~$a$ considered. It is really more instructive to consider the limit at a point where a function is not continuous. For example, consider the function of which the graph is given in \Fig[fig.]{20} of \ChapRef{XI}. This function~$f(x)$ is defined to have the value~$1$ for all values of the argument except the integers $0$,~$1$, $2$, $3$,~etc., and for these integral values it has the value~$0$. Now let us think of its limit when $x = 3$. We notice that in the definition of the limit the value of the function at~$a$ (in this case, $a = 3$) is excluded. But, excluding~$f(3)$, the values of~$f(x)$, when $x$~lies within any interval which (i)~contains $3$ not as an end-point, and (ii)~does not extend so far as $2$ and~$4$, are all equal to~$1$; and hence these values approximate to~$1$ within every standard of approximation. Hence $1$~is the limit of~$f(x)$ at the \PageSep{231} value~$3$ of the argument~$x$, but by definition $f(3) = 0$. This is an instance of a function which possesses both a value and a limit at the value~$3$ of the argument, but the value is not equal to the limit. At the end of \ChapRef{XI}.\ the function~$x^{2}$ was considered at the value~$2$ of the argument. Its value at~$2$ is~$2^{2}$, \ie~$4$, and it was proved that its limit is also~$4$. Thus here we have a function with a value and a limit which are equal. Finally we come to the case which is essentially important for our purposes, namely, to a function which possesses a limit, but no defined value at a certain value of its argument. We need not go far to look for such a function, $\dfrac{2x}{x}$~will serve our purpose. Now in any mathematical book, we might find the equation, $\dfrac{2x}{x} = 2$, written without hesitation or comment. But there is a difficulty in this; for when $x$~is zero, $\dfrac{2x}{x} = \dfrac{0}{0}$; and $\dfrac{0}{0}$~has no defined meaning. Thus the value of the function~$\dfrac{2x}{x}$ at $x = 0$ has no defined \PageSep{232} meaning. But for every other value of~$x$, the value of the function~$\dfrac{2x}{x}$ is~$2$. Thus the limit of~$\dfrac{2x}{x}$ at $x = 0$ is~$2$, and it has no value at $x = 0$. Similarly the limit of~$\dfrac{x^{2}}{x}$ at $x = a$ is~$a$ whatever $a$~may be, so that the limit of~$\dfrac{x^{2}}{x}$ at $x = 0$ is~$0$. But the value of~$\dfrac{x^{2}}{x}$ at $x = 0$ takes the form~$\dfrac{0}{0}$, which has no defined meaning. Thus the function~$\dfrac{x^{2}}{x}$ has a limit but no value at~$0$. We now come back to the problem from which we started this discussion on the nature of a limit. How are we going to define the rate of increase of the function~$x^{2}$ at any value~$x$ of its argument. Our answer is that this rate of increase is the limit of the function $\dfrac{(x + h)^{2} - x^{2}}{h}$ at the value zero for its argument~$h$. (Note that $x$~is here a ``constant.'') Let us see how this answer works \PageSep{233} in the light of our definition of a limit. We have \[ \frac{(x + h)^{2} - x^{2}}{h} = \frac{2hx + h^{2}}{h} = \frac{h(2x + h)}{h}\Add{.} \] Now in finding the limit of~$\dfrac{h(2x + h)}{h}$ at the value~$0$ of the argument~$h$, the value (if any) of the function at $h = 0$ is excluded. But for all values of~$h$, except $h = 0$, we can divide through by~$h$. Thus the limit of~$\dfrac{h(2x + h)}{h}$ at $h = 0$ is the same as that of $2x + h$ at $h = 0$. Now, whatever standard of approximation~$k$ we choose to take, by considering the interval from $-\frac{1}{2}k$ to~$+\frac{1}{2}k$ we see that, for values of~$h$ which fall within it, $2x + h$~differs from~$2x$ by less than~$\frac{1}{2}k$, that is by less than~$k$. This is true for \emph{any} standard~$k$. Hence in the neighbourhood of the value~$0$ for~$h$, $2x + h$~approximates to~$2x$ within \emph{every} standard of approximation, and therefore $2x$~is the limit of~$2x + h$ at $h = 0$. Hence by what has been said above $2x$~is the limit of $\dfrac{(x + h)^{2} - x^{2}}{h}$ at the value~$0$ for~$h$. It follows, therefore, that $2x$~is what we have called the rate of increase of~$x^{2}$ at the value~$x$ of the argument. Thus this method conducts us to the same rate of increase \PageSep{234} for~$x^{2}$ as did the Leibnizian way of making $h$~grow ``infinitely small.'' The more abstract terms ``differential coefficient,'' \index{Differential Coefficient}% or ``derived function,'' are generally \index{Derived Function}% used for what we have hitherto called the ``rate of increase'' of a function. The general definition is as follows: the differential coefficient of the function~$f(x)$ is the limit, if it exist, of the function $\dfrac{f(x + h) - f(x)}{h}$ of the argument~$h$ at the value~$0$ of its argument. How have we, by this definition and the subsidiary definition of a limit, really managed to avoid the notion of ``infinitely small numbers'' which so worried our mathematical forefathers? For them the difficulty arose because on the one hand they had to use an interval $x$~to $x + h$ over which to calculate the average increase, and, on the other hand, they finally wanted to put $h = 0$. The result was they seemed to be landed into the notion of an existent interval of zero size. Now how do we avoid this difficulty? In this way---we use the notion that corresponding to \emph{any} standard of approximation, \emph{some} interval with such and such properties can be found. The difference is that we have \index{Variable, The}% grasped the importance of the notion of ``the variable,'' and they had not done so. Thus, \PageSep{235} at the end of our exposition of the essential notions of mathematical analysis, we are led back to the ideas with which in \ChapRef{II}.\ we commenced our enquiry---that in mathematics the fundamentally important ideas are those of ``\emph{some} things'' and ``\emph{any} things.'' \PageSep{236} \Chapter{XVI}{Geometry} \First{Geometry}, like the rest of mathematics, is \index{Geometry|EtSeq}% abstract. In it the properties of the shapes and relative positions of things are studied. But we do not need to consider who is observing the things, or whether he becomes acquainted with them by sight or touch or hearing. In short, we ignore all particular sensations. Furthermore, particular things such as the Houses of Parliament, or the terrestrial globe are ignored. Every proposition refers to any things with such and such geometrical properties. Of course it helps our imagination to look at particular examples of spheres and cones and triangles and squares. But the propositions do not merely apply to the actual figures printed in the book, but to any such figures. Thus geometry, like algebra, is dominated by the ideas of ``any'' and ``some'' things. Also, in the same way it studies the interrelations of sets of things. For example, consider any two triangles $ABC$ and~$DEF$. \PageSep{237} What relations must exist between some of \index{Triangle}% the parts of these triangles, in order that the triangles may be in all respects equal? This is one of the first investigations undertaken in all elementary geometries. It is a study \Figure{33} of a certain set of possible correlations between the two triangles. The answer is that the triangles are in all respects equal, if:--- Either, (a)~Two sides of the one and the included angle are respectively equal to two sides of the other and the included angle: Or, (b)~Two angles of the one and the side joining them are respectively equal to two angles of the other and the side joining them: Or, (c)~Three sides of the one are respectively equal to three sides of the other. This answer at once suggests a further enquiry. What is the nature of the correlation between the triangles, when the three angles of the one are respectively equal to the three angles of the other? This further investigation leads us on to the whole theory of similarity \index{Similarity}% \PageSep{238} (\Chg{cf.}{\cf}\ \ChapRef{XIII}.), which is another type of correlation. Again, to take another example, consider the internal structure of the triangle~$ABC$. Its sides and angles are inter-related---the greater angle is opposite to the greater side, and the base angles of an isosceles triangle are equal. If we proceed to trigonometry this correlation receives a more exact determination in the familiar shape \[ \frac{\sin A}{a} = \frac{\sin B}{b} = \frac{\sin C}{c}, \] $a^{2} = b^{2} + c^{2} - 2bc \cos A$, with two similar formulæ. Also there is the still simpler correlation between the angles of the triangle, namely, that their sum is equal to two right angles; and between the three sides, namely, that the sum of the lengths of any two is greater than the length of the third\Add{.} Thus the true method to study geometry is to think of interesting simple figures, such as the triangle, the parallelogram, and the circle, and to investigate the correlations between their various parts. The geometer has in his mind not a detached proposition, but a figure with its various parts mutually inter-dependent. Just as in algebra, he generalizes the triangle into the polygon, and the side into \PageSep{239} the conic section. Or, pursuing a converse route, he classifies triangles according as they are equilateral, isosceles, or scalene, and polygons according to their number of sides, and conic sections according as they are hyperbolas, ellipses, or parabolas. The preceding examples illustrate how the fundamental ideas of geometry are exactly the same as those of algebra; except that algebra deals with numbers and geometry with lines, angles, areas, and other geometrical entities. This fundamental identity is one of the reasons why so many geometrical truths can be put into an algebraic dress. Thus if $A$,~$B$, and~$C$ are the numbers of degrees respectively in the angles of the triangle~$ABC$, the correlation between the angles is represented by the equation \[ A + B + C = 180°; \] and if $a$,~$b$,~$c$ are the number of feet respectively in the three sides, the correlation between the sides is represented by $a < b + c$, $b < c + a$, $c < a + b$. Also the trigonometrical formulæ quoted above are other examples of the same \index{Variable, The}% fact. Thus the notion of the variable and the correlation of variables is just as essential in geometry as it is in algebra. But the parallelism between geometry and algebra can be pushed still further, owing to the fact that lengths, areas, volumes, and \PageSep{240} angles are all measurable; so that, for example, the size of any length can be determined by the number (not necessarily integral) of times which it contains some arbitrarily known unit, and similarly for areas, volumes, and angles. The trigonometrical formulæ, given above, are examples of this fact. But it receives its crowning application in analytical geometry. This great subject is often misnamed as Analytical Conic Sections, thereby \index{Analytical Conic Sections}% fixing attention on merely one of its subdivisions. It is as though the great science of Anthropology were named the Study of Noses, owing to the fact that noses are a prominent part of the human body. Though the mathematical procedures in geometry and algebra are in essence identical and intertwined in their development, there is necessarily a fundamental distinction between the properties of space and the properties of number---in fact all the essential difference between space and number. The ``spaciness'' of space and the ``numerosity'' of number are essentially different things, and must be directly apprehended. None of the applications of algebra to geometry or of geometry to algebra go any step on the road to obliterate this vital distinction. One very marked difference between space and number is that the former seems to be so much less abstract and fundamental than the \PageSep{241} latter. The number of the archangels can be counted just because they are things. When we once know that their names are Raphael, Gabriel, and Michael, and that these distinct names represent distinct beings, we know without further question that there are three of them. All the subtleties in the world about the nature of angelic existences cannot alter this fact, granting the premisses. But we are still quite in the dark as to their relation to space. Do they exist in space at all? Perhaps it is equally nonsense to say that they are here, or there, or anywhere, or everywhere. Their existence may simply have no relation to localities in space. Accordingly, while numbers must apply to all things, space need not do so. The perception of the locality of things would appear to accompany, or be involved in many, or all, of our sensations. It is independent of any particular sensation in the sense that it accompanies many sensations. But it is a special peculiarity of the things which we apprehend by our sensations. The direct apprehension of what we mean by the positions of things in respect to each other is a thing \Foreign{sui generis}, just as are the apprehensions of sounds, colours, tastes, and smells. At first sight therefore it would appear that mathematics, in so far as it includes geometry in its scope, is not abstract in the sense in \PageSep{242} which abstractness is ascribed to it in \ChapRef{I}. This, however, is a mistake; the truth being \index{Abstract Nature of Geometry|EtSeq}% that the ``spaciness'' of space does not enter into our geometrical \emph{reasoning} at all. It enters into the geometrical intuitions of mathematicians in ways personal and peculiar to each individual. But what enter into the reasoning are merely certain properties of things in space, or of things forming space, which properties are completely abstract in the sense in which abstract was defined in \ChapRef{I}.; these properties do not involve any peculiar space-apprehension or space-intuition or space-sensation. They are on exactly the same basis as the mathematical properties of number. Thus the space-intuition which is so essential an aid to the study of geometry is logically irrelevant: it does not enter into the premisses when they are properly stated, nor into any step of the reasoning. It has the practical importance of an example, which is essential for the stimulation of our thoughts. Examples are equally necessary to stimulate our thoughts on number. When we think of ``two'' and ``three'' we see strokes in a row, or balls in a heap, or some other physical aggregation of particular things. The peculiarity of geometry is the fixity and overwhelming importance of the one particular example which occurs to our \PageSep{243} minds. The abstract logical form of the propositions when fully stated is, ``If any collections of things have such and such abstract properties, they also have such and such other abstract properties.'' But what appears before the mind's eye is a collection of points, lines, surfaces, and volumes in the space: this example inevitably appears, and is the sole example which lends to the proposition its interest. However, for all its overwhelming importance, it is but an example. Geometry, viewed as a mathematical science, is a division of the more general science of order. It may be called the science of dimensional order; the qualification ``dimensional'' has been introduced because the limitations, which reduce it to only a part of the general science of order, are such as to produce the regular relations of straight lines to planes, and of planes to the whole of space. It is easy to understand the practical importance of space in the formation of the scientific conception of an external physical world. On the one hand our space-perceptions are intertwined in our various sensations and connect them together. We normally judge that we touch an object in the same place as we see it; and even in abnormal cases we touch it in the same space as we see it, and this is the real fundamental fact which ties together our various sensations. Accordingly, \PageSep{244} the space perceptions are in a sense the common part of our sensations. Again it happens that the abstract properties of space form a large part of whatever is of spatial interest. It is not too much to say that to every property of space there corresponds an abstract mathematical statement. To take the most unfavourable instance, a curve may have a special beauty of shape: but to this shape there will correspond some abstract mathematical properties which go with this shape and no others. Thus to sum up: (1)~the properties of space which are investigated in geometry, like those of number, are properties belonging to things as things, and without special reference to any particular mode of apprehension: (2)~Space-perception accompanies our sensations, perhaps all of them, certainly many; but it does not seem to be a necessary quality of things that they should all exist in one space or in any space. \PageSep{245} \Chapter{XVII}{Quantity} \First{In} the previous chapter we pointed out \index{Quantity|EtSeq}% that lengths are measurable in terms of some unit length, areas in term of a unit area, and volumes in terms of a unit volume. When we have a set of things such as lengths which are measurable in terms of any one of them, we say that they are quantities of the same kind. Thus lengths are quantities of the same kind, so are areas, and so are volumes. But an area is not a quantity of the same kind as a length, nor is it of the same kind as a volume. Let us think a little more on what is meant by being measurable, taking lengths as an example. Lengths are measured by the foot-rule. By transporting the foot-rule from place to place we judge of the equality of lengths. Again, three adjacent lengths, each of one foot, form one whole length of three feet. Thus to measure lengths we have to determine the equality of lengths and the addition of lengths. When some test has been applied, such as the transporting of a foot-rule, we say that the lengths are equal; and when some process \PageSep{246} has been applied, so as to secure lengths being contiguous and not overlapping, we say that the lengths have been added to form one whole length. But we cannot arbitrarily take any test as the test of equality and any process as the process of addition. The results of operations of addition and of judgments of equality must be in accordance with certain preconceived conditions. For example, the addition of two greater lengths must yield a length greater than that yielded by the addition of two smaller lengths. These preconceived conditions when accurately formulated may be called axioms of quantity. The only question as to their truth or falsehood \index{Axioms of Quantity|EtSeq}% which can arise is whether, when the axioms are satisfied, we necessarily get what ordinary people call quantities. If we do not, then the name ``axioms of quantity'' is ill-judged---that is all. These axioms of quantity are entirely abstract, just as are the mathematical properties of space. They are the same for all quantities, and they presuppose no special mode of perception. The ideas associated with the notion of quantity are the means by which a continuum like a line, an area, or a volume can be split up into definite parts. Then these parts are counted; so that numbers can be used to determine the exact properties of a continuous whole. \PageSep{247} Our perception of the flow of time and of \index{Time|EtSeq}% the succession of events is a chief example of the application of these ideas of quantity. We measure time (as has been said in considering periodicity) by the repetition of similar events---the burning of successive inches of a uniform candle, the rotation of the earth relatively to the fixed stars, the rotation of the hands of a clock are all examples of such repetitions. Events of these types take the place of the foot-rule in relation to lengths. It is not necessary to assume that events of any one of these types are exactly equal in duration at each recurrence. What is necessary is that a rule should be known which will enable us to express the relative durations of, say, two examples of some type. For example, we may if we like suppose that the rate of the earth's rotation is decreasing, so that each day is longer than the preceding by some minute fraction of a second. Such a rule enables us to compare the length of any day with that of any other day. But what is essential is that one series of repetitions, such as successive days, should be taken as the standard series; and, if the various events of that series are not taken as of equal duration, that a rule should be stated which regulates the duration to be assigned to each day in terms of the duration of any other day. \PageSep{248} What then are the requisites which such a rule ought to have? In the first place it should lead to the assignment of nearly equal durations to events which common sense judges to possess equal durations. A rule which made days of violently different lengths, and which made the speeds of apparently similar operations vary utterly out of proportion to the apparent minuteness of their differences, would never do. Hence the first requisite is general agreement with common sense. But this is not sufficient absolutely to determine the rule, for common sense is a rough observer and very easily satisfied. The next requisite is that minute adjustments of the rule should be so made as to allow of the simplest possible statements of the laws of nature. For example, astronomers tell us that the earth's rotation is slowing down, so that each day gains in length by some inconceivably minute fraction of a second. Their only reason for their assertion (as stated more fully in the discussion of periodicity) is that without it they would have to abandon the Newtonian laws of motion. In order to keep \index{Laws of Motion}% the laws of motion simple, they alter the measure of time. This is a perfectly legitimate procedure so long as it is thoroughly understood. What has been said above about the abstract nature of the mathematical properties \PageSep{249} of space applies with appropriate verbal changes to the mathematical properties of time. A sense of the flux of time accompanies all our sensations and perceptions, and practically all that interests us in regard to time can be paralleled by the abstract mathematical properties which we ascribe to it. Conversely what has been said about the two requisites for the rule by which we determine the length of the day, also applies to the rule for determining the length of a yard measure---namely, the yard measure appears to retain the same length as it moves about. Accordingly, any rule must bring out that, apart from minute changes, it does remain of invariable length; Again, the second requisite is this, a definite rule for minute changes shall be stated which allows of the simplest expression of the laws of nature. For example, in accordance with the second requisite the yard measures are supposed to expand and contract with changes of temperature according to the substances which they are made of. Apart from the facts that our sensations are accompanied with perceptions of locality and of duration, and that lines, areas, volumes, and durations, are each in their way quantities, the theory of numbers would be of very subordinate use in the exploration of the laws of the Universe, As it is, physical science \PageSep{250} reposes on the main ideas of number, quantity, space, and time. The mathematical sciences associated with them do not form the whole of mathematics, but they are the substratum of mathematical physics as at present existing. \BackMatter \Appendix{Notes} \Note{A} (\Pageref{60}).---In reading these equations it must be noted that a bracket is used in mathematical symbolism to mean that the operations within it are to be performed first. Thus $(1 + 3) + 2$ directs us first to add $3$ to~$1$, and then to add~$2$ to the result; and $1 + (3 + 2)$ directs us first to add $2$ to~$3$, and then to add the result to~$1$. Again a numerical example of equation~\Eq{(5)} is \[ 2 × (3 + 4) = (2 × 3) + (2 × 4). \] We perform first the operations in brackets and obtain \[ 2 × 7 = 6 + 8 \] which is obviously true. \Note{B} (\Pageref{136}).---This fundamental ratio~$\dfrac{SP}{PN}$ is called the eccentricity of the curve. The shape of the curve, as \index{Eccentricity}% distinct from its scale or size, depends upon the value of its eccentricity. Thus it is wrong to think of ellipses in general or of hyperbolas in general as having in either case one definite shape. Ellipses with different eccentricities have different shapes, and their sizes depend upon the lengths of their major axes. An ellipse with small eccentricity is very nearly a circle, and an ellipse of eccentricity only slightly less than unity is a long flat oval. All parabolas have the same eccentricity and are therefore of the same shape, though they can be drawn to different scales. \PageSep{251} \Note{C} (\Pageref{204}).---If a series with all its terms positive is \index{Absolute Convergence}% \index{Convergence, Absolute}% convergent, the modified series found by making some terms positive and some negative according to any definite rule is also convergent. Each one of the set of series thus found, including the original series, is called ``absolutely convergent.'' But it is possible for a series with terms partly positive and partly negative to be convergent, although the corresponding series with all its terms positive is divergent. For example, the series \[ 1 - \tfrac{1}{2} + \tfrac{1}{3} - \tfrac{1}{4} + \text{etc.} \] is convergent though we have just proved that \[ 1 + \tfrac{1}{2} + \tfrac{1}{3} + \tfrac{1}{4} + \text{etc.} \] is divergent. Such convergent series, which are not absolutely convergent, are much more difficult to deal with than absolutely convergent series. \Appendix[Note on the Study of Mathematics]{Bibliography} \First{The} difficulty that beginners find in the study of this science is due to the large amount of technical detail which has been allowed to accumulate in the elementary text-books, obscuring the important ideas. The first subjects of study, apart from a knowledge of arithmetic which is presupposed, must be elementary geometry and elementary algebra. The courses in both subjects should be short, giving only the necessary ideas; the algebra should be studied graphically, so that in practice the ideas of elementary coordinate geometry are also being assimilated. The next pair of subjects should be elementary trigonometry and the coordinate geometry of the straight line and circle. The latter subject is a short one; for it really merges into the algebra. The student is then prepared to enter upon conic sections, a very short course of geometrical conic sections and a longer one of analytical conics. But in all these courses great care should be taken not to overload the mind with more \PageSep{252} detail than is necessary for the exemplification of the fundamental ideas. The differential calculus and afterwards the integral calculus now remain to be attacked on the same system. A good teacher will already have illustrated them by the consideration of special cases in the course on algebra and coordinate geometry. Some short book on three-dimensional geometry must be also read. This elementary course of mathematics is sufficient for some types of professional career. It is also the necessary preliminary for any one wishing to study the subject for its intrinsic interest. He is now prepared to commence on a more extended course. He must not, however, hope to be able to master it as a whole. The science has grown to such vast proportions that probably no living mathematician can claim to have achieved this. Passing to the serious treatises on the subject to be read \emph{after} this preliminary course, the following may be mentioned: Cremona's \Title{Pure Geometry} (English Translation, Clarendon Press, Oxford), Hobson's \Title{Treatise on Trigonometry}, Chrystal's \Title{Treatise on Algebra} (2~volumes), Salmon's \Title{Conic Sections}, Lamb's \Title{Differential Calculus}, and some book on \Title{Differential Equations}. The student will probably not desire to direct equal attention to all these subjects, but will study one or more of them, according as his interest dictates. He will then be prepared to select more advanced works for himself, and to plunge into the higher parts of the subject. If his interest lies in analysis, he should now master an elementary treatise on the theory of Functions of the Complex Variable; if he prefers to specialize in Geometry, he must now proceed to the standard treatises on the Analytical Geometry of three dimensions. But at this stage of his career in learning he will not require the advice of this note. I have deliberately refrained from mentioning any elementary works. They are very numerous, and of various merits, but none of such outstanding superiority as to require special mention by name to the exclusion of all the others. %[** TN: Index text] % ** Page 253 \printindex \iffalse Abel 156 Abscissa 95 Absolute Convergence 251 Abstract Nature of Geometry|EtSeq 242 Abstractness (\emph{defined}) 9, 13 Adams 220 Addition-Theorem 212 Ahmes 71 Alexander the Great 128, 129 Algebra, Fundamental Laws of 60 Ampere@Ampère 34 Analytical Conic Sections 240 Apollonius of Perga 131, 134 Approximation|EtSeq 197 Arabic Notation|EtSeq 58 Archimedes|EtSeq 37 Argument of a Function 146 Aristotle 30, 42, 128 Astronomy 137, 173, 174 Axes 125 Axioms of Quantity|EtSeq 246 Bacon 156 Ball, W. W. R. 58 Beaconsfield, Lord 41 Berkeley, Bishop 226 Bhaskara 58 Cantor, Georg 79 Circle 120, 130 Circle@Circle|EtSeq 180 Circular Cylinder 143 Clerk Maxwell 34, 35 Columbus 122 Compact Series 76 Complex Quantities 109 Conic Sections|EtSeq 128 Constants 69, 117 Continuous Functions@Continuous Functions|EtSeq 150 Continuous Functions@Continuous Functions (\emph{defined}) 162 Convergence, Absolute 251 Convergent|EtSeq 203 Coordinate Geometry|EtSeq 112 Coordinates 95 Copernicus 45, 137 %[** TN: Entry italicized in the original, "Sine" not italicized] Cosine|EtSeq 182 Coulomb 33 Cross Ratio 140 Darwin 138, 220 Derived Function 234 Descartes 95, 113, 116, 122, 218 Differential Calculus|EtSeq 217 Differential Coefficient 234 Directrix 135 Discontinuous Functions|EtSeq 150 Distance 30 Divergent|EtSeq 203 % ** Page 254 Dynamical Explanation 13, 14 Dynamical Explanation@Dynamical Explanation|EtSeq 47 Dynamics 30 Dynamics@Dynamics|EtSeq 43 Eccentricity 250 Electric Current 33 Electricity|EtSeq 32 Electromagnetism|EtSeq 31 Ellipse 45, 120 Ellipse@Ellipse|EtSeq 130 Euclid 114 Exponential Series|EtSeq 211 Faraday 34 Fermat 218 Fluxions 219 Focus 120, 135 Force 30 Form, Algebraic@Form, Algebraic|EtSeq 66 Form, Algebraic 82, 117 Fourier's Theorem 191 Fractions|EtSeq 71 Franklin 32, 122 Function|EtSeq 144 Galileo@Galileo|EtSeq 42 Galileo 30, 122 Galvani 33 Generality in Mathematics 82 Geometrical Series|EtSeq 206 Geometry 36 Geometry@Geometry|EtSeq 236 Gilbert, Dr. 32 Graphs|EtSeq 148 Gravitation 29, 139 Halley 139 Harmonic Analysis 192 Harriot, Thomas 66 Herz 35 Hiero 38 Hipparchus 173 Hyperbola|EtSeq 131 Imaginary Numbers|EtSeq 87 Imaginary Quantities 109 Incommensurable Ratios|EtSeq 72 Infinitely Small Quantities|EtSeq 226 Integral Calculus 222 Interval|EtSeq 158 Kepler 45, 46, 137, 138 Kepler's Laws 138 Laputa 10 Laws of Motion@Laws of Motion|EtSeq 167 Laws of Motion 248 Leibniz 16 Leibniz@Leibniz|EtSeq 218 Leonardo da Vinci 42 Leverrier 220 Light 35 Limit of a Function|EtSeq 227 Limit of a Series|EtSeq 199 Limits 77 Locus@Locus|EtSeq 121 Locus 141 Macaulay 156 Malthus 138 Marcellus 37 Mass 30 Mechanics 46 Menaechmus 128, 129 Motion, First Law of 43 % ** Page 255 Neighbourhood|EtSeq 159 Newton 10, 16, 30, 34, 37, 38, 43, 46, 139 Newton@Newton|EtSeq 218 Non-Uniform Convergence|EtSeq 208 Normal Error, Curve of 214 Oersted@Öersted 34 Order|EtSeq 194 Order, Type of@Order, Type of|EtSeq 75 Order, Type of 196 Ordered Couples|EtSeq 93 Ordinate 95 Origin 95, 126 Pappus 135, 136 Parabola|EtSeq 131 Parallelogram Law@Parallelogram Law|EtSeq 51 Parallelogram Law 99, 126 Parameters 69, 117 Pencils 140 Period 170 Period@Period|EtSeq 189 Periodicity@Periodicity|EtSeq 164 Periodicity 188, 216 Pitt, William 194 Pizarro 122 Plutarch 37 Positive and Negative Numbers|EtSeq 83 Projective Geometry 139 Ptolemy 137, 173 Pythagoras 18 Quantity|EtSeq 245 Rate of Increase of Functions|EtSeq 220 Ratio|EtSeq 72 Real Numbers|EtSeq 73 Rectangle 57 Relations between Variables|EtSeq 18 Resonance 170, 171 Rosebery, Lord 194 Scale of a Map 178 Seidel 210 Series|EtSeq 74, 194 Shelley (quotation from) 217 Similarity@Similarity|EtSeq 177 Similarity 237 Sine|EtSeq 182 Specific Gravity 41 Squaring the Circle 187 Standard of Approximation|EtSeq 159, 201, 229 Steps@Steps|EtSeq 79 Steps 96 Stifel 85 Stokes, Sir George 210 Sum to Infinity|EtSeq 201 Surveys|EtSeq 176 Swift 10 Tangents 221, 222 Taylor's Theorem 156, 157 Time|EtSeq 166, 247 Transportation, Vector of|EtSeq 54 Triangle@Triangle|EtSeq 176 Triangle 237 Triangulation 177 Trigonometry|EtSeq 173 Uniform Convergence|EtSeq 208 Unknown, The 17, 23 % ** Page 256 Value of a Function 146 Variable, The 18, 24, 49, 82, 234, 239 Variable Function 147 Vectors@Vectors|EtSeq 51 Vectors 85, 96 Vertex 134 Volta 33 Wallace 220 Weierstrass 156, 226, 228 Zero@Zero|EtSeq 63 Zero 103 %[** TN: End of index] \fi % Printed by Hazell, Walton \& Viney, Ld., London and Aylesbury. %[** TN: Raw OCR output of book catalog follows] \iffalse The Home University Library of Modern Knowledge jj Comprehensive Series of New and Specially Written (Books EDITORS: PROF. GILBERT MURRAY, D.Litt., LL.D., F.B.A. HERBERT FISHER, M.A., F.B.A. PKOF. J. ARTHUR THOMSON, M.A. PROF. WM. T. BREWSTER, M.A. The Home University Library " Is without the slightest doubt the pioneer in supplying serious literature for a large section of the public who are interested in the liberal educa- tion of the State." The Daily Mail. " It is a thing very favourable to the real success of The Home University Library that its volumes do not merely attempt to feed ignorance with knowledge. The authors noticeably realise that the simple willing appetite of sharp-set ignorance is not specially common nowadays; what is far more common is a hunger which has been partially but injudiciously filled, with more or less serious results of indigestion. The food supplied is therefore frequently medicinal as well as nutritious; and this is certainly what the time requires. " Manchester Guardian. "Each volume represents a three-hours' traffic with the talking-power of a good brain, operating with the ease and interesting freedom of a specialist dealing with his own subject. ... A series which promises to perform a real social service." The Times. "We can think of no series now being issued which better deserves support." The Observer. We think if they were given as prizes in place of the more costly di: id prol series they might well take: ispensed on prize days, the pupils would rofit. If the publishers want a motto for the rubbish that is wont to be find more pleasure and series they might well take: ' Infinite riches in a little room.'" Irish Journal of Education, " The scheme was successful at the start because it met a want among earnest readers; but its wider and* sustained success, surely, comes from the fact that it has to a large extent created and certainly refined the taste by which it is appreciated." Daily Chronicle. " Here is the world's learning in little, and none too poor t< house-room!" Daily Telegraph. to give it ]/- net in cloth 256 Pages 2/6 net in leather History and (geography 3. THE FRENCH REVOLUTION By HILAIKE BELLOC, M.A. (With Maps.) "It is coloured with all the militancy of the author's temperament." Daily News. 4. HISTORY OF WAR AND PEACE By G. H. FERRIS. The Rt. Hon. JAMES BRYCE writes: " I have read it with much interest and pleasure, admiring the skill with which you have managed to compress so many facts and views into so small a volume." 8. POLAR EXPLORATION By Dr W. S. BRUCE, F.R.S.E., Leader of the "Scotia" Expedition. (With Maps.) "A very freshly written and interesting narrative." The Times. "A fascinating book." Portsmouth Times. 12. THE OPENING-UP OF AFRICA By Sir H. H. JOHNSTON. G.C.M.G., K.C.B., D.Sc., F.Z.S. (With Maps.) " The Home University Library is much enriched by this excellent work." Daily Mail. 13. MEDIAEVAL EUROPE By H. W. C. DAVIS, M.A. (With Maps.) "One more illustration of the fact that it takes a complete master of the subject to write briefly upon it." Manchester Guardian. 14. THE PAPACY \&* MODERN TIMES (1303-1870) By WILLIAM BARRY, D.D. "Dr Barry has a wide range of knowledge and an artist's power of selection." Manchester Guardian. 23. HISTORY OF OUR TIME, 1885-1911 By G. P. GOOCH, M.A. " Mr Gooch contrives to breathe vitality into his story, and to give us the flesh as well as the bones of recent happenings." Observer. 25. THE CIVILISATION OF CHINA By H. A. GILES, LL.D., Professor of Chinese in the University of Cambridge. "In all the mass of facts, Professor Giles never becomes dull. He is always ready with a ghost story or a street adventure for the reader's recreation." Spectator. 29. THE DA WN OF HISTORY By J.L.MYRES, M. A., F.S. A., Wykeham Professor of Ancient History, Oxford. "There is not a page in it that is not suggestive." Manchester Guardian. 33. THE HISTORY OF ENGLAND: A Study in Political Evolution. By Prof. A. F. POLLARD, M.A. With a Chronological Table. " It takes its place at once among the authoritative works on English history." Observer. 34. CANADA By A. G. BRADLEY. " Who knows Canada, better than Mr A. G. Bradley? " Daily Chronicle. "The volume makes an immediate appeal to the man who wants to know something vivid and true about Canada." Canadian Gazette. 37. PEOPLES 6* PROBLEMS OF INDIA By Sir T. W. HOLDERNESS, K.C.S.I., Secretary of the Revenue, Statistics, ! and Commerce Department of the India Office. "Just the book which news- paper readers require to-day, and a marvel of comprehensiveness." Pall \ Mall Gazette. 42. ROME By W. WARDE FOWLHR, M.A. " A masterly sketch of Roman character and of what it did for the world." The Spectator. "It has all the lucidity and charm of presentation we expect from this writer." Manchester Guardian. 48. THE AMERICAN CIVIL WAR By F. L. PAXSON, Professor of American History, Wisconsin University. (With Maps.) "A stirring study." The Guardian. 51. WARFARE IN BRITAIN By HILAIRE BELLOC, M.A. An account of how and where great battles of the past were fought on British soil, the roads and physical conditions determining the island's strategy, the castles, walled towns, etc. 55. MASTER MARINERS By J. R. SPEARS. The romance of the sea, the great voyages of discovery, naval battles, the heroism of the sailor, and the development of the ship, from ancient times to to-day. IN PREPARATION ANCIENT GREECE. By Prof. GILBERT MURRAY, D.Litt., LL.D., F.B.A ANCIENT EGYPT. By F. LL. GRIFFITH, M.A. THE ANCIENT EAST. By D. G. HOGARTH, M.A., F.B.A. A SHORT h'ISTOR YOFEUROPE. By HERBERT FISHER, M. A., F.B.A. PREHISTORIC BRITAIN. By ROBERT MUNRO, M.A., M.D., LL.D. THE BYZANTINE EMPIRE. By NORMAN H. BAVNES. THE REFORM A TION. By Principal LINDSAY, LL.D. NAPOLEON. By HERBERT FISHER, M.A., F.B.A. A SHORT HISTORY OF RUSSIA. By Prof. MILYOUKOV. MODERN TURKEY. By D. G. HOGARTH, M.A. FRANCE OF TO-DAY. By ALBERT THOMAS. GERMANY OF TO-DA Y. By CHARLES TOWER. THE NAVY AND SEA POWER. By DAVID HANNAY. HISTORY OF SCOTLAND. By R. S. RAIT, M.A. SOUTH AMERICA. By Prof. W. R. SHEPHERD. LONDON. By Sir LAURENCE GOMME, F.S.A. HISTORY AND LITERATURE OF SPAIN. By J. FITZMAURICE- KELLY, F.B.A., Litt.D. Literature and 2. SHAKESPEARE By JOHN MASEFIELD. " The book is a joy. We have had half-a-dozen more learned books on Shakespeare in the last few years, but not one so wise." Manchester Guardian. 27. ENGLISH LITERATURE: MODERN By G. H. MAIR, M.A. " Altogether a fresh and individual book." Olstrver. 35. LANDMARKS IN FRENCH LITERATURE By G. L. STRACHEY. " Mr Strachey is to be congratulated on his courage and success. It is difficult to imagine how a better account of French Literature could be given in 250 small pages than he has given here." The Times. 39- ARCHITECTURE By Prof. W. R. LETHABY. (Over forty Illustrations.) " Popular guide-books to architecture are, as a rule, not worth ranch. This volume is a welcome excep- tion." Building News. " Delightfully bright reading." Christian World. 43. ENGLISH LITERATURE: MEDIAEVAL By Prof. W. P. KER, M.A. "Prof. Ker has long proved his worth as one of the soundest scholars in English we have, and he is the very man to put an outline of English Mediaeval Literature before the uninstructed public. His knowledge and taste are unimpeachable, and his style is effective, simple, yet never dry." The Athemeum. 45. THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE By L. PEARSALL SMI-TH, M.A. "A wholly fascinating study of the different streams that went to the making of the great river of the English speech." Daily News. 52. GREAT WRITERS OF AMERICA By Prof. J. EKSKINE and Prof. W. P. TRENT. A popular sketch by two foremost authorities. IN PREPARATION ANCIENT ART AND RITUAL. By Miss JANE HARRISON, LL.D., D.Litt. GREEK LITERA TURE. By Prof. GILBERT MURRAY, D.Litt. LA TIN LITER A TURE. By Prof. J. S. PHILLIMORE. CHA UCER AND HIS TIME. By Miss G. E. HADOW. THE RENAISSANCE. By Mrs R. A. TAYLOR. ITALIAN A RTOF THE RENAISSANCE. By ROGER E. FRY, M.A. THE ART OF PAINTING. By Sir FREUERICK WEDMORE. DR JOHNSON AND HIS CIRCLE. By JOHN BAILEY, M.A. THE VIC IORIAN AGE. By G. K- CHESTERTON. ENGLISH COMPOSITION. By Prof. WM. T. BREWSTER. GREA T WRITERS OF RUSSIA. By C. T. HAGBERG WRIGHT, LL.D. THE LITERATURE OF GERMANY. By Prof. J. G. ROBERTSON, M.A., Ph.D. SCANDINAVIAN HISTORY AND LITERATURE. By T. C. SNOW, M.A. Science 7. MODERN GEOGRAPHY By Dr MARION NEWBIGIN. (Illustrated.) "Geography, again: what a dull, tedious study that was wont to be I . . . But Miss Marion Newbigin invests its dry bones with the flesh and blood of romantic interest, taking stock of geography as a fairy-book of science." Daily Telegraph. 9. THE EVOLUTION OF PLANTS By Dr D. H. SCOTT, M.A., F.R.S., late Hon. Keeper of the Jodrell Laboratory, Kew. (Fully illustrated.) "The information which the book provides is as trustworthy as first-band knowledge can make it. ... Dr Scott's candid and familiar style makes the difficult subject both fascinating and easy." Gardeners' Chronicle. 17. HEALTH AND DISEASE By W. LESLIE MACKKNZIE, M.D., Local Government Board, Edinburgh. "The science of public health administration has had no abler or more attractive exponent than Dr Mackenzie. He adds to a thorough grasp of the problems an illuminating style, and an arresting manner of treating a subject often dull and sometimes unsavoury." Economist. 1 8. INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS ' By A. N. WHITEHEAD, Sc.D., F.R.S. (With Diagrams.) "MrWhitehead has discharged with conspicuous success the task he is so exceptionally qualified I to undertake. For he is one of our great authorities upon the foundations of the science, and has the breadth of view which is so requisite in presenting to the reader its aims. His exposition is clear and striking." Westminster Gazette. 19. THE ANIMAL WORLD By Professor F. W. GAMBLE, D.Sc., F.R.S. With Introduction hy Sir Oliver Lodge. (Many Illustrations.) " A delightful and instructive epitome of animal (and vegetable) life. ... A most fascinating and suggestive survey." Morning Post. 20. EVOLUTION By Professor J. ARTHUR THOMSON and Professor PATRICK GEDDES. "A many-coloured and romantic panorama, opening up, like no other book we know, a rational vision of world-development." Belfast News-Letter. 22. CRIME AND INSANITY By Dr C. A. MERCIER, F.R.C.P., F.R.C.S., Author of "Text-Book of In- sanity," etc- " Furnishes much valuable information from one occupying the highest position among medico-legal psychologists." Asylum NCVJS. 28. PSYCHICAL RESEARCH and thus what he has to say on thought-reading, hypnotism, telepathy, crystal- vision, spiritualism, divinings, and so on, will be read with avidity." Dundee 31. ASTRONOMY By A. R. HINKS, M.A., Chief Assistant, Cambridge Observatory. "Original in thought, eclectic in substance, and critical in treatment. . . . No better little book is available." School World. 32. INTRODUCTION TO SCIENCE By J. ARTHUR THOMSON, M.A., Regius Professor of Natural History, Aberdeen University. " Professor Thomson's delightful literary style is well known; and here he discourses freshly and easily on the methods of science and its relations with philosophy, art, religion, and practical life." Aberdeen Journal, 36. By H. N. DICKSON, D.Sc. Oxon., M.A., F.R.S.E., President of the Royal Meteorological Society; Professor of Geography in University College, Reading. (With Diagrams.) "The author has succeeded in presenting in a very lucid and agreeable manner the causes of the movement of the atmosphere and of the more stable winds." Manchester Guardian. 41. ANTHROPOLOGY By R R. MARETT, M.A., Reade "An absolutely perfect handboo fascinating and human that it bea 44. THE PRINCIPLES OF PHYSIOLOGY By Prof. J. G. McKENDRiCK, M.D. " It is a delightful and wonderfully com- prehensive handling of a subject which, while of importance to all, does not readily lend itself to untechnical explanation. . . . The little book is more than a mere repository of knowledge; upon every page of it is stamped the impress of a creative imagination." Glasgow Herald. By R. R. MARETT, M.A., Reader in Social Anthropology in Oxford University. "An absolutely perfect handbook, so clear that a child could understand it, so fascinating and human that it beats fiction ' to a frazzle.' " Morning Leader. 46. MATTER AND ENERGY By F. SODDY, M.A., F.R.S. "A most fascinating and instructive account or the great facts of physical science, concerning which our knowledge, of later years, has made such wonderful progress." The Bookseller. 49. PSYCHOLOGY, THE STUDY OF BEHAVIOUR By Prof. W. McDouGALL, F.R.S., M.B. "A happy example of the non- technical handling of an unwieldy science, suggesting rather than dogmatising. It should whet appetites for deeper study." Christian World. 53. THE MAKING OF THE EARTH ByProf.J.W. GREGORY, F.R.S. (With 38 Maps and Figures.) The Professor of Geology at Glasgow describes the origin of the earth, the formation and changes of its surface and structure, its geological history, the first appearance of life, and its influence upon the globe. 57. THE HUMAN BODY By A. KEITH, M.D., LL,D., Conservator of Museum and Hunterian Pro- fessor, Royal College of Surgeons. (Illustrated.) The work of the dissecting- room is described, and among other subjects dealt with are: the development of the body; malformations and monstrosities; changes of youth and age; sex differences, are they increasing or decreasing? race characters; bodily features as indexes of mental character; degeneration and regeneration; and the genealogy and antiquity of man. 58. ELECTRICITY By GisBERT KAPP, D.Eng., M.I.E.E., M.I.C.E., Professor of Electrical Engineering in the University of Birmingham. (Illustrated.) Deals with frictional and contact electricity; potential; electrification by mechanical means; the electric current; the dynamics of electric currents; alternating currents; the distribution of electricity, etc. IN PREPARATION CHEMISTRY. Py Prof. R. MELDOLA, F.R.S. THE MINERAL WORLD. By Sir T. H. HOLLAND, K.C.I. E., D.Sc. PLANT LII-'E. By Prof. J. B. FARMER, F.R.S. NERVES. By Prof. D. FRASER HARRIS, M.D., D.Sc. A STUDY OF SEX. By Prof. J. A. THOMSON and Prof. PATRICK GEDDES. THE GROWTH OF EUROPE. By Prof. GRKNVILLE COLE. Philosophy and "Religion ig's :tate 15. MOHAMMEDANISM By Prof. D. S. MARGOLIOUTH, M.A., D.Litt. "This generous shilling': worth of wisdom. ... A delicate, humorous, and most responsible tractati by an illuminative professor." Daily Mail. 40. THE PROBLEMS OF PHILOSOPHY By the Hon. BERTRAND RUSSELL, F.R.S.: 'A book that the ' man in the street ' will recognise at once to be a boon. . . . Consistently lucid and non- technical throughout." Christian World. 47. BUDDHISM go. NONCONFORMITY: Its ORIGIN and PROGRESS I'.'- Principal W. B. SELBIE, M.A. "The historical part is brilliant in its :., clarity, and proportion, and in the later chapters on the present position .urns of Nonconformity Dr Selbie proves himself to be an ideal exponent of sound and moderate views." Christian World. 54. ETHICS By G. E. MOORE, M.A., Lecturer in Moral Science in Cambridge University. Discusses Utilitarianism, the Objectivity of Moral Judgments, the Test of Right and Wrong, Free Will, and Intrinsic Value. 56. THE MAKING OF THE NEW TESTAMENT By Prof. B. W. BACON, LL. LX, D.D. An authoritative summary of the results of modern critical research with regard to the origins of the New Testament, in " the formative period when conscious inspiration was still in its full glow rather than the period of collection into an official canon," showing the mingling of the two great currents of Christian thought " Pauline and 'Apostolic,' the Greek- Christian gospel about Jesus, and the Jewish-Christian gospel of Jesus, the gospel of the Spirit and the gospel of au thority." jo. MISSIONS: THEIR RISE and DEVELOPMENT By Mrs CREIGHTON. The beginning of modern missions after the Reforma- tion and their growth are traced, and an account is given of their present work, its extent and character. IN PREPARATION THE OLD TESTAMENT. By Prof. GEORGE MOORE, D.D., LL.D. BETWEEN THE OLD AND NEW TESTAMENTS. By R. H. CHARLES, D.D. COMPARATIVE RELIGION. By Prof. J. ESTLIN CARPENTER, D.Litt. A HISTOR Y of FREEDOM of THOUGHT. By Prof. J. B. BURY, LL.D. A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. By CLEMKNT WKBB, M.A. Social Science . PARLIAMENT Its History, Constitution, and Practice. By Sir COURTENAY P. ILBERT. K.C.B., K.C.S.I., Clerk of the House of Commons. "The best book on the history and practice of the House of Commons since Bagehot's 'Constitution.'" Yorkshire Post. . THE STOCK EXCHANGE By F. W. HIRST, Editor of " The Economist." " To an unfinancial mind must be a revelation. . . . The book is as clear, vigorous, and sane as Bagehot's ' Lom- bard Street,' than which there is no higher compliment." Morning Leader . IRISH NATIONALITY By Mrs J. R. GREEN. " As glowing as it is learned. No book could be more timely." Daily News. "A powerful study. . . . A magnificent demonstration of the deserved vitality of the Gaelic spirit." Freeman s Journal. 3. THE SOCIALIST MOVEMENT RAMSAY MACDONALD, M.T. "Admirably adapted for the purpose of exposition." The Times. "Mr MacDonald is a very lucid exponent. . . . The volume will be of great use in dispelling illusions about the tendencies of Socialism in this country." The Nation. i. CONSERVATISM Jy Lord HUGH CECIL, M.A., M.P. "One of those great little books which seldom appear more than once in a generation." Morning Post. 1 6. THE SCIENCE OF WEALTH By J. A. HOUSON, M.A. "Mr J. A. Hobson holds an unique position among living economists. . . . The text-book produced is altogether admirable. Original, reasonable, and illuminating." The Nation. 21. LIBERALISM By L. T. HOBHOUSE, M. A., Professor of Sociology in the University of London. "A book of rare quality. . . . We have nothing but praise for the rapid and masterly summaries of the arguments from first principles which form a large part of this book." Westminster Gazette. 24. THE EVOLUTION OF INDUSTRY ByD. H. MACGREGCR, M.A., Professor of Political Economy in the University of Leeds. "A volume so dispassionate in terms may be read with profit by all interested in the present state of unrest." Aberdeen Journal. 26. AGRICULTURE By Prof. W. SOMERVILLE, F.L.S. " It makes the results of laboratory work at the University accessible to the practical farmer." Athena-urn. 30. ELEMENTS OF ENGLISH LA W By W. M. GELDART, M.A., B.C.L., Vinerian Professor of English Law at Oxford. "Contains a very clear account of the elementary principles under- lying the rules of English law; and we can recommend it to all who wish to become acquainted with these elementary principles with a minimum of trouble." Scots Law Times. 38. THE SCHOOL An Introduction to the Study of Education. By J. J. FINDLAY, M.A., Ph.D., Professor of Education in Manchester University. <: An amazingly comprehensive volume. . . . It is a remarkable performance, distinguished in its crisp, striking phraseology as well as its inclusiveness of subject-matter." Morning Post. -59. ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY By S. J. CHAPMAN, M.A., Professor of Political Economy in Manchester University. A simple explanation, in the light of the latest economic thought, of the working of demand and supply; the nature of monopoly; money and international trade; the relation of wages, profit, interest, and rent; and the effects of labour combination prefaced by a short sketch of economic study since Adam Smith. IN PREPARATION THE CRIMINAL AND THE COMMUNITY. By Viscount ST. CYRES, M.A. COMMONSENSE IN LA W. By Prof. P. VINOGRADOFF, D.C.L. THE CIVIL SERVICE. By GRAHAM WALLAS, M.A. PRACTICAL IDEALISM. By MAURICE HEWLETT. NEWSPAPERS. By G. BINNEY DIBBLEE. ENGLISH VILLAGE LIFE. By E. N. BENNETT, M.A. CO -PARTNERSHIP At\D PROFIT-SHARING. By ANEURIN WILLIAMS, J.P. THE SOCIAL SETTLEMENT. By JANE ADDAMS and R. A. WOODS. GREA T INVENTIONS. By Prof. J. L. MYRES, M.A., F.S.A. TOWN PLANNING. By RAYMOND UNWIN. POLITICAL THOUGHT IN ENGLAND: From Bentham to J. S. Mill. By Prof. W. L. DAVIDSON. POLITICAL THOUGHT IN ENGLAKD: From Herbert Spencer to To-day. By ERNEST BARKER, M.A. London: WimTMS^AND~NORGATE And of all Bookshops and Bookstalls. %[** TN: End of catalog OCR text] \fi %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% GUTENBERG LICENSE %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \PGLicense \begin{PGtext} End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of An Introduction to Mathematics, by Alfred North Whitehead *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK AN INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS *** ***** This file should be named 41568-tex.tex or 41568-tex.zip ***** This and all associated files of various formats will be found in: http://www.gutenberg.org/4/1/5/6/41568/ Produced by Andrew D. Hwang. (This ebook was produced using OCR text generously provided by the University of California, Santa Barbara, through the Internet Archive.) Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions will be renamed. Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission. If you do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the rules is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research. They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks. Redistribution is subject to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution. *** START: FULL LICENSE *** THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project Gutenberg-tm License available with this file or online at www.gutenberg.org/license. Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8. 1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below. 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation" or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an individual work is in the public domain in the United States and you are located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg-tm License when you share it without charge with others. 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United States. 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg: 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase "Project Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed: This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is derived from the public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase "Project Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9. 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works posted with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work. 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm. 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project Gutenberg-tm License. 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary, compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1. 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying, performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9. 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works provided that - You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation." - You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg-tm works. - You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of receipt of the work. - You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works. 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael Hart, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below. 1.F. 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread public domain works in creating the Project Gutenberg-tm collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain "Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment. 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE. 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the problem. 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS', WITH NO OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE. 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions. 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause. Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from people in all walks of life. Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at www.gutenberg.org Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state's laws. The Foundation's principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr. S. Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered throughout numerous locations. Its business office is located at 809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up to date contact information can be found at the Foundation's web site and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact For additional contact information: Dr. Gregory B. Newby Chief Executive and Director gbnewby@pglaf.org Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS. The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who approach us with offers to donate. International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff. Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project Gutenberg-tm concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and distributed Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support. Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition. Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility: www.gutenberg.org This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm, including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks. \end{PGtext} % %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % % % % End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of An Introduction to Mathematics, by % Alfred North Whitehead % % % % *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK AN INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS *** % % % ***** This file should be named 41568-tex.tex or 41568-tex.zip ***** % % This and all associated files of various formats will be found in: % % http://www.gutenberg.org/4/1/5/6/41568/ % % % % %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % \end{document} ### @ControlwordReplace = ( ['\\AD', 'A.D.'], ['\\BC', 'B.C.'], ['\\cf', 'cf.'], ['\\Cf', 'Cf.'], ['\\eg', 'e.g.'], ['\\ie', 'i.e.'], ['\\viz', 'viz.'] ); @ControlwordArguments = ( ['\\Diagram', 1, 0, '', ''], ['\\Figure', 0, 0, '', '', 1, 0, '', ''], ['\\ToCLine', 1, 1, '', ' ', 1, 1, '', '', 1, 0, '', ''], ['\\BookMark', 1, 0, '', '', 1, 0, '', ''], ['\\First', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Chapter', 0, 0, '', '', 1, 1, 'Chapter ', '. ', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\ChapRef', 0, 0, '', '', 1, 1, 'Chapter ', ''], ['\\Appendix', 0, 0, '', '', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Note', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Fig', 0, 0, '', '', 1, 1, 'Fig. ', ''], ['\\FigNum', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Pagelabel', 1, 0, '', ''], ['\\Pageref', 0, 0, '', '', 1, 0, 'p. ', '00'], ['\\Eq', 0, 0, '', '', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Typo', 1, 0, '', '', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Add', 1, 1, '', ''], ['\\Chg', 1, 0, '', '', 1, 1, '', ''] ); $PageSeparator = qr/^\\PageSep/; $CustomClean = 'print "\\nCustom cleaning in progress..."; my $cline = 0; while ($cline <= $#file) { $file[$cline] =~ s/--------[^\n]*\n//; # strip page separators $cline++ } print "done\\n";'; ### This is pdfTeX, Version 3.1415926-1.40.10 (TeX Live 2009/Debian) (format=pdflatex 2012.9.24) 6 DEC 2012 09:22 entering extended mode %&-line parsing enabled. **41568-t.tex (./41568-t.tex LaTeX2e <2009/09/24> Babel and hyphenation patterns for english, usenglishmax, dumylang, noh yphenation, farsi, arabic, croatian, bulgarian, ukrainian, russian, czech, slov ak, danish, dutch, finnish, french, basque, ngerman, german, german-x-2009-06-1 9, ngerman-x-2009-06-19, ibycus, monogreek, greek, ancientgreek, hungarian, san skrit, italian, latin, latvian, lithuanian, mongolian2a, mongolian, bokmal, nyn orsk, romanian, irish, coptic, serbian, turkish, welsh, esperanto, uppersorbian , estonian, indonesian, interlingua, icelandic, kurmanji, slovenian, polish, po rtuguese, spanish, galician, catalan, swedish, ukenglish, pinyin, loaded. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/book.cls Document Class: book 2007/10/19 v1.4h Standard LaTeX document class (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/leqno.clo File: leqno.clo 1998/08/17 v1.1c Standard LaTeX option (left equation numbers) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/bk12.clo File: bk12.clo 2007/10/19 v1.4h Standard LaTeX file (size option) ) \c@part=\count79 \c@chapter=\count80 \c@section=\count81 \c@subsection=\count82 \c@subsubsection=\count83 \c@paragraph=\count84 \c@subparagraph=\count85 \c@figure=\count86 \c@table=\count87 \abovecaptionskip=\skip41 \belowcaptionskip=\skip42 \bibindent=\dimen102 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/inputenc.sty Package: inputenc 2008/03/30 v1.1d Input encoding file \inpenc@prehook=\toks14 \inpenc@posthook=\toks15 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/latin1.def File: latin1.def 2008/03/30 v1.1d Input encoding file )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/ifthen.sty Package: ifthen 2001/05/26 v1.1c Standard LaTeX ifthen package (DPC) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsmath.sty Package: amsmath 2000/07/18 v2.13 AMS math features \@mathmargin=\skip43 For additional information on amsmath, use the `?' option. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amstext.sty Package: amstext 2000/06/29 v2.01 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsgen.sty File: amsgen.sty 1999/11/30 v2.0 \@emptytoks=\toks16 \ex@=\dimen103 )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsbsy.sty Package: amsbsy 1999/11/29 v1.2d \pmbraise@=\dimen104 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsopn.sty Package: amsopn 1999/12/14 v2.01 operator names ) \inf@bad=\count88 LaTeX Info: Redefining \frac on input line 211. \uproot@=\count89 \leftroot@=\count90 LaTeX Info: Redefining \overline on input line 307. \classnum@=\count91 \DOTSCASE@=\count92 LaTeX Info: Redefining \ldots on input line 379. LaTeX Info: Redefining \dots on input line 382. LaTeX Info: Redefining \cdots on input line 467. \Mathstrutbox@=\box26 \strutbox@=\box27 \big@size=\dimen105 LaTeX Font Info: Redeclaring font encoding OML on input line 567. LaTeX Font Info: Redeclaring font encoding OMS on input line 568. \macc@depth=\count93 \c@MaxMatrixCols=\count94 \dotsspace@=\muskip10 \c@parentequation=\count95 \dspbrk@lvl=\count96 \tag@help=\toks17 \row@=\count97 \column@=\count98 \maxfields@=\count99 \andhelp@=\toks18 \eqnshift@=\dimen106 \alignsep@=\dimen107 \tagshift@=\dimen108 \tagwidth@=\dimen109 \totwidth@=\dimen110 \lineht@=\dimen111 \@envbody=\toks19 \multlinegap=\skip44 \multlinetaggap=\skip45 \mathdisplay@stack=\toks20 LaTeX Info: Redefining \[ on input line 2666. LaTeX Info: Redefining \] on input line 2667. ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/amssymb.sty Package: amssymb 2009/06/22 v3.00 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/amsfonts.sty Package: amsfonts 2009/06/22 v3.00 Basic AMSFonts support \symAMSa=\mathgroup4 \symAMSb=\mathgroup5 LaTeX Font Info: Overwriting math alphabet `\mathfrak' in version `bold' (Font) U/euf/m/n --> U/euf/b/n on input line 96. )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/alltt.sty Package: alltt 1997/06/16 v2.0g defines alltt environment ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/tools/indentfirst.sty Package: indentfirst 1995/11/23 v1.03 Indent first paragraph (DPC) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/footmisc/footmisc.sty Package: footmisc 2009/09/15 v5.5a a miscellany of footnote facilities \FN@temptoken=\toks21 \footnotemargin=\dimen112 \c@pp@next@reset=\count100 \c@@fnserial=\count101 Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style bringhurst on input line 855. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style chicago on input line 863. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style wiley on input line 872. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style lamport-robust on input line 883. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style lamport* on input line 903. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style lamport*-robust on input line 924 . ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/tools/multicol.sty Package: multicol 2008/12/05 v1.6h multicolumn formatting (FMi) \c@tracingmulticols=\count102 \mult@box=\box28 \multicol@leftmargin=\dimen113 \c@unbalance=\count103 \c@collectmore=\count104 \doublecol@number=\count105 \multicoltolerance=\count106 \multicolpretolerance=\count107 \full@width=\dimen114 \page@free=\dimen115 \premulticols=\dimen116 \postmulticols=\dimen117 \multicolsep=\skip46 \multicolbaselineskip=\skip47 \partial@page=\box29 \last@line=\box30 \mult@rightbox=\box31 \mult@grightbox=\box32 \mult@gfirstbox=\box33 \mult@firstbox=\box34 \@tempa=\box35 \@tempa=\box36 \@tempa=\box37 \@tempa=\box38 \@tempa=\box39 \@tempa=\box40 \@tempa=\box41 \@tempa=\box42 \@tempa=\box43 \@tempa=\box44 \@tempa=\box45 \@tempa=\box46 \@tempa=\box47 \@tempa=\box48 \@tempa=\box49 \@tempa=\box50 \@tempa=\box51 \c@columnbadness=\count108 \c@finalcolumnbadness=\count109 \last@try=\dimen118 \multicolovershoot=\dimen119 \multicolundershoot=\dimen120 \mult@nat@firstbox=\box52 \colbreak@box=\box53 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/makeidx.sty Package: makeidx 2000/03/29 v1.0m Standard LaTeX package ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/graphicx.sty Package: graphicx 1999/02/16 v1.0f Enhanced LaTeX Graphics (DPC,SPQR) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/keyval.sty Package: keyval 1999/03/16 v1.13 key=value parser (DPC) \KV@toks@=\toks22 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/graphics.sty Package: graphics 2009/02/05 v1.0o Standard LaTeX Graphics (DPC,SPQR) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/trig.sty Package: trig 1999/03/16 v1.09 sin cos tan (DPC) ) (/etc/texmf/tex/latex/config/graphics.cfg File: graphics.cfg 2009/08/28 v1.8 graphics configuration of TeX Live ) Package graphics Info: Driver file: pdftex.def on input line 91. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/pdftex-def/pdftex.def File: pdftex.def 2009/08/25 v0.04m Graphics/color for pdfTeX \Gread@gobject=\count110 )) \Gin@req@height=\dimen121 \Gin@req@width=\dimen122 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/caption/caption.sty Package: caption 2009/10/09 v3.1k Customizing captions (AR) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/caption/caption3.sty Package: caption3 2009/10/09 v3.1k caption3 kernel (AR) \captionmargin=\dimen123 \captionmargin@=\dimen124 \captionwidth=\dimen125 \caption@indent=\dimen126 \caption@parindent=\dimen127 \caption@hangindent=\dimen128 ) \c@ContinuedFloat=\count111 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/tools/calc.sty Package: calc 2007/08/22 v4.3 Infix arithmetic (KKT,FJ) \calc@Acount=\count112 \calc@Bcount=\count113 \calc@Adimen=\dimen129 \calc@Bdimen=\dimen130 \calc@Askip=\skip48 \calc@Bskip=\skip49 LaTeX Info: Redefining \setlength on input line 76. LaTeX Info: Redefining \addtolength on input line 77. \calc@Ccount=\count114 \calc@Cskip=\skip50 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/fancyhdr/fancyhdr.sty \fancy@headwidth=\skip51 \f@ncyO@elh=\skip52 \f@ncyO@erh=\skip53 \f@ncyO@olh=\skip54 \f@ncyO@orh=\skip55 \f@ncyO@elf=\skip56 \f@ncyO@erf=\skip57 \f@ncyO@olf=\skip58 \f@ncyO@orf=\skip59 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/geometry/geometry.sty Package: geometry 2008/12/21 v4.2 Page Geometry (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/ifpdf.sty Package: ifpdf 2009/04/10 v2.0 Provides the ifpdf switch (HO) Package ifpdf Info: pdfTeX in pdf mode detected. ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/ifvtex.sty Package: ifvtex 2008/11/04 v1.4 Switches for detecting VTeX and its modes (HO) Package ifvtex Info: VTeX not detected. ) \Gm@cnth=\count115 \Gm@cntv=\count116 \c@Gm@tempcnt=\count117 \Gm@bindingoffset=\dimen131 \Gm@wd@mp=\dimen132 \Gm@odd@mp=\dimen133 \Gm@even@mp=\dimen134 \Gm@dimlist=\toks23 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/xelatex/xetexconfig/geometry.cfg)) (/usr/share/te xmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/hyperref.sty Package: hyperref 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hypertext links for LaTeX (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/ifxetex/ifxetex.sty Package: ifxetex 2009/01/23 v0.5 Provides ifxetex conditional ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/oberdiek/hycolor.sty Package: hycolor 2009/10/02 v1.5 Code for color options of hyperref/bookmark (H O) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/oberdiek/xcolor-patch.sty Package: xcolor-patch 2009/10/02 xcolor patch )) \@linkdim=\dimen135 \Hy@linkcounter=\count118 \Hy@pagecounter=\count119 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/pd1enc.def File: pd1enc.def 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hyperref: PDFDocEncoding definition (HO) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/etexcmds.sty Package: etexcmds 2007/12/12 v1.2 Prefix for e-TeX command names (HO) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/infwarerr.sty Package: infwarerr 2007/09/09 v1.2 Providing info/warning/message (HO) ) Package etexcmds Info: Could not find \expanded. (etexcmds) That can mean that you are not using pdfTeX 1.50 or (etexcmds) that some package has redefined \expanded. (etexcmds) In the latter case, load this package earlier. ) (/etc/texmf/tex/latex/config/hyperref.cfg File: hyperref.cfg 2002/06/06 v1.2 hyperref configuration of TeXLive ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/oberdiek/kvoptions.sty Package: kvoptions 2009/08/13 v3.4 Keyval support for LaTeX options (HO) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/kvsetkeys.sty Package: kvsetkeys 2009/07/30 v1.5 Key value parser with default handler suppor t (HO) )) Package hyperref Info: Option `hyperfootnotes' set `false' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Option `bookmarks' set `true' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Option `linktocpage' set `false' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Option `pdfdisplaydoctitle' set `true' on input line 286 4. Package hyperref Info: Option `pdfpagelabels' set `true' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Option `bookmarksopen' set `true' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Option `colorlinks' set `true' on input line 2864. Package hyperref Info: Hyper figures OFF on input line 2975. Package hyperref Info: Link nesting OFF on input line 2980. Package hyperref Info: Hyper index ON on input line 2983. Package hyperref Info: Plain pages OFF on input line 2990. Package hyperref Info: Backreferencing OFF on input line 2995. Implicit mode ON; LaTeX internals redefined Package hyperref Info: Bookmarks ON on input line 3191. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/ltxmisc/url.sty \Urlmuskip=\muskip11 Package: url 2006/04/12 ver 3.3 Verb mode for urls, etc. ) LaTeX Info: Redefining \url on input line 3428. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/bitset.sty Package: bitset 2007/09/28 v1.0 Data type bit set (HO) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/intcalc.sty Package: intcalc 2007/09/27 v1.1 Expandable integer calculations (HO) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/bigintcalc.sty Package: bigintcalc 2007/11/11 v1.1 Expandable big integer calculations (HO) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/pdftexcmds.sty Package: pdftexcmds 2009/09/23 v0.6 LuaTeX support for pdfTeX utility functions (HO) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/ifluatex.sty Package: ifluatex 2009/04/17 v1.2 Provides the ifluatex switch (HO) Package ifluatex Info: LuaTeX not detected. ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/ltxcmds.sty Package: ltxcmds 2009/08/05 v1.0 Some LaTeX kernel commands for general use (HO ) ) Package pdftexcmds Info: LuaTeX not detected. Package pdftexcmds Info: \pdf@primitive is available. Package pdftexcmds Info: \pdf@ifprimitive is available. ))) \Fld@menulength=\count120 \Field@Width=\dimen136 \Fld@charsize=\dimen137 \Field@toks=\toks24 Package hyperref Info: Hyper figures OFF on input line 4377. Package hyperref Info: Link nesting OFF on input line 4382. Package hyperref Info: Hyper index ON on input line 4385. Package hyperref Info: backreferencing OFF on input line 4392. Package hyperref Info: Link coloring ON on input line 4395. Package hyperref Info: Link coloring with OCG OFF on input line 4402. Package hyperref Info: PDF/A mode OFF on input line 4407. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/oberdiek/atbegshi.sty Package: atbegshi 2008/07/31 v1.9 At begin shipout hook (HO) ) \Hy@abspage=\count121 \c@Item=\count122 ) *hyperref using driver hpdftex* (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/hpdftex.def File: hpdftex.def 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hyperref driver for pdfTeX \Fld@listcount=\count123 ) \TmpLen=\skip60 \@indexfile=\write3 \openout3 = `41568-t.idx'. Writing index file 41568-t.idx (./41568-t.aux) \openout1 = `41568-t.aux'. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OML/cmm/m/it on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for T1/cmr/m/n on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OT1/cmr/m/n on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OMS/cmsy/m/n on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OMX/cmex/m/n on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for U/cmr/m/n on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for PD1/pdf/m/n on input line 494. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 494. (/usr/share/texmf/tex/context/base/supp-pdf.mkii [Loading MPS to PDF converter (version 2006.09.02).] \scratchcounter=\count124 \scratchdimen=\dimen138 \scratchbox=\box54 \nofMPsegments=\count125 \nofMParguments=\count126 \everyMPshowfont=\toks25 \MPscratchCnt=\count127 \MPscratchDim=\dimen139 \MPnumerator=\count128 \everyMPtoPDFconversion=\toks26 ) Package caption Info: Begin \AtBeginDocument code. Package caption Info: hyperref package is loaded. Package caption Info: End \AtBeginDocument code. *geometry auto-detecting driver* *geometry detected driver: pdftex* -------------------- Geometry parameters paper: class default landscape: -- twocolumn: -- twoside: true asymmetric: -- h-parts: 9.03375pt, 307.14749pt, 9.03375pt v-parts: 1.26749pt, 466.58623pt, 1.90128pt hmarginratio: 1:1 vmarginratio: 2:3 lines: -- heightrounded: -- bindingoffset: 0.0pt truedimen: -- includehead: true includefoot: true includemp: -- driver: pdftex -------------------- Page layout dimensions and switches \paperwidth 325.215pt \paperheight 469.75499pt \textwidth 307.14749pt \textheight 404.71243pt \oddsidemargin -63.23624pt \evensidemargin -63.23624pt \topmargin -71.0025pt \headheight 12.0pt \headsep 19.8738pt \footskip 30.0pt \marginparwidth 98.0pt \marginparsep 7.0pt \columnsep 10.0pt \skip\footins 10.8pt plus 4.0pt minus 2.0pt \hoffset 0.0pt \voffset 0.0pt \mag 1000 \@twosidetrue \@mparswitchtrue (1in=72.27pt, 1cm=28.45pt) ----------------------- (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/color.sty Package: color 2005/11/14 v1.0j Standard LaTeX Color (DPC) (/etc/texmf/tex/latex/config/color.cfg File: color.cfg 2007/01/18 v1.5 color configuration of teTeX/TeXLive ) Package color Info: Driver file: pdftex.def on input line 130. ) Package hyperref Info: Link coloring ON on input line 494. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/nameref.sty Package: nameref 2007/05/29 v2.31 Cross-referencing by name of section (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/oberdiek/refcount.sty Package: refcount 2008/08/11 v3.1 Data extraction from references (HO) ) \c@section@level=\count129 ) LaTeX Info: Redefining \ref on input line 494. LaTeX Info: Redefining \pageref on input line 494. (./41568-t.out) (./41568-t.out) \@outlinefile=\write4 \openout4 = `41568-t.out'. \AtBeginShipoutBox=\box55 Overfull \hbox (20.10721pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 501--501 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 Project Gutenberg's An Introduction to Mathematics, by Alfred North Whitehead[] [] Overfull \hbox (15.85715pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 519--519 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK AN INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS ***[] [] LaTeX Font Info: Try loading font information for U+msa on input line 521. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/umsa.fd File: umsa.fd 2009/06/22 v3.00 AMS symbols A ) LaTeX Font Info: Try loading font information for U+msb on input line 521. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/umsb.fd File: umsb.fd 2009/06/22 v3.00 AMS symbols B ) [1 {/var/lib/texmf/fonts/map/pdftex/updmap/pdftex.map}] [2] [1 ] [2 ] [1 ] [2] [3] [4] [5] [6] [7 ] [8] [9] [10] <./images/fig1.pdf, id=236, 299.1175pt x 166.6225pt> File: ./images/fig1.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [11 <./images/fig1.pdf>] <./images/fig2.pdf, id=255, 31 1.1625pt x 166.6225pt> File: ./images/fig2.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [12] [13 <./images/fig2.pdf>] [14] [15 ] [16] [17] [18] [19] [20] [21] LaTeX Font Info: Try loading font information for OMS+cmr on input line 1529 . (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/omscmr.fd File: omscmr.fd 1999/05/25 v2.5h Standard LaTeX font definitions ) LaTeX Font Info: Font shape `OMS/cmr/m/n' in size <8> not available (Font) Font shape `OMS/cmsy/m/n' tried instead on input line 1529. LaTeX Font Info: Font shape `OMS/cmr/m/n' in size <7> not available (Font) Font shape `OMS/cmsy/m/n' tried instead on input line 1531. [22] [23] [24] [25] <./images/fig3.pdf, id=327, 324.21124pt x 150.5625pt> File: ./images/fig3.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [26] [27 <./images/fig3.pdf>] [28] [29 ] [30] <./images/fig4.pdf, id=362, 150.5625pt x 128.48pt> File: ./images/fig4.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) <./images/fig5.pdf, id=364, 150.5625pt x 126.4725pt> File: ./images/fig5.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [31] [32 <./images/fig4.pdf> <./images/fig5.pdf>] [33] [34] [35] [36] <./images/fig6.pdf, id=405, 162.6075pt x 136.51pt> File: ./images/fig6.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [37 <./images/fig6.pdf>] [38] [39] <./images/fig7.pdf, id=428, 230.8625pt x 161.60374pt> File: ./images/fig7.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [40] [41 <./images/fig7.pdf>] [42] [43 ] [44] [45] [46] [47] [48] [49] [50] [51] [52] [53] [54 ] <./images/pg76.pdf, id=515, 302.12875pt x 36.135pt> File: ./images/pg76.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [55] [56 <./images/pg76.pdf>] [57] [58] [59] [60] [61] [62] [63] <./images/pg86.pdf, id=567, 324.21124pt x 32.12pt> File: ./images/pg86.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [64 <./images/pg86.pdf>] [65] [66] [67 ] [68] [69] [70] <./images/fig8.pdf, id=617, 341.275pt x 230.8625pt> File: ./images/fig8.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [71 <./images/fig8.pdf>] <./images/fig9.pdf, id=633, 33 8.26375pt x 239.89626pt> File: ./images/fig9.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [72] [73 <./images/fig9.pdf>] [74] [75] [76] <./images/ fig10.pdf, id=672, 341.275pt x 236.885pt> File: ./images/fig10.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [77 <./images/fig10.pdf>] [78] [79] [80 ] [81] [82] [83] <./images/fig11.pdf, id=720, 319.1925pt x 166.6225pt> File: ./images/fig11.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [84] [85 <./images/fig11.pdf>] <./images/fig12.pdf, id =742, 250.9375pt x 199.74625pt> File: ./images/fig12.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [86 <./images/fig12.pdf>] [87] [88] [89] <./images/fig 13.pdf, id=768, 319.1925pt x 274.02374pt> File: ./images/fig13.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [90 ] [91 <./images/fig13.pdf>] [92] [93] [94] [95] [96] [97] [98] <./images/fig14. pdf, id=819, 319.1925pt x 279.0425pt> File: ./images/fig14.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [99] [100 <./images/fig14.pdf>] [101] [102] [103 ] [104] <./images/fig15.pdf, id=864, 337.26pt x 357.335pt> File: ./images/fig15.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [105] <./images/fig16.pdf, id=870, 290.08376pt x 156.5 85pt> File: ./images/fig16.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) <./images/fig17.pdf, id=871, 199.74625pt x 186.6975pt> File: ./images/fig17.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) <./images/fig18.pdf, id=875, 351.3125pt x 257.96375pt> File: ./images/fig18.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [106 <./images/fig15.pdf>] [107 <./images/fig16.pdf>] [108 <./images/fig17.pdf>] [109 <./images/fig18.pdf>] [110] [111] [112] <./imag es/fig19.pdf, id=959, 178.6675pt x 131.49126pt> File: ./images/fig19.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [113] [114 <./images/fig19.pdf>] [115] [116] [117] [11 8 ] [119] [120] <./images/fig20.pdf, id=1007, 275.0275pt x 120.45pt> File: ./images/fig20.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [121 <./images/fig20.pdf>] [122] [123] <./images/fig21 .pdf, id=1039, 305.14pt x 230.8625pt> File: ./images/fig21.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [124] [125 <./images/fig21.pdf>] [126] [127] [128] [12 9] [130] [131] [132] [133] [134 ] [135] [136] [137] [138] [139] [140] [141 ] <./images/fig22.pdf, id=1139, 163.61125pt x 135.50626pt> File: ./images/fig22.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) <./images/fig23.pdf, id=1140, 145.54375pt x 92.345pt> File: ./images/fig23.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [142] [143 <./images/fig22.pdf>] <./images/fig24.pdf, id=1156, 348.30125pt x 143.53625pt> File: ./images/fig24.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) <./images/fig25.pdf, id=1157, 202.7575pt x 126.4725pt> File: ./images/fig25.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) <./images/fig26.pdf, id=1160, 309.155pt x 265.99374pt> File: ./images/fig26.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [144 <./images/fig23.pdf>] [145 <./images/fig24.pdf>] [146 <./images/fig25.pdf>] [147] [148 <./images/fig26.pdf>] [149] <./images/fig 27.pdf, id=1226, 351.3125pt x 291.0875pt> File: ./images/fig27.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [150] [151] [152 <./images/fig27.pdf>] [153] [154] <./ images/fig28.pdf, id=1267, 298.11375pt x 69.25874pt> File: ./images/fig28.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [155 <./images/fig28.pdf>] [156] [157] [158] [159 ] [160] [161] [162] [163] [164] [165] [166] Overfull \hbox (0.85368pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 6806--6814 []\OT1/cmr/m/n/12 It is tempt-ing to sup-pose that the con-di-tion for $\OML/cm m/m/it/12 u[]$\OT1/cmr/m/n/12 , $\OML/cmm/m/it/12 u[]$\OT1/cmr/m/n/12 , ..., [] [167] [168] [169] [170] [171] [172] Underfull \hbox (badness 1565) in paragraph at lines 7074--7079 []\OT1/cmr/m/n/12 The crit-i-cal points, where non-uniform con-ver-gence [] [173] [174] <./images/fig29.pdf, id=1377, 341.275pt x 183.68625pt> File: ./images/fig29.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [175] <./images/fig30.pdf, id=1385, 305.14pt x 129.483 75pt> File: ./images/fig30.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [176 <./images/fig29.pdf>] <./images/fig31.pdf, id=140 0, 293.095pt x 149.55875pt> File: ./images/fig31.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [177 <./images/fig30.pdf>] [178 <./images/fig31.pdf>] [179 ] [180] [181] <./images/fig32.pdf, id=1442, 309.155pt x 166.6225pt> File: ./images/fig32.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [182 <./images/fig32.pdf>] [183] [184] [185] [186] [18 7] [188] [189] [190] [191] [192] [193] <./images/fig33.pdf, id=1514, 339.2675pt x 114.4275pt> File: ./images/fig33.pdf Graphic file (type pdf) [194 ] [195 <./images/fig33.pdf>] [196] [197] [198] [199] [200] [201] [202 ] [203] [204] [205] [206] [207 ] [208] [209 ] [210] (./41568-t.ind [211] [212 ] [213] [214] [215]) Overfull \hbox (7.35703pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 9490--9490 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK AN INTRODUCTION TO MA THEMATICS ***[] [] [1 ] Overfull \hbox (3.10696pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 9560--9560 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation"[] [] Overfull \hbox (3.10696pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 9565--9565 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prev ent you from[] [] [2] Overfull \hbox (3.10696pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 9570--9570 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of[] [] [3] Overfull \hbox (3.10696pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 9633--9633 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/8 posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gut enberg.org),[] [] [4] [5] [6] [7] [8] [9] (./41568-t.aux) *File List* book.cls 2007/10/19 v1.4h Standard LaTeX document class leqno.clo 1998/08/17 v1.1c Standard LaTeX option (left equation numbers) bk12.clo 2007/10/19 v1.4h Standard LaTeX file (size option) inputenc.sty 2008/03/30 v1.1d Input encoding file latin1.def 2008/03/30 v1.1d Input encoding file ifthen.sty 2001/05/26 v1.1c Standard LaTeX ifthen package (DPC) amsmath.sty 2000/07/18 v2.13 AMS math features amstext.sty 2000/06/29 v2.01 amsgen.sty 1999/11/30 v2.0 amsbsy.sty 1999/11/29 v1.2d amsopn.sty 1999/12/14 v2.01 operator names amssymb.sty 2009/06/22 v3.00 amsfonts.sty 2009/06/22 v3.00 Basic AMSFonts support alltt.sty 1997/06/16 v2.0g defines alltt environment indentfirst.sty 1995/11/23 v1.03 Indent first paragraph (DPC) footmisc.sty 2009/09/15 v5.5a a miscellany of footnote facilities multicol.sty 2008/12/05 v1.6h multicolumn formatting (FMi) makeidx.sty 2000/03/29 v1.0m Standard LaTeX package graphicx.sty 1999/02/16 v1.0f Enhanced LaTeX Graphics (DPC,SPQR) keyval.sty 1999/03/16 v1.13 key=value parser (DPC) graphics.sty 2009/02/05 v1.0o Standard LaTeX Graphics (DPC,SPQR) trig.sty 1999/03/16 v1.09 sin cos tan (DPC) graphics.cfg 2009/08/28 v1.8 graphics configuration of TeX Live pdftex.def 2009/08/25 v0.04m Graphics/color for pdfTeX caption.sty 2009/10/09 v3.1k Customizing captions (AR) caption3.sty 2009/10/09 v3.1k caption3 kernel (AR) calc.sty 2007/08/22 v4.3 Infix arithmetic (KKT,FJ) fancyhdr.sty geometry.sty 2008/12/21 v4.2 Page Geometry ifpdf.sty 2009/04/10 v2.0 Provides the ifpdf switch (HO) ifvtex.sty 2008/11/04 v1.4 Switches for detecting VTeX and its modes (HO) geometry.cfg hyperref.sty 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hypertext links for LaTeX ifxetex.sty 2009/01/23 v0.5 Provides ifxetex conditional hycolor.sty 2009/10/02 v1.5 Code for color options of hyperref/bookmark (HO ) xcolor-patch.sty 2009/10/02 xcolor patch pd1enc.def 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hyperref: PDFDocEncoding definition (HO) etexcmds.sty 2007/12/12 v1.2 Prefix for e-TeX command names (HO) infwarerr.sty 2007/09/09 v1.2 Providing info/warning/message (HO) hyperref.cfg 2002/06/06 v1.2 hyperref configuration of TeXLive kvoptions.sty 2009/08/13 v3.4 Keyval support for LaTeX options (HO) kvsetkeys.sty 2009/07/30 v1.5 Key value parser with default handler support (HO) url.sty 2006/04/12 ver 3.3 Verb mode for urls, etc. bitset.sty 2007/09/28 v1.0 Data type bit set (HO) intcalc.sty 2007/09/27 v1.1 Expandable integer calculations (HO) bigintcalc.sty 2007/11/11 v1.1 Expandable big integer calculations (HO) pdftexcmds.sty 2009/09/23 v0.6 LuaTeX support for pdfTeX utility functions ( HO) ifluatex.sty 2009/04/17 v1.2 Provides the ifluatex switch (HO) ltxcmds.sty 2009/08/05 v1.0 Some LaTeX kernel commands for general use (HO) atbegshi.sty 2008/07/31 v1.9 At begin shipout hook (HO) hpdftex.def 2009/10/09 v6.79a Hyperref driver for pdfTeX supp-pdf.mkii color.sty 2005/11/14 v1.0j Standard LaTeX Color (DPC) color.cfg 2007/01/18 v1.5 color configuration of teTeX/TeXLive nameref.sty 2007/05/29 v2.31 Cross-referencing by name of section refcount.sty 2008/08/11 v3.1 Data extraction from references (HO) 41568-t.out 41568-t.out umsa.fd 2009/06/22 v3.00 AMS symbols A umsb.fd 2009/06/22 v3.00 AMS symbols B ./images/fig1.pdf ./images/fig2.pdf omscmr.fd 1999/05/25 v2.5h Standard LaTeX font definitions ./images/fig3.pdf ./images/fig4.pdf ./images/fig5.pdf ./images/fig6.pdf ./images/fig7.pdf ./images/pg76.pdf ./images/pg86.pdf ./images/fig8.pdf ./images/fig9.pdf ./images/fig10.pdf ./images/fig11.pdf ./images/fig12.pdf ./images/fig13.pdf ./images/fig14.pdf ./images/fig15.pdf ./images/fig16.pdf ./images/fig17.pdf ./images/fig18.pdf ./images/fig19.pdf ./images/fig20.pdf ./images/fig21.pdf ./images/fig22.pdf ./images/fig23.pdf ./images/fig24.pdf ./images/fig25.pdf ./images/fig26.pdf ./images/fig27.pdf ./images/fig28.pdf ./images/fig29.pdf ./images/fig30.pdf ./images/fig31.pdf ./images/fig32.pdf ./images/fig33.pdf 41568-t.ind *********** ) Here is how much of TeX's memory you used: 7739 strings out of 493848 110834 string characters out of 1152823 197518 words of memory out of 3000000 10386 multiletter control sequences out of 15000+50000 16794 words of font info for 64 fonts, out of 3000000 for 9000 714 hyphenation exceptions out of 8191 37i,13n,44p,298b,544s stack positions out of 5000i,500n,10000p,200000b,50000s Output written on 41568-t.pdf (228 pages, 1021150 bytes). PDF statistics: 2077 PDF objects out of 2487 (max. 8388607) 462 named destinations out of 1000 (max. 500000) 392 words of extra memory for PDF output out of 10000 (max. 10000000)